Public Enforcement Of Law

  • August 2019
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Public Enforcement Of Law as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 16,791
  • Pages: 38
8000 PUBLIC ENFORCEMENT OF LAW A. Mitchell Polinsky Stanford University

Steven Shavell Harvard University © Copyright 1999 A. Mitchell Polinsky and Steven Shavell

Abstract This chapter discusses the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use of public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to sanction violators of legal rules. We first present the basic elements of the theory, focusing on the probability of imposition of sanctions, the magnitude and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. We then examine a variety of extensions of the central theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing fines, mistake, marginal deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses and incapacitation. JEL classification: K14, K42 Keywords: Law Enforcement, Crime, Deterrence

1. Introduction In this chapter we consider the theory of the public enforcement of law - the use of public agents (inspectors, tax auditors, police, prosecutors) to detect and to sanction violators of legal rules. Of course, private parties also play an important role in law enforcement, by providing information to public authorities and also by initiating their own legal actions (notably, tort suits), but to maintain focus we restrict attention here to public enforcement activity. (On private enforcement, see generally Landes and Posner, 1987, and Shavell, 1987c; and on private versus public enforcement, see Becker and Stigler, 1974; Landes and Posner, 1975, and Polinsky, 1980a.) In Sections 2 through 4, we present the basic elements of the theory of public enforcement of law. Our concern is with the probability of imposition of sanctions, the magnitude and form of sanctions, and the rule of liability. In Sections 5 through 16 we then examine a variety of extensions of the central theory, including accidental harms, costs of imposing fines, mistake, marginal deterrence, settlement, self-reporting, repeat offenses and incapacitation.

307

308

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Before proceeding, we note that economically-oriented analysis of public law enforcement dates from the eighteenth century contributions of Montesquieu (1748), Beccaria (1770), and, especially, Bentham (1789), whose analysis of deterrence was sophisticated and expansive. But, curiously, after Bentham (1789), the subject of enforcement lay essentially dormant in economic scholarship until the late 1960s, when Becker (1968) published a highly influential article, which has led to a voluminous literature.

2. The Basic Framework An individual (or a firm) chooses whether to commit an act that for simplicity is assumed to cause harm with certainty (see Section 5 on uncertain harm). If he commits the act, he obtains some gain, and also faces the risk of being caught, found liable and sanctioned. The rule of liability could be either strict under which the individual is definitely sanctioned - or fault-based - under which he is sanctioned only if his behavior fell below a fault standard. The sanction that he suffers could be a monetary fine, a prison term, or a combination of the two. Whether an individual commits a harmful act is determined by an expected utility calculation. He will commit the act if that would raise his expected utility, taking into account the gain he would derive and the probability, form, and level of sanction that he would then face. We will usually first examine the assumption that individuals are risk neutral with respect to sanctions, that is, that they treat an uncertain sanction as equivalent to its expected value; but we will also consider alternative assumptions. Social welfare generally is presumed to equal the sum of individuals’ expected utilities. An individual’s expected utility depends on whether he commits a harmful act, on whether he is a victim of someone else’s harmful act, and on his tax payment, which will reflect the costs of law enforcement, less any fine revenue collected. If individuals are risk neutral, social welfare can be expressed simply as the gains individuals obtain from committing their acts, less the harms caused, and less the costs of law enforcement. (The assumption that individuals’ gains always are credited in social welfare could be relaxed without affecting most of our conclusions. The principal difference that altering the assumption would make is that more acts would be treated as socially undesirable and that optimal sanctions and enforcement effort would increase.) We assume, as is conventional, that fines are socially costless to employ because they are mere transfers of money (but in Section 6 we consider fines that are costly to impose), whereas imprisonment involves positive social costs because of the expense associated with the operation of prisons and the disutility due to imprisonment (which is not naturally balanced by gains to others).

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

309

The enforcement authority’s problem is to maximize social welfare by choosing enforcement expenditures or, equivalently, a probability of detection, the level of sanctions and their form (a fine, prison term, or combination), and the rule of liability (strict or fault-based).

3. Optimal Enforcement Given the Probability of Detection We consider here optimal enforcement given the assumption that the probability of detection is fixed (the probability will be treated as a policy instrument in the next section). Thus, we ask about the optimal form and level of sanctions under strict and fault-based liability, and about how the two liability rules compare. Strict Liability Assume initially that fines are the form of sanction and that individuals are risk neutral. Then the optimal fine is the harm h divided by the probability of detection p, that is, h/p; for then the expected fine equals the harm (observe that p(h/p) = h). If, for example, the harm is $1,000 and the probability of detection is 25 percent, the optimal fine is $4,000, and the expected fine is $1,000. This fine is optimal because, when the expected fine equals the harm, an individual will commit a harmful act if, but only if, the gain he would derive from it exceeds the harm he would cause. Essentially this basic and fundamental formula was noted by Bentham (1789, p. 173) and it has been observed by many others since. If individuals are risk averse with regard to fines, one would expect the optimal fine to be lower than in the risk-neutral case for two reasons. First, this reduces the bearing of risk by individuals who commit the harmful act. Second, because risk-averse individuals are more easily deterred than risk-neutral individuals, the fine does not need to be as high as before to achieve any desired degree of deterrence. (However, for subtle reasons that we will not address here, the optimal fine could, in principle, be higher when individuals are risk averse.) Next assume that imprisonment is the form of sanction, with social costs incurred in imposing sanctions. In this case, there is not a simple formula for the optimal imprisonment term (see Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The optimal term could be such that there is either underdeterrence or overdeterrence, compared to socially ideal behavior. On one hand, a relatively low imprisonment term, implying underdeterrence, might be socially desirable because it means that imprisonment costs are reduced for those individuals who commit harmful acts. On the other hand, a relatively high term, implying overdeterrence, might be socially desirable because it means that imprisonment costs are reduced due to fewer individuals committing harmful acts, even if

