Philosophical Method Part 1: Concepts, Necessary And Sufficient Conditions And Model Epistemology

  • Uploaded by: Jesse Butler
  • 0
  • 0
  • May 2020
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Philosophical Method Part 1: Concepts, Necessary And Sufficient Conditions And Model Epistemology as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 1,433
  • Pages: 4
Concepts (copyright © 2009 Jesse Butler)

In this course, like any other course in philosophy, certain assumptions must be made in order for our study to begin. Our most fundamental assumption, that I'll try to made as explicit as I can in these notes so that we may understand that which most fundamentally guides our study, has to do with what the text book calls 'concepts'. What is a concept? It's unclear that there are concepts (as certain entities which exist in the same way physical objects exist). But what is clear, or at least what we must assume is clear if a beginning is to be made in Introduction to Philosophy, is that talk of “conceptual mastery” makes sense. So what is conceptual mastery? The short answer can be given by an example: An individual (Andy) has conceptual mastery with regard to the predicate 'is a dog' if Andy can successfully sort individuals into dogs and non-dogs. Of course, if Andy is conceptually competent with respect to dogs, then Andy can tell actual dogs he's presented with from actual things he's presented with that are not dogs. But, if Andy is conceptually competent with dogs, he can ALSO tell dogs apart from non-dogs in "counter-factual" or merely imagined situations. That is, if we describe to Andy an imaginary or fictional situation in enough detail, then Andy can tell if the imaginary situation we've described includes a dog. So to have conceptual mastery is to be disposed to have at at least some knowledge about the world and to be able tocommunicate about imaginary situations with others who have similar conceptual mastery. Conceptual mastery is something which guarantees that our thoughts and words have a sort of "appropriate" or "accurate" relation to the world we think and speak about. Necessary and Sufficient Conditions Necessary Conditions What are the conditions under which the concept of being a dog correctly applies to something? First off, a thing must be alive or must have been alive at one time for it to be considered a dog. Second, the thing must be a mammal. Third, the thing must have (or have had or been disposed to have had under the right conditions) four legs and a tail. Forth, the thing must not be disposed to perspire, but rather it's tongue must be disposed to evaporate water on a hot day. Each of these conditions is necessary for the concept of being a dog. In other words, if the concept DOG applies to something, that thing must (1) be living or have died, (2) must be or have been a mammal, (3) must have or have had four legs and a tail, etc. We might symbolize the situation in the following way: DOG  being alive or having died

DOG  being a mammal DOG  having four legs + a tail If being alive or having died is a necessary condition for the concept of DOG to apply, then something's being a dog implies that that thing is alive or has died. The arrow "" stands for "implies". Sufficient Conditions Now what is sufficient for the concept of being a dog to apply to something? In other words, what conditions are those that, if they are satisfied by object Z, are such as to guarantee that Z is a dog? One proposal is that each of the necessary conditions (1), (2), (3), ... for being a dog are TOGETHER a sufficient condition. So if something (1) is alive AND (2) it is a mammal AND (3) it has four legs and a tail AND ... We’d write: (1) AND (2) AND (3) AND ...  DOG if we could fill out (1), (2) , (3), ... well enough we could get a sufficient condition for being a dog. A way to learn and keep clear necessary and sufficient conditions is remember the following way of symbolizing the situation in which having the property P1 and property P2 imply the having of property P3. (We use the shorthand "&" for "and"). P1 & P2  P3 From this we know that having both P1 and P2 is a SUFFICIENT condition for something's having P3, and that being P3 is a NECESSARY condition on something which has both P1 and P2. (Things seem fairly straightforward (simple even) when we're talking about the concept of being a dog. Things become much more interesting and difficult when we're concerned with the concept of having a mind, the concept of having free will, the concept of being the same person over time, the concept of the good and the concept of God.) The Socratic Method We're interested in determining the necessary and sufficient conditions for applications of certain concepts. Unfortunately, things won't be as simple as there they were when we were searching for the necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of the concept DOG. We try to discover the necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of concepts using the Socratic method. In the Socratic method, participants in a discussion engage in

a dialogue (the procedure is sometimes called a "Socratic dialogue") of a partricular sort. First, someone poses a question such as "What is virtue?" or "What is goodness?" or "When does an individual have a mind?" Someone else, proposes an answer, such as "A thing has a mind when the parts of that thing are of the right sort to perform the function that a human brain performs." The first person, says "Well, in that case, if all the starts in the sky just happened to be arranged in such a way that the structure, structural organization and function relative to this structural organization were exactly analogous to the arrangement of neurons in a human brain, would this configuration of stars in the sky have a mind as the person with the brain has a mind?" The conversational partner then says, "Well, probably not ..." And has to think a bit more about how to narrow or otherwise modify the claims he has made about the necessary and sufficient conditions for a thing to have a mind. With this sort of question and answer, the participants in a Socratic dialogue work toward finding the necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of certain concept together. Two things are necessary for the Socratic method to succeed. First, the participants must work together in a friendly and helpful way: they must work toward the answer as a team in the agonistic spirit. Scorn and derision have no place in a Socratic dialogue; harsh words only make the answer harder to find for everybody involved. Second, each participant must struggle to see problems with any set of necessary and sufficient conditions that are proposed for the application of a certain concept. Most importantly, one must examine one's own proposals as critically as (perhaps even more so) one examines others. It's only by "trying on" a set of necessary and sufficient conditions that we can see why the proposal falls short of what we desire for it. Conceivability and Possibility The claim that it's possible for a concept to apply if and only if it's coherently conceivable that the concept applies is a touchy, hotly contested philosophical position, but we must assume it as our starting point. We'll say that something is logically possible (it's existence leads to no contradiction) if and only if it is coherently imaginable (that is, if and only if, it is imaginable by someone who has conceptual mastery of all the relevant concepts involved in the imagining of this thing). The important thing to notice now is that the set of logically possible things is much greater than the set of physically possible things. For example, it's logically possible that the speed of light was faster than it actually is. We can see this because we can coherently imagine a universe in which light travels twice as fast as it actually does. It's physically impossible for light to travel any faster than it actually does. The actual laws of nature constrain the speed of light. In Socratic dialogues, we're concerned with the notion of logical possibility (given by coherent conceivability) rather than any narrower sort of possibility (such as physical or biological possibility) because we wish to find the necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of concepts. These conditions will span the entire realm of logical

possibility because our tools for investigating the necessary and sufficient conditions for application of concepts are those of coherent conceivability and argument (which depends, most generally upon the broad notion).

Related Documents


More Documents from ""