Truth And Warranted Assertion

  • June 2020
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Truth And Warranted Assertion as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 3,961
  • Pages: 9
TRUTH AND WARRANTED ASSERTION

Clayton Littlejohn INTRODUCTION

There is a strange lacuna in the literature on warranted assertion. A commonly held view is that the knowledge norm governs assertion: KW:

You must not assert p unless you know that p is true.

KW entails that there are no false, warranted assertions. No matter how good the speaker’s evidence is for believing p, if p is false but the speaker asserts that it is true, the speaker should not have asserted that p is the case. At best, the speaker could be excused for her breach. If warrant is anything like justification, just as excuses do not provide justifications, warranted assertions are not merely excusable assertions. The literature doesn’t seem to contain any direct argument for the thesis that assertion is governed by the norm of truth: TW:

You must not assert p unless p is true.

Perhaps this is because it is thought that we do not need an argument for TW. We have arguments for KW and KW cannot govern assertion unless TW does. One problem is that the arguments offered in support of KW do not seem to support anything stronger than reasonable or justified belief accounts of assertion.1 Another problem is that it seems plausible to maintain that if the speaker is epistemically permitted to believe p, the speaker cannot then be obliged to refrain from asserting that p is the case. If there were an obligation to refrain from asserting p, there is an undefeated reason that demands that the speaker not assert that p is the case but it seems that there would be no such reason that had any bearing on whether the speaker should believe. That seems rather odd. Why wouldn’t reasons to refrain from asserting do double duty as reasons to refrain from believing? If we know that there are no such reasons to refrain from believing, why doesn’t 1

We might grant that anyone who asserts that some lottery proposition is true asserted something she (epistemically) oughtn’t have asserted. We might grant that you shouldn’t assert Moorean absurdities such as ‘Custer died at Little Big Horn but I believe he didn’t’ are true, but you might think that since speakers know (or could easily know with little reflection) that they do not know these propositions to be true and it seems you might not be justified in believing what you know (or could easily know with little reflection) that you do not know, we do not need anything stronger than a rule that enjoins us to refrain from asserting what we do not believe with justification or what we cannot reasonably take ourselves to know.

that show that there’s a clear path to believing? The problem is that if justified belief justifies assertion, neither TW nor KW governs assertion because there can be false, justified beliefs. The main rival to the knowledge account of assertion takes something along these lines to be the norm that governs assertion: RBKW: You must not assert p unless you can reasonably take yourself to know p.2 It seems we have little reason to prefer KW to RBKW and some reason to think that KW demands too much. What I’d like to do is offer an argument against RBKW and similar views that do not require truth for warranted assertion. This will not give us an argument for KW, but it will give us some reason to think that the truth about warranted assertion is that it is more like knowledge than critics of the knowledge account seem to think. 1. WARRANT ENTAILS TRUTH Let’s say that S’s assertion that p is the case is warranted iff S is epistemically permitted to assert that p is the case. I think that if someone is permitted to Φ, there may be reasons for them not to Φ but there cannot be undefeated reasons for them not to Φ. And, I think that if there are no undefeated reasons for them not to Φ, it cannot be that they are obliged not to Φ. In the absence of reasons not to Φ, Φ-ing is permitted. In other words, Φ-ing is warranted. To argue that truth is necessary for warranted assertion, I’ll argue (predictably) that there’s always reason to refrain from asserting false propositions and there’s no reason that defeats this reason that could warrant the false assertion. My target in this paper is RBKW and similar views. They either have to say that there is no norm that governs assertion that gives us reason to refrain from asserting the false or they have to identify additional norms that give us reasons that defeat the reasons generated by the truth norm, TW. An important part of my argument is case driven. Here is a case: Cook. Peacock just moved into the apartment next to Plum’s. To welcome her to the building, Plum cooked her dinner. She did 2

RBKW seems to enjoy a distinctive advantage over KW. According to KW, you oughtn’t assert p if you don’t know p for purely Gettierish reasons. RBKW seems to have no such implication and it seems that someone who reasonably believes themselves to know p but fails to know p for purely Gettierish reasons is not obliged to refrain from asserting p.

not realize that the mushrooms she used in making her dinner were poisonous. (So far as this is possible, imagine that she is not culpable or blameworthy for her ignorance. She used a field guide for distinguishing safe from unsafe mushrooms, but it contained a few errors.) Plum has on hand the stuff to give people who eat poisoned mushrooms, but only enough for one person. It just so happens that her other neighbor, Mustard, is suffering from food poisoning because he at a can of bad peaches. (So far as this is possible, imagine that he is non-culpably ignorant). Plum’s stuff could help Mustard just as well as it could help Peacock. It’s good stuff. Now, Mustard and Peacock are equally sick and Plum can help only one. It seems intuitively: (*)

Plum has a more stringent duty to assist Peacock than Mustard.