310

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

some of these deterred individuals would have obtained gains exceeding the harm. (The possible optimality of overdeterrence strikes us as more theoretical than real, however.) Now consider the combined use of fines and imprisonment. Here, the main point is that fines should be employed to the maximum extent feasible before resort is made to imprisonment. In other words, it is not optimal to impose a positive imprisonment term unless the fine is maximal. (The maximal fine might be interpreted as the wealth of an individual.) The rationale for this conclusion is that fines are socially costless to impose, whereas imprisonment is socially costly, so deterrence should be achieved through the cheaper form of sanction first. This point is noted by Bentham (1789, p. 183) and Becker (1968, p. 193); see also Polinsky and Shavell (1984). To amplify, suppose that the fine f is less than the maximal fine fm and that a positive prison term t is employed. Raise f toward fm and lower t so as to keep the disutility of the combined sanctions constant. Then deterrence and the amount of harm will not change, but the cost of imposing the imprisonment sanction will fall, raising social welfare. Hence, it must be optimal for the fine to be maximal before imprisonment is used. (Observe that this argument holds regardless of individuals’ attitudes toward risk of either fines or imprisonment.) Fault-Based Liability Assume again that fines are the form of liability. Then the same formula for the fine that we said was optimal under strict liability - namely, h/p, the harm divided by the probability of detection - will lead to compliance with the fault standard (assuming that the fault standard is optimally selected). For example, suppose that the harm is $1,000, and that an individual would be found at fault if he failed to take a precaution costing less than $1,000 that could have prevented the harm. Furthermore, suppose such a precaution exists that costs $700. If the probability of detection is 25 percent, then a fine of $4,000 for being at fault would induce the individual to take a precaution costing less than $1,000; in particular, he would prefer to spend $700 on the precaution and escape liability than not to take the precaution and bear an expected fine of $1,000. Observe that the optimal fine of $4,000 in the preceding example is not unique. Any higher fine also would induce compliance with the fault standard, as would some lower fines (as long as the expected value of the fine exceeds $700, or whatever is the expense of the precaution that costs less than $1,000). Note that higher fines do not lead to a problem of overdeterrence because parties can escape fines by complying with the fault standard. (However, if mistakes occur in the legal process, they might be induced to spend excessively on precautions; see Section 8 below). If individuals are risk averse, they are more easily deterred than if they are risk neutral, so the fine does not need to be as high to induce compliance with the fault standard. Moreover, assuming that compliance occurs, no one actually

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

311

is sanctioned because no one is found at fault (assuming, as we do here, that there are no mistakes). Thus, fault-based liability has the attractive feature that it can accomplish desired deterrence of harm-creating conduct without imposing risk on risk-averse individuals (Shavell, 1982). Next, consider imprisonment as the sanction; see Shavell (1987a). Here, for essentially the reasons given in the case of fines, any sanction above a threshold level will ensure compliance with the fault standard, and the minimum sanction necessary to induce compliance is higher the lower is the probability of detection. Also (Shavell, 1985), fault-based liability again can accomplish deterrence without the actual imposition of sanctions, which would be socially costly. Finally, consider the joint use of fines and imprisonment. In this case, it does not matter what the combination of sanctions is, provided that the sanctions achieve compliance with the fault standard. In particular, it is not advantageous for society to employ maximal fines before resorting to imprisonment because compliance means that sanctions are never imposed. Comparison of Liability Rules Because sanctions are not imposed under fault-based liability (in the absence of mistakes), this form of liability has an advantage over strict liability when the sanction is the fine and individuals are risk-averse, or when the sanction is imprisonment. However, fault-based liability is more difficult to administer. Namely, to apply fault-based liability, the enforcement authority must have more information than under strict liability: it must be able to calculate optimal behavior to determine the fault standard and it must ascertain whether the fault standard was met. Under strict liability, the authority need only ascertain harm. (Moreover, for reasons we discuss in Section 7 below, strict liability encourages better decisions by injurers regarding their level of participation in harm-creating activities.)

4. Optimal Enforcement Including the Probability of Detection We now consider the optimal system of enforcement when expenditures on enforcement, and hence the probability of detection, are allowed to vary. Consideration of this issue originated with Becker (1968); the early writers on enforcement (including Bentham, 1789) did not examine the issue of the choice of enforcement effort. Strict Liability Assume first that the sanction is a fine and that individuals are risk neutral. Then the optimal level of the fine is maximal and the optimal probability is low

312

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

(in a sense to be described). The basic explanation for this conclusion is that if the fine were not maximal, society could save enforcement costs by simultaneously raising the fine and lowering the probability without affecting the level of deterrence. Suppose, for example, that the fine initially is $4,000 and that the probability of detection is 25 percent. Now raise the fine to $10,000, presuming that the maximal fine is at least this high, and lower the probability of detection to 10 percent. Then the expected fine remains equal to $1,000, so that deterrence is maintained, but expenditures on enforcement are significantly reduced, implying that social welfare rises. This process can be continued, and social welfare augmented, as long as the fine is below the maximal level fm. Becker (1968) suggested this result (although much of his analysis implicitly presumes that the fine is not maximal); Carr-Hill and Stern (1979, pp. 280-309) and Polinsky and Shavell (1979) note it explicitly. The optimal probability is low in that there is some underdeterrence; that is, the optimal p is such that the expected fine pfm is less than the harm h (Polinsky and Shavell, 1984). The reason for this result is that if pfm equals h, behavior will be ideal, meaning that the individuals who are just deterred obtain gains essentially equal to the harm. These are the individuals who would be led to commit the harmful act if p were lowered slightly. That in turn must be socially beneficial because these individuals cause no net social losses (because their gains essentially equal the harm), but reducing p saves enforcement costs. How much pfm should be lowered below h depends on the saving in enforcement costs from reducing p compared to the net social costs of underdeterrence that will result if p is lowered non-trivially. If individuals are risk averse, the optimal fine generally is less than maximal, as first shown in Polinsky and Shavell (1979) (and elaborated upon in Kaplow, 1992). This is because the use of a very high fine would impose a substantial risk-bearing cost on individuals who commit the harmful act. Another more particular explanation involves reconsidering the argument that we used in the risk-neutral case. If the fine f is less than fm, it is still true that f can be raised and p lowered so as to maintain deterrence, but because of risk aversion, this implies that pf falls, meaning that fine revenue falls. The reduction in fine revenue reflects the disutility caused by imposing greater risk on risk-averse individuals. If individuals are sufficiently risk averse, the decline in fine revenue associated with greater risk-bearing could more than offset the savings in enforcement expenditures from reducing the probability of detection, implying that social welfare would be lower. Next, assume that the sanction is imprisonment and that individuals are risk neutral in imprisonment, that is, the disutility of imprisonment is the same for each additional year. (We did not discuss individuals’ attitudes toward the risk of imprisonment in Section 3 because the points we made there did not depend on this consideration.) Then the optimal imprisonment term is maximal

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

313

(Shavell, 1991b). The reasoning behind this result parallels that used to show that the optimal fine is maximal when individuals are risk neutral in fines. Specifically, if the imprisonment term is raised and the probability of detection lowered so as to keep the expected sanction constant, neither individual behavior nor the costs of imposing imprisonment are affected (by construction, the expected prison term is the same), but enforcement expenditures fall. Suppose instead that individuals are risk averse in imprisonment. In other words, the disutility of each year of imprisonment grows with the number of years in prison, perhaps because imprisonment becomes increasingly difficult to tolerate. In this case there is a stronger argument for setting the imprisonment sanction maximally than when individuals are risk neutral (Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). This is because, when the imprisonment term is raised, the probability of detection can be lowered even more than in the risk-neutral case without reducing deterrence. Thus, not only are there greater savings in enforcement expenditures, but also the social costs of imposing imprisonment sanctions decline because the expected prison term falls. Last, suppose that individuals are risk preferring in imprisonment, that is, the disutility of each year of imprisonment falls with the number of years in prison. This assumption seems particularly important: the first years of imprisonment may create special disutility, due to brutalization of the prisoner, or due to the stigma effect of having been imprisoned at all. Additionally, the fact that individuals discount the future disutility of imprisonment makes earlier years of imprisonment more important than later ones. If individuals are risk preferring in imprisonment, the optimal sanction may well be less than maximal (Polinsky and Shavell, 1997). In particular, the type of argument used above does not necessarily apply. When the sanction is raised, the probability that maintains deterrence cannot be lowered proportionally, implying that the expected prison term rises. Because the resulting increased cost of imposing imprisonment sanctions might exceed the savings in enforcement expenditures from lowering the probability, the optimal prison term might not be maximal. When the probability of detection is set optimally, together with the imprisonment term, underdeterrence may well result, not only to save enforcement expenditures, but also to reduce the costs of imposing imprisonment sanctions. (In theory, however, overdeterrence could be optimal for the reason mentioned in Section 3 - that overdeterrence could reduce the costs of imprisonment.) Now consider the situation when both fines and imprisonment are employed as sanctions. Recall that under the optimal enforcement policy, the fine must be maximal, for otherwise it cannot be desirable to employ imprisonment. The main point we wish to make is that, unlike when imprisonment is used alone, the optimal imprisonment term may not be maximal even if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment. Suppose that individuals are risk

314

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

neutral in imprisonment and fines. Then if the imprisonment term is raised and the probability of detection is lowered so as to keep the expected imprisonment term constant, deterrence declines because the expected fine falls (due to the reduction in the probability). Hence, to maintain deterrence, the probability cannot fall proportionally. But this implies that the expected prison term, and the costs of imposing imprisonment, are higher than previously. Only if the savings in enforcement costs are sufficiently large, therefore, is it socially desirable to raise the imprisonment sanction. Fault-Based Liability The least expensive way to accomplish compliance with the fault standard is to use the highest possible sanction and, given this sanction, the lowest probability of detection that deters individuals who would be at fault. The reason is that, if all individuals who would be at fault are deterred, the only cost incurred is associated with the setting of the probability; this cost is minimized by using the maximal sanction and a correspondingly low probability. Note that this is true regardless of whether the sanction is a fine or imprisonment and regardless of individuals’ attitudes toward the risk of fines or of imprisonment. Comparison of Rules As we emphasized earlier, under fault-based liability sanctions are not actually imposed (in the absence of mistakes), which is an advantage over strict liability when the sanction is a fine and individuals are risk averse, and is always an advantage when the sanction is imprisonment. Moreover, this advantage of fault-based liability implies a second advantage: it may allow a further savings in enforcement expenditures over that under strict liability. For example, suppose that the sanction is a fine and that injurers are risk averse. Then, as we have emphasized, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is not maximal, due to risk-bearing by injurers. This implies that the probability of detection needed to achieve any given level of deterrence is higher than if the fine were maximal. Under fault-based liability, however, the optimal fine is maximal despite the risk aversion of injurers (because the fine is not actually imposed), meaning that a lower probability can be employed. However, to decide which liability rule is preferable, these advantages of fault-based liability would have to be weighed against the disadvantages of this rule relative to strict liability that we mentioned at the end of Section 3 (one of which, as noted, will be discussed in Section 7). This concludes the presentation of the basic theory of public enforcement of law. We now turn to various extensions and refinements of the analysis.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

315

5. Accidental Harms As we noted at the outset, we assumed that individuals decide whether or not to commit acts that cause harm with certainty, that is, they decide whether or not to cause intentional harms. In many circumstances, however, harms are accidental - they occur only with a probability. For instance, if a driver speeds, he only creates a likelihood of a collision; or if a firm stores toxic chemicals in a substandard tank, the firm only creates the probability of a harmful spill. Essentially all that we have said above applies in a straightforward way when harms are accidental. If individuals are risk neutral, sanctions are monetary, and the expected sanction equals harm, then induced behavior will be socially optimal; further, the optimal magnitude of sanctions is maximal if individuals are risk neutral because this allows enforcement costs to be saved; and so forth. Our general conclusions from above can thus be interpreted to apply both when harms are intentional and cause harm for sure, as well as when actions alter the risk of harm. There is, however, an additional issue that arises when harm is uncertain: a sanction can be imposed either on the basis of the commission of a dangerous act that increases the chance of harm - storing chemicals in a substandard tank - or on the basis of the actual occurrence of harm - only if the tank ruptures and results in a spill. In principle, either approach can achieve optimal deterrence. To illustrate, suppose that the substandard tank has a 10 percent chance of rupturing, in which case the harm would be $10 million; the expected harm from using the tank therefore is $1 million. If injurers are risk neutral and sanctions are imposed only when harm occurs, deterrence will be optimal if, as usual, the expected sanction equals the harm of $10 million. Alternatively, if sanctions are imposed on the basis of the dangerous act of using the substandard tank, deterrence will be optimal if the owner of the tank faces an expected sanction equal to the expected harm due to his use of the substandard tank, $1 million. Several factors are relevant to the choice between act-based and harm-based sanctions (Shavell, 1993). First, act-based sanctions need not be as high to accomplish a given level of deterrence, and thus offer an underlying advantage over harm-based sanctions because of limitations in parties’ assets. In the example in the preceding paragraph, the owner of the storage tank might be able to pay the $1 million required if sanctions are act-based but not the $10 million required if sanctions are harm-based. Second, and closely related, because act-based sanctions need not be as high to accomplish deterrence, they offer an advantage over harm-based sanctions when parties are risk averse. Third, act-based sanctions and harm-based sanctions may differ in the ease with which they can be applied. In some circumstances, act-based sanctions may be simpler to impose (it might be less difficult to determine whether an oil shipper properly maintains its vessels’ holding tanks than to detect whether one