She did poison Peacock, after all. The intuition elicited by this example seems to disconfirm the internalist idea that the conditions or properties that determine whether someone acts permissibly or with justification are limited to the properties that are internal to the subject or the subject’s perspective: DI:

Necessarily, if S and S’ are mental duplicates from the cradle to the time at which they Φ, S is permitted to Φ iff S’ is permitted to Φ.

In some nearby possible world where Plum’s mental duplicate gives her neighbor a dish with mushrooms that are not poisonous, I think we can easily imagine that she does nothing wrongful since Plum’s mental duplicate is no more negligent than Plum and she does not harm her neighbor with her gift. If (*) is correct, I don’t think that Plum’s duty to Peacock could be some mere duty of beneficence. After all, Mustard’s needs are as great as Peacock’s and Plum’s stuff could help him just as well as that stuff could help Peacock. My hypothesis is this. The reason that (*) is true is that Plum’s duty is to right some past wrongful act of hers by assisting Peacock. The problem with DI is that it can’t allow for the possibility that there was wrongdoing in the past because the internal conditions common to Plum and Plum’s mental duplicates do not ensure that there was some good

reason for Plum not to act in the way that she did. The reason that she ought to assist Peacock first is that she poisoned Peacock when she served her the mushrooms and the problem with DI is that this fact is inaccessible to Plum. Someone could say that while (*) is true, it doesn’t follow that this is a duty to address some prior wrong she’s committed. That is to say, it is no mere duty of beneficence, but it is not a reparative duty if such duties are understood as responses to past wrongs that the agent has committed. To give this kind of duty a name, we can speak of reparative* duties. It is similar to a reparative duty insofar as they are duties one can be under only if the agent brought about some bad state of affairs, but they are like the duty of beneficence insofar as they can arise without any prior wrongdoing on the agent’s part. Why can’t we say that the difference in stringency is due to the fact that there is a prima facie duty to assist both Peacock and Mustard, but a stronger duty to Peacock because there is the additional reparative* duty that gives her a pro tanto reason to assist Peacock? That way, we can accommodate intuition without giving up internalism about justification. The problem with this is with this idea of reparative* duties. If this is merely a reparative* duty, then we would have to say that this is a case in which Plum did not act against any pro tanto reason to refrain from giving Peacock the poisoned dish. (Otherwise, we would have to say that this was a reparative duty.) But, then it seems quite odd to think that Plum could have such a duty because it would have to combine two features. First, it would have to give Plum a reason to act that a similarly situated but causally idle agent would not have.3 Second, it would have to be a reason for Plum to act over and above a reason associated with a mere duty of beneficence to address some bad state of affairs when she could know full well that she never had any reason not to bring about in the first place. On this account, there would be a resultant moral difference between Plum and Green’s duties (i.e., both would have reasons of beneficence to assist either subject but Plum would have the additional reason to discharge a reparative* duty) that alters the range of permissible options available to them that arose in virtue of a causal difference that was not coupled with any normative difference. That sounds really strange. Better, I think, to say that the reason that this causal difference between Plum and Green makes a normative difference. It was in virtue of a causal relation between Plum and the bad state of affairs that she acted against a pro tanto 3

Otherwise, we would say that the reparative* duty was really a mere duty of beneficence. It would be the very duty that, say, Green would have if he had just the same amount of stuff to give to someone who has been poisoned as Plum has.

reason. She now has the knowledge necessary to see that her actions were wrongful. This is why Peacock has a stronger claim on Plum’s assistance than Mustard does. But, this is why there is a reparative duty that Plum ought to discharge, not a reparative* duty. Suppose DI is false. Suppose Plum didn’t know what to make Peacock so she asked White. White said that she should use the mushrooms growing in the garden to make her a salad. Plum followed his advice. Should White have said this? Consider: (AP) If an advisee oughtn’t Φ and there is no reason to give insincere advice, the advisor oughtn’t assert that the advisee ought to Φ. If AP is false, the reasons that speak against Φ-ing do not constitute reasons to refrain from encouraging someone to act against those reasons by advising them to do so. That seems to go against everything we know about giving sincere advice. Now we have our argument against RBKW: (1)

Circumstances can arise in which there is a decisive case against Φ-ing where the reasons not to Φ are grounded in considerations the agent is non-culpably ignorant of (e.g., Cook).

(2)

In such cases, an advisor might also be reasonably ignorant of the reasons that constitute a decisive case against Φ-ing.