316

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

of the vessels leaked oil into the ocean); in other circumstances, harm-based sanctions may be easier (a driver who causes harm might be caught without difficulty, but not one who speeds). Fourth, it may be hard to calculate the expected harm due to an act, but relatively easy to ascertain the actual harm if it eventuates; if so, this constitutes an advantage of harm-based liability.

6. Costs of Imposing Fines We inquire in this section about the implications of costs borne by enforcement authorities in imposing fines. Our principal observation is that such costs should raise the level of the fine. We assume for simplicity that the probability of detection is fixed, that liability is strict, and that individuals are risk neutral. In this setting, recall from Section 3 that the optimal fine is h/p, the harm divided by the probability of detection. Now let there be a public cost k of imposing a fine. The optimal fine then becomes h/p + k; the cost k should be added to the fine that would otherwise be desirable (Becker, 1968, p. 192 and Polinsky and Shavell, 1992). The intuition behind this result is that, if an individual commits a harmful act, he causes society to bear not only the immediate harm h, but also, with probability p, the cost k of imposing the fine - that is, his act results in an expected total social cost of h + pk. If the fine is h/p + k, the individual’s expected fine is p[(h/p) + k] = h + pk, leading him to commit the harmful act if and only if his gain exceeds the expected total social cost of his act. For example, suppose the harm is $1,000, the probability of detection is 25 percent, and the cost of imposing the fine is $500. An individual’s harmful act causes society to bear expected total social costs of $1,125 - the harm of $1,000 plus a 25 percent chance of the $500 cost of imposing a fine. If the fine is set equal to $4,500, the individual’s expected fine also will equal $1,125. Additionally, observe that, not only does the state bear costs when fines are imposed, so do individuals who pay the fines (such as legal defense expenses). The costs borne by individuals, however, do not affect the formula for the optimal fine. Individuals properly take these costs into account, because they bear them.

7. Level of Activity We have been assuming that the sole decision that an individual makes is whether to act in a way that causes harm when engaging in some activity. In many contexts, however, an individual also makes a choice about his activity

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

317

level - that is, not only does he choose whether to commit a harmful act when engaging in an activity, he also chooses whether to engage in that activity or, more generally, at what level to do so. For example, besides deciding how to behave when driving (whether to exercise care in changing lanes), an individual also chooses how many miles to drive; the number of miles driven is the individual’s level of activity. Similarly, not only does a firm decide how to conduct its operations during production (whether to pollute), it also chooses its level of production; the output of the firm is its level of activity. The socially optimal activity level is such that the individual’s marginal utility from the activity just equals the marginal expected harm caused by the activity. Thus, the optimal number of miles driven is the level at which the marginal utility of driving an extra mile just equals the marginal expected harm per mile driven. The determination of the optimal level of activity presumes that individuals act optimally when engaging in the activity - for example, that they drive with appropriate care. Thus, in determining the optimal level of activity, an individual’s marginal utility from the activity is compared to the expected harm that results when he acts appropriately when engaging in the activity. Often this expected harm is positive even when a party acts optimally, because the cost of precautions (or, equivalently, the gain or savings from not taking precautions) exceeds the expected reduction in harm that taking the precautions would bring about. Will parties’ choices about their activity levels be socially correct under the two major forms of liability? The answer is that under strict liability, their choices about activity levels will be correct, but under fault-based liability, they generally will participate in activities to a socially excessive extent. Under strict liability, parties will choose the optimal level of activity because they will pay for all harm done. They will choose the optimal number of miles to drive because they will pay for all harm per mile driven. Under fault-based liability, however, parties generally do not pay for the harm they cause because, as we have discussed, they will be induced to behave so as not to be found at fault. Consequently, when deciding on their level of activity, they will choose an excessive level. They will not take into account the harm that each additional mile of driving causes, and therefore they will drive too much. The interpretation of the preceding points in relation to firms is that under strict liability the product price will reflect the expected harm caused by production, so that the price will reflect the full social cost of production. Hence, the amount purchased, and thus the level of production, will tend to be socially optimal. However, under fault-based liability, the product price will not reflect harm, but only the cost of precautions; thus, the amount sold, and the level of production, will be excessive. A related comment is that safety regulations and other regulatory requirements are often framed as standards of care that have to be met, but

318

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

which, if met, free the regulated party from liability. Hence, regulations of this character are subject to the criticism that they lead to excessive levels of the regulated activity. Making parties strictly liable for harm would be superior to safety regulation with respect to inducing socially correct activity levels. The tendency of parties to choose an excessive level of activity under fault-based liability, but not under strict liability, constitutes a fundamental advantage of strict liability; it was first emphasized in Shavell (1980) and Polinsky (1980b). This advantage, note, is stronger the greater is the harm engendered by engaging in the activity (given that behavior is optimal when engaging in the activity). Thus, for activities for which expected harm is likely to be substantial, the disadvantage of fault-based liability will be significant.

8. Mistakes Errors of the two classic types can occur in public enforcement of law. First, an individual who should be found liable might mistakenly not be found liable - a Type I error. Second, an individual who should not be found liable might mistakenly be found liable - a Type II error. For an individual who has been detected, let the probabilities of these errors be 01 and 02, respectively. Given the probability of detection p and the chances of Type I and Type II errors, an individual will commit the wrongful act if and only if his gain g net of his expected fine if he does commit it exceeds his expected fine if he does not commit it, namely, when g ! p(1 ! 01)f > ! p02f, or, equivalently, when g > (1 ! 01 ! 02)pf. The first point to note is that, as emphasized in Png (1986), both types of error reduce deterrence: the term (1 ! 01 ! 02)pf is declining in both 01 and 02. The first type of error diminishes deterrence because it lowers the expected fine if an individual violates the law. The second type of error, when an individual is mistakenly found liable, also lowers deterrence because it reduces the difference between the expected fine from violating the law and not violating it. In other words, the greater is 02, the smaller the increase in the expected fine if one violates the law, making a violation less costly to the individual. Because mistakes dilute deterrence, they reduce social welfare (see generally Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a). Specifically, to achieve any level of deterrence, the probability p must be higher to offset the effect of errors. It should also be noted that, were one to take into account an individual’s decision whether to engage in an activity (like driving), Type II errors have the additional effect of discouraging socially desirable participation in the activity. Now consider the optimal choice of the fine. Given any probability of detection, the dilution in deterrence caused by errors requires a higher fine to restore deterrence. If the probability and the fine are variable, then, as

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

319

explained in Section 4, the optimal fine is maximal. Somewhat surprisingly, the optimal fine remains maximal despite mistakes, by essentially the argument used previously: if the fine f were less than maximal, then f could be raised and the probability p lowered so as to keep deterrence constant, but saving enforcement costs. Now consider the possible risk aversion of individuals. As we emphasized in Section 4, the optimal fine under strict liability generally is less than maximal when individuals are risk averse, because lowering the fine from the maximum level reduces the bearing of risk. Introducing the possibility of mistakes may increase the desirability of lowering the fine because, due to Type II errors, individuals who do not violate the law are subject to the risk of having to pay a fine (Block and Sidak, 1980). Indeed, because the number of persons who do not violate the law often would far exceed the number who do, the desire to avoid imposing risk on the former group can lead to a substantial reduction in the optimal fine. Next, consider imprisonment and mistake. In this regard, our conclusions parallel those with respect to fines in several respects. Notably, mistakes of both types dilute the deterrent effects of imprisonment; and the optimal imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment but generally is not maximal if they are risk preferring in imprisonment. We have not yet commented on fault-based liability. Here, an important implication of mistake is that some individuals will bear sanctions even if they comply with the fault standard. Hence, the results regarding the optimal probability of detection and the sanction under strict liability apply to some extent under fault-based liability as well. Moreover, as stressed by Craswell and Calfee (1986), individuals will often have a motive to take excessive precautions in order to reduce the chance of being found erroneously at fault. Finally, observe that, although we have treated the probabilities of error as fixed, they can be influenced by procedural choices. For example, prosecutorial resources can be increased in order to reduce the probability of a Type I error, or the standard of proof can be raised to reduce the chance of a Type II error (although this presumably increases Type I errors). Because the reduction of both types of error increase deterrence, expenditures made to reduce errors may be socially beneficial (Kaplow and Shavell, 1994a).

9. General Enforcement In many settings, enforcement may be said to be general in the sense that several different types of violations will be detected by an enforcement agent’s activity. For example, a police officer waiting at the roadside may notice a driver who litters as well as one who goes through a red light or who speeds, and a tax auditor may detect a variety of infractions when he examines a tax

320

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

return. To investigate such situations, suppose that a single probability of detection applies uniformly to all harmful acts, regardless of the magnitude of the harm. (The contrasting assumption is that enforcement is specific, meaning that the probability is chosen independently for each type of harmful act.) The main point that we want to make is that in contexts in which enforcement is general, the optimal sanction rises with the severity of the harm and is maximal only for relatively high harms; this point was first made in Shavell (1991b) (Mookherjee and Png, 1992a is closely related). To see this, assume that liability is strict, the sanction is a fine, and injurers are risk neutral. Let f(h) be the fine given harm h. Then, for any given general probability of detection p, the optimal fine schedule is h/p, provided that h/p is feasible; otherwise - for high h (all h such that h/p > fm) - the optimal fine is maximal. This schedule is obviously optimal given p because it implies that the expected fine equals harm, thereby inducing ideal behavior, whenever that is possible. The question remains whether it would be desirable to lower p and raise fines to the maximal level for the low-harm acts for which h/p is less than maximal. The answer is that if p is reduced for the relatively low-harm acts (and the fine raised for them), then p - being general - is also reduced for the high-harm acts for which the fine is already maximal, resulting in lower deterrence of these acts. The decline in deterrence of high-harm acts may cause a greater social loss than the savings in enforcement costs from lowering p. To express this point differently, p must be sufficiently high to avoid significant underdeterrence of high-harm acts (for which fines are maximal). But since this p also applies to less harmful acts, the fines for them do not need to be maximal in order to appropriately deter them. The result that, when enforcement is general, sanctions should rise with the severity of harm up to a maximum also holds if the sanction is imprisonment and if liability is fault-based. The underlying reasoning is the same as that given above.

10. Marginal Deterrence In many circumstances, a person may consider which of several harmful acts to commit, for example, whether to release only a small amount of a pollutant into a river or a large amount, or whether to kidnap a person or also to kill the kidnap victim. In such contexts, the threat of sanctions plays a role in addition to the usual one of attempting to deter individuals from committing harmful acts: for individuals who are not deterred, sanctions influence which harmful acts individuals choose to commit. Notably, such individuals will have a reason to commit less harmful rather than more harmful acts if expected sanctions rise with harm. Deterrence of a more harmful act because its sanction exceeds that

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

321

for a less harmful act is sometimes referred to as marginal deterrence (it apparently was so named by Stigler, 1970). Other things being equal, as observed by Beccaria (1770, p. 32) and Bentham (1789, p. 171), it is socially desirable that enforcement policy creates marginal deterrence, so that those who are not deterred from committing harmful acts have a reason to moderate the amount of harm that they cause. This suggests that sanctions should rise with the magnitude of harm and, therefore, that sanctions should not generally be maximal. However, fostering marginal deterrence may conflict with achieving deterrence generally: in order for the schedule of sanctions to rise steeply enough to accomplish marginal deterrence, sanctions for less harmful acts may have to be so low that individuals are not deterred from committing some harmful act. We have two additional observations to make about marginal deterrence. First, marginal deterrence can be promoted by increasing the probability of detection as well as the magnitude of sanctions. For example, kidnappers can be better deterred from killing their victims if more police resources are devoted to apprehending kidnappers who murder their victims than to those who do not. (But in circumstances in which enforcement is general, the probability of detection cannot be independently altered for acts that cause different degrees of harm.) Second, marginal deterrence is naturally accomplished if the expected sanction equals harm for all levels of harm; for if a person is paying for harm done, he will have to pay appropriately more if he does greater harm. Thus, for instance, if a polluter’s expected fine would rise from $100 to $500 if he dumps five gallons instead of one gallon of waste into a lake, where each gallon causes $100 of harm, his marginal incentives to pollute will be correct. For formal analyses of marginal deterrence, see Shavell (1992), Wilde (1992), and Mookherjee and Png (1994).