(C)

Circumstances can arise in which there is a decisive case against to be made against the advisor’s assertion that the advisee ought to Φ where the considerations that constitute this case are considerations the advisor is nonculpably ignorant of.

Since you cannot have warrant to assert when there decisive reason to refrain from asserting, Cook is a counterexample to RBKW. 2. THE OBJECTION RBKW is a theory of epistemically warranted assertion. In Cook, there is a decisive practical case to be made against asserting. Cook isn’t a counterexample to RBKW.

Here’s my response. Suppose Cook shows: (1)

If Plum morally oughtn’t Φ in C and Plum is in C, White morally oughtn’t assert that Plum ought to Φ.

The objector assumes (1) doesn’t entail: (2)

If Plum morally oughtn’t Φ in C and Plum is in C, White epistemically oughtn’t assert that Plum ought to Φ.

If we deny that (1) entails (2), we have to accept: (3)

Although Plum morally oughtn’t Φ in C, White is epistemically permitted to assert that Plum ought to Φ in C.

(3) is false, so the entailment holds. Suppose White considers the matter and judges that he should Ψ (i.e., assert that Plum ought to Φ in C). White is thereby motivated to Ψ accordingly. We call White on it. We might say to White that if he wasn’t epistemically permitted to judge that he should Ψ, he could not defend his Ψ-ing as being epistemically permissible.4 White agrees but says that his judgment that he should Ψ was epistemically permissible. He then points out that if the judgment that he should Ψ is epistemically permissible then his Ψ-ing would be epistemically permissible. This follows from two further assumptions: (AI)

If S intends to Ψ and it’s not the case that she should not so intend, it’s not the case that S oughtn’t Ψ.

(IB)

If S believes that she should Ψ and it’s not the case that she should not so believe, it’s not the case that S oughtn’t intend to Ψ in accordance with that belief.

The problem is that we can say that if he judged that he should Ψ and was permitted to Ψ in only some non-moral sense, then he would not be defending his Ψ-ing. If he insisted that in light of his epistemic permission to judge that he should Ψ there was an additional moral permission to Ψ because the moral reasons that determined the permissibility of his Ψ-ing were the relevant epistemic reasons that determined whether he was epistemically permitted to Ψ, that would be a defense. This defense assumes that (3) is false.5 4

This means that this would not be a situation in which Ψ-ing would be epistemically permissible, so (3) would be false because its second conjunct would be false. 5 (3) is true only if the reasons that constitute a decisive non-epistemic case against Ψ-ing do not

The problem with (3) can be brought out as follows. Suppose White had no mistaken beliefs. It seems natural for someone in White’s position to think that the same reasons in light of which the advisee oughtn’t Φ are the reasons in light of which he oughtn’t epistemically and morally assert that the advisee ought to Φ or ought to feel free to Φ. In other words, it seems to the subject in the good case that the epistemic and non-epistemic reasons demand the same thing from him. Now, consider a second subject in a bad case, a case where the subject is mistaken about the external surroundings. It might be that as a result of this factual ignorance the subject doesn’t know what reasons bear on whether her advisee ought to Φ. It doesn’t seem to follow from the fact that the subject suffers from this factual ignorance that there would be a change in the relations between the reasons that bear on whether the agent ought to Φ and whether she should advise the agent to Φ. This is just intuitive. Note that if these relations varied between the good case and bad, the subject’s knowledge of the relations between the reasons would not be apriori.6 I take it, however, that the subject’s knowledge of the relations between the reasons that bear on whether the advisee ought to Φ and whether she ought to advise the advisee to Φ is apriori and thus independent from the empirical knowledge that subjects have in the good case but lack in the bad. To sum up, in the good case, the subject knows that the reasons not to Φ constitute a decisive case against asserting that the subject ought to Φ. This relation between reasons is invariant and doesn’t change depending upon facts that vary between the good case and the bad. Thus, the reasons not to Φ for practical reasons constitute a decisive epistemic case against asserting that the subject ought to Φ. Thus, (3) is false.7 Focusing on the ‘downstream effects’ of

thereby create a decisive epistemic case against Ψ-ing as well. 6 That is because it would depend, inter alia, upon knowledge of those contingent matters of fact that differ in the good and bad cases. 7 To deny this, it seems that you would have to deny at least one of the following: (PRO) Reasons that count in favor of beliefs or intentions thereby count in favor of the intentions and actions these beliefs and intentions rationalize. (CON) Reasons that count against actions or intentions count against the intentions and beliefs that purport to rationalize them. (DEON) If S’s Φ-ing is permitted, there is no unmatched or undefeated reason not to Φ. These all look good to me. If they are true, we can argue from the ‘downstream effects’ of an assertion about what should be done to conclusions about whether that assertion is warranted. When we do this, we find that TW is among the norms that governs assertion.

an assertion, we can see that asserting that an advisee ought to do what oughtn’t be done, we can see that the reasons the advisor advises acting against give reason not to advise. These reasons are, inter alia, reasons to refrain from asserting generated by a norm that governs assertion that enjoins us not to assert the false. 3.