11. Principal-Agent Relationship Although we have assumed that an injurer is a single actor, injurers often are more appropriately characterized as collective entities, and specifically as a principal and the principal’s agent. For example, the principal could be a firm and the agent an employee; or the principal could be a contractor and the agent a subcontractor. When harm is caused by the behavior of principals and agents, many of the conclusions of our prior analysis are not fundamentally altered; they simply carry over to the sanctioning of principals. Notably, if a risk-neutral principal faces an expected fine equal to harm done, he will in effect be in the same position vis-à-vis his agent as society is vis-à-vis a single potential violator of law (see Newman and Wright, 1990 on a closely related point). Consequently,

322

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

the principal will behave socially optimally in controlling his agents, and in particular will contract with them and monitor them in ways that will give the agents socially appropriate incentives to reduce harm (but see Arlen, 1994). Another result that carries over to the principal-agent context is that it often will be desirable for society to tolerate some degree of underdeterrence in order to conserve enforcement resources. A question about enforcement that arises when there are principals and agents is the allocation of financial sanctions between the two parties. It is apparent, however, that the particular allocation of sanctions does not matter when, as would be the natural presumption, the parties can reallocate the sanctions through their own contract. For example, if the agent finds that he faces a large fine but is more risk averse than the principal, the principal can assume it; conversely, if the fine is imposed on the principal, he will retain it and not impose an internal sanction on the agent. Thus, the post-contract sanctions that the agent bears are not affected by the particular division of sanctions initially selected by the enforcement authority. The allocation of monetary sanctions between principals and agents would matter, however, if some allocations allow the pair to reduce their total burden. An important example is when a fine is imposed only on the agent and he is unable to pay it because his assets are less than the fine (see Sykes, 1981, and Kornhauser, 1982). Then, he and the principal (who often would have higher assets) would jointly escape part of the fine, diluting deterrence. The fine therefore should be imposed on the principal rather than on the agent (or at least the part of the fine that the agent cannot pay). A closely related point is that the imposition of imprisonment sanctions on agents may be desirable when their assets are less than the harm that they can cause, even if the principal’s assets are sufficient to pay the optimal fine (see Polinsky and Shavell, 1993). The fact that an agent’s assets are limited means that the principal may be unable to control him adequately through use of contractually-determined penalties, which can only be monetary. For example, a firm may not be able, despite the threat of salary reduction or dismissal, to induce its employees never to rig bids. In such circumstances, it may be socially valuable to use the threat of personal criminal liability and a jail sentence to better control agents’ misconduct.

12. Settlements Although we have thus far assumed that when a liable injurer is discovered he is sanctioned in some automatic fashion, in practice he must be found civilly or criminally liable in a trial, and before this occurs, he commonly settles in lieu of trial. (In the criminal context, the settlement usually takes the form of

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

323

a plea bargain, an agreement in which the injurer pleads guilty to a reduced charge.) Given the prevalence of settlements, it is important to consider how they affect deterrence and the optimal system of public enforcement, and whether settlements are socially desirable. There are two general reasons why parties might prefer an out-of-court settlement to a trial (see generally the survey by Cooter and Rubinfeld, 1989; and for some recent discussions of plea bargaining, see, for example, Reinganum, 1988, and Miceli, 1996). First, a trial is costly to the parties in terms of time and/or money. Second, settlements eliminate the risks inherent in the trial outcome, a benefit to parties who are averse to such risks. These advantages of settlement to the parties suggest that settlement is socially valuable, but the effect of settlement on deterrence is a complicating factor. Specifically, settlements dilute deterrence: for if injurers desire to settle, it must be because the expected disutility of sanctions is lowered for them (see generally Polinsky and Rubinfeld, 1988). The state may be able to offset this settlement-related reduction in deterrence by increasing the level of sanctions; if so, settlements need not compromise the overall level of deterrence. Settlements may have other socially undesirable consequences. First, they may result in sanctions that are not as well tailored to harmful acts as would be true of court-determined sanctions. For example, if injurers have private information about the harm that they have caused, settlements will tend to reflect the average harm caused, whereas trial outcomes may better approximate the actual harm. Thus, the distribution of sanctions meted out through settlements will not be as good in terms of inducing injurers to take proper precautions (high-harm injurers will be underdeterred, and vice versa). Second, settlements hinder the amplification and development of the law through the setting of precedents, a factor of occasional relevance; and settlements also sometimes allow defendants to keep aspects of their behavior secret, which can reduce deterrence. Third, settlements for prison terms can result in increases in public expenditures on jail if defendants are risk averse in imprisonment. On the social desirability of settlement, see, for example, Shavell (1997a) and Spier (1997).

13. Self-Reporting We have assumed that individuals are subject to sanctions only if they are detected by an enforcement agent, but in fact parties sometimes disclose their own violations to enforcement authorities. For example, firms often report violations of environmental and safety regulations, individuals usually notify police of their involvement in traffic accidents, and even criminals occasionally turn themselves in.

324

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

We explain here why it is generally socially desirable for the structure of enforcement to be such as to encourage self-reporting (see Kaplow and Shavell, 1994b). Self-reporting can be induced by lowering the sanction for individuals who disclose their own infractions. Moreover, the reward for self-reporting can be made small enough that deterrence is only negligibly reduced. To amplify, assume for simplicity that the sanction is a fine f, that the probability of detection is p, and that individuals are risk neutral. If an individual commits a violation and does not self report, his expected fine is pf. Suppose the fine if an individual self-reports is set just below pf, say at pf ! 0, where 0 > 0 is arbitrarily small. Then the individual will want to self-report but the deterrent effect of the sanction will be (approximately) the same as if he did not self-report. For example, suppose that the fine if an individual does not self report is $1,000 and that the probability of detection is 10 percent, so the expected fine is $100. If the fine for self-reporting is slightly below $100, such as $95, or even $99, individuals will self-report but deterrence will barely be reduced. Given that self-reporting can be induced essentially without compromising deterrence, why is self-reporting socially advantageous? There are two basic reasons. First, self-reporting reduces enforcement costs because, when it occurs, the enforcement authority does not have to identify and prove who the violator was. If a company reports that it caused pollution, environmental enforcers do not need to spend as much effort trying to detect pollution and establishing its source. Second, self-reporting reduces risk, and thus is advantageous if injurers are risk averse. Drivers bear less risk because they know that if they cause an accident, they can (and will be led to) report this to the police and suffer a lower and certain sanction, rather than face a substantially higher sanction (for hit and run driving) imposed only with some probability.

14. Repeat Offenders In practice, the law often sanctions repeat offenders more severely than first-time offenders. We explain here why such a policy may be socially desirable. Note first that sanctioning repeat offenders more severely cannot be socially advantageous if deterrence always induces first-best behavior. If the sanction for polluting and causing a $1,000 harm is $1,000, then any person who pollutes and pays $1,000 is a person whose gain from polluting (say the savings from not installing pollution control equipment) must have exceeded $1,000. Social welfare therefore is higher as a result of his polluting. If such an individual polluted and was sanctioned in the past, that only means that it was socially desirable for him to have polluted previously. Raising the current sanction because of his having a record of sanctions would overdeter him now.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

325

Accordingly, only if deterrence is inadequate is it possibly desirable to condition sanctions on offense history to increase deterrence. But deterrence often will be inadequate because, as we emphasized in Section 4, it will usually be worthwhile for the state to tolerate some underdeterrence in order to reduce enforcement expenses. Given that there is underdeterrence, making sanctions depend on offense history may be beneficial for two reasons. First, as developed in Polinsky and Shavell (1996), the use of offense history may create an additional incentive not to violate the law: if getting caught violating the law implies not only an immediate sanction, but also a higher sanction for any future violation, an individual will be more deterred from committing a violation presently. Second, as studied, for example, in Rubinstein (1979) and Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1991), making sanctions depend on offense history allows society to take advantage of information about the dangerousness of individuals and the need to deter them: individuals with offense histories may be more likely than average to commit future violations, which might make it desirable for purposes of deterrence to impose higher sanctions on them. There is also an incapacitation-based (see Section 16) reason for making sanctions depend on offense history. Repeat offenders are more likely to have higher propensities to commit violations in the future and thus more likely to be worth incapacitating by imprisonment.

15. Imperfect Knowledge about the Probability and Magnitude of Sanctions Although we have implicitly assumed that injurers know the probability and magnitude of sanctions, this is not always the case. Individuals frequently have imperfect knowledge of these variables; that is, they have estimates, or more likely, subjective probability distributions, describing the true probability of a sanction and its true magnitude. They might not know the true probability of a sanction for several reasons: because the enforcement authority refrains from publishing information about the probability (perhaps hoping that individuals will believe it to be higher than it is in fact); because the probability is variable, depending on factors that individuals do not fully understand (the probability of a tax audit, for example, is influenced by a large number of considerations); and because probabilities seem to be difficult for individuals to assess. Also, individuals may have incomplete knowledge of the true magnitude of sanctions, particularly if the magnitudes of sanctions are not fixed by law, but are to some degree discretionary. The implications of injurers’ imperfect knowledge are straightforward. First, to predict how individuals behave, what is relevant, of course, is not the

326

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

actual probability and magnitude of a sanction, but the perceived levels or distributions of these variables. Second, to determine the optimal probability and magnitude of a sanction, account must be taken of the relationship between the actual and the perceived variables (on which, see, for instance, Bebchuk and Kaplow, 1992, and see Kaplow, 1990b, on learning about sanctions). For example, suppose that there is a delay of at least a year before individuals fully comprehend a change in the probability of enforcement. Then if enforcement resources are increased so as to make the probability, say, 15 percent rather than 10 percent, there might not be a significant increase in deterrence for some time, making such an investment less worthwhile. Or, for instance, suppose that the sanction for some act, such as robbery, is variable (say from one month of jail time to 10 years), and that individuals’ perceptions are quite rough, not based on true averages but more on the possible range. Then increasing the average sentence might have very little effect on deterrence, but increasing the probability substantially might still augment deterrence. The psychology and learning process (see Sah, 1991) by which individuals assimilate and formulate perceived probabilities of sanctions and their magnitude are important, therefore, to determining how deterrence works and what optimal policy is.

16. Incapacitation Our discussion of public enforcement has presumed that the threat of sanctions reduces harm by discouraging individuals from causing harm - that is, by deterring them. However, an entirely different way for society to reduce harm is by imposing sanctions that remove parties from positions in which they are able to cause harm - that is, by incapacitating them. Imprisonment is the primary incapacitative sanction, although there are other examples: individuals can lose their drivers licenses, preventing them from doing harm while driving; businesses can lose their right to operate in certain domains, and the like. We focus here on imprisonment, but what we say applies to incapacitative sanctions generally; on the economic theory of incapacitation, see Shavell (1987b). To better understand the role of public enforcement when sanctions are incapacitative, suppose that the sole function of sanctions is to incapacitate; that is, sanctions do not deter. (Deterrence might not occur if, for instance, individuals’ gains from harmful acts exceed the expected sanctions, given the relevant range of the probabilities and magnitudes of the sanctions.) We assume that the social goal is as before, to maximize gains from acts less harm, and less the costs of enforcement and sanctions, including the costs of keeping individuals in prison.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