JUSTIFICATION IS SUFFICIENT FOR WARRANT

You have warrant to assert that p is true if you justifiably believe p (JSW).8 If assertion is governed by (TW), it seems that the following principle is true: (ENM) If S were to assert that p is true and cause S’ an epistemic harm by convincing S’ to believe p, S should not assert that p is true.9 If someone’s assertion convinces you that p is true when in fact p is false, you have suffered an epistemic harm. So, if (ENM) is true, you should not assert false propositions. I know you are curious as to whether p is true and assert: (1)

8

There is sufficient justification for believing p.

If you don’t have sufficient warrant to assert p, you epistemically shouldn’t assert that p is the case. If you shouldn’t assert p, there is an undefeated reason for you to refrain from asserting that p is the case. If it is nevertheless the case that your belief is justified, that is either because the reason to refrain from asserting is not a reason to refrain from believing or because there is an overriding reason to believe that does not provide a justification for asserting. The suggestion that the (alleged) reason to refrain from asserting on epistemic grounds would not constitute a reason to refrain from believing is obscure, as is the suggestion that the (alleged) overriding reason to believe could not provide an overriding reason to assert what there is (allegedly) a reason not to assert. So, it seems plausible to maintain that belief and assertion are held to common rather than divergent epistemic standards. 9 The principle needs to be restricted. If I assert that p is true and that pragmatically implies that q is true, it isn’t clear that I’ve violated an epistemic norm by asserting that p is true if q is false. I might have violated a conversational norm, but that’s a different matter. If I say ‘Mustard hasn’t been drunk in days’ and you infer mistakenly that he had been drunk a time or two in the past, I don’t want to say that I’ve violated (ENM) if Mustard has never been drunk. Here’s the fix. If I say that there’s sufficient reason to believe p, it seems someone cannot both believe my assertion and suspend judgment as to whether p, so let’s say that (ENM) enjoins us to refrain from causing those epistemic harms that cannot be avoided on the condition that the subject accepts our assertion. Those harms that can be avoided if only some conversational implicature had been cancelled might be conversationally inappropriate but not epistemically inappropriate. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.

As there cannot be sufficient justification for believing p unless it is permissible for you to believe p, it follows from (1) that: (2)

It is permissible for you to believe p.

When p is false, it seems that my assertion that (1) is true or that (2) is true could cause the very same epistemic harm as my assertion that p is true. Thus, if you accept (ENM), it follows that you cannot have sufficient warrant to assert (1) or (2) if p is false. It seems knowledge is sufficient for warranted assertion (KSW).10 Combine the (ENM) with (KSW) and you get the result that you cannot know that (1) or (2) is true if p is not true. If p is not true, (ENM) says that you cannot have sufficient warrant to assert that (1) or (2) is true. It follows from this and (KSW) that you do not know that (1) or (2) is true. Why can’t you know that (1) or (2) if ~p? Is it that your belief in (1) and (2) cannot be justified unless p is true? Then, there are no false, justified beliefs.11 Is it that your belief in (1) and (2) cannot be true unless p is true? If so, there are no false, justified beliefs. Is it that you cannot believe (1) or (2) unless p? I doubt it. I also doubt that belief in (1) or (2) is always Gettiered. Thus, it seems that the only two plausible explanations as to why it follows from the fact that p is false that someone cannot have sufficient warrant to assert (1) or (2) assume that it cannot be that someone justifiably believes p when ~p.

10

Remember that the notion of propriety that figures in an account of warranted assertion is epistemic and it is hard to see what more than knowledge that p is true could be needed for properly saying that p is true. If knowledge, justified belief, or truth suffices for warranted assertion, knowledge suffices for warranted assertion. If knowledge is not enough for warranted assertion, situations should arise where we can properly say something like, ‘He knew that p, but he was in no position to claim that p was true’. I doubt such situations would arise with any frequency. 11 We often have sufficient warrant to ascribe justification as we do not infrequently ascribe knowledge to one another. If the fact that p is false does not prevent someone from justifiably believing p on its own, why would it prevent the speaker from having sufficient justification to believe that there is sufficient justification for the first-order belief that p is true?

Related Documents

Ce Mc Assertion
November 2019 14
Truth
May 2020 35
Praise And Worship - Truth
October 2019 17
Truth
May 2020 30