327

The optimal sanction to impose on an individual who is apprehended is determined by comparing the expected harm, net of gains, he would cause if not in prison to the private and public costs of imprisonment. If the expected net harm exceeds the costs of imprisonment, he should be put in prison and kept there as long as this condition holds. Thus, the optimal sanction as a function of expected net harm is zero up to a threshold - the point at which expected net harm equals the costs of imprisonment - and then rises discontinuously to the length of time during which the person’s net expected harm exceeds imprisonment costs. Jail should only be used to incapacitate individuals whose net harm is relatively high. Two points about the incapacitative rationale are worth making. First, there is evidence that suggests that the expected harm caused by individuals declines with their age. Thus, from the incapacitative standpoint, individuals should be released from jail when their dangerousness falls below the cost of incapacitation. Second, as a matter of logic, the incapacitative rationale might imply that a person should be put in jail even if he has not committed a crime - because his danger to society makes incapacitating him worthwhile. This would be true, for example, if there were some means accurately to predict a person’s dangerousness independently of his actual behavior. In practice, however, the fact that a person has committed a harmful act may be the best basis for predicting his future behavior, in which case the incapacitation rationale would suggest imposing a jail term only if the individual has committed an especially harmful act. Last, we comment on the relationship between optimal enforcement when incapacitation is the goal versus when deterrence is the goal. First, when incapacitation is the goal, the optimal magnitude of the sanction is independent of the probability of apprehension. In contrast, when deterrence is the goal, the optimal sanction depends on the probability - the sanction generally is higher the lower is the probability. Second, when incapacitation is the goal, the sanction rises discontinuously with the magnitude of harm (from zero to a positive amount), but when deterrence is the goal the sanction rises continuously with harm. Third, when deterrence is the goal, the probability and magnitude of sanctions depend on the ability to deter, and if this ability is limited (as, for instance, with the enraged), a low expected sanction may be optimal. However, a high expected sanction still might be called for to incapacitate.

328

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

17. Conclusion It may be worthwhile summarizing the main points that we have made in this chapter: (a) When the probability of detection is for some reason fixed, the benchmark level of the optimal fine is the harm divided by the probability of detection, for this results in an expected fine equal to the harm. However, costs incurred by the public in collecting the fine should be added to the benchmark level of the fine, and risk aversion of injurers should usually lower the level of the fine. (b) When the probability of detection may be varied, high sanctions may be optimal, for this allows a relatively low probability to be employed and thereby saves enforcement costs. Indeed, the optimal fine is in principle maximal for this reason if individuals are risk neutral in wealth, and the optimal imprisonment term is maximal if individuals are risk neutral or risk averse in imprisonment. More realistically, optimal sanctions are not maximal when individuals are risk averse in wealth or risk preferring in imprisonment (as well as for the general enforcement reasons discussed in Section 9), although the motive to set sanctions at relatively high levels in order to reduce enforcement costs still applies. (c) Optimal enforcement tends to be characterized by some degree of underdeterrence relative to first-best behavior, because this conserves enforcement resources. More precisely, by lowering the probability of detection from a level that would lead to first-best behavior, the state reduces enforcement costs, and although more individuals commit the harmful act, these individuals do not cause social welfare to decline substantially because their gains are nearly equal to the harm. (d) The use of fines should be exhausted before resort is made to costlier sanctions, notably imprisonment. (e) An advantage of fault-based liability over strict liability is that costly sanctions - fines when individuals are risk averse, and imprisonment - are imposed less often: under fault-based liability, injurers generally are induced (in the absence of mistakes) to obey fault standards, and therefore ordinarily do not bear sanctions. Under strict liability, however, injurers are sanctioned whenever they are caught. (f) An advantage of strict liability over fault-based liability is that it is easier to apply. Another advantage is that injurers’ activity-level decisions generally will be better: under strict liability, injurers’ activity levels will tend to be optimal because injurers will pay for harm that they cause. But under fault-based liability, their activity levels will tend to be excessive because they generally will not pay for harm that they cause (because they will be led to behave without fault).

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

329

These and other basic conclusions about the public enforcement of law that we have described in this essay are now, for the most part, well-established in the economic literature on enforcement. However, an important aspect of this subject that has received relatively little attention is the behavior of public enforcers themselves. Because our focus was on deriving socially optimal public enforcement policies, we assumed, as is conventional, that public enforcers act so as to maximize social welfare. A logical step to take next would be to re-examine optimal enforcement policies when public enforcers behave in a self-interested manner. Although some effort already has been devoted to this inquiry, much remains to be done.

Acknowledgments Polinsky’s research was supported by the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences (through National Science Foundation grant #SBR-960123) and the John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics at Stanford Law School. Shavell’s research was supported by the John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business at Harvard Law School. This essay previously appeared with a less comprehensive bibliography in Peter Newman (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and The Law, London, Macmillan Reference Ltd. (1998).

Bibliography on Public Enforcement of Law (8000) Adelstein, Richard and Miceli, Thomas J. (1997), ‘Toward a Comparative Economics of Plea Bargaining’, Manuscript. Allingham, Michael G. and Sandmo, Agnar (1972), ‘Income Tax Evasion: A Theoretical Analysis’, 1 Journal of Public Economics, 323-338. Altrogge, Phyllis and Shughart, William F. (1984), ‘The Regressive Nature of Civil Penalties’, 4 International Review of Law and Economics, 55-66. Andenaes, Johannes (1966), ‘The General Preventive Effects of Punishment’, 114 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 949-983. Andenaes, Johannes (1971), ‘Deterrence and Specific Offenses’, 38 University of Chicago Law Review, 537-553. Andenaes, Johannes (1974), Punishment and Deterrence, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press. Anderson, Lee G. and Lee, Dwight R. (1986), ‘Optimal Governing Instrument, Operation Level, and Enforcement in Natural Resource Regulation: The Case of the Fishery’, 68 American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 678-690. Andreoni, James (1991), ‘Reasonable Doubt and the Optimal Magnitude of Fines: Should the Penalty Fit the Crime?’, 22 RAND Journal of Economics, 385-395.

330

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Andreoni, James, Erard, Brian and Feinstein, Jonathan (1998), ‘Tax Compliance’, Journal of Economic Literature, forthcoming. Arlen, Jennifer A. (1994), ‘The Potentially Perverse Effects of Corporate Criminal Liability’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 833-867. Arlen, Jennifer. (1997), ‘Corporate Crime and Its Control’, U.S.C. Law School Working Paper Series, Working Paper No. 97-2, forthcoming in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law. Arlen, Jennifer and Kraakman, Reinier (1997), ‘Controlling Corporate Misconduct: An Analysis of Corporate Liability Regimes’, 72 New York University Law Review, 687-779. Avio, Kenneth L. (1975), ‘Recidivism in the Economic Model of Crime’, 13 Economic Inquiry, 450-456. Avio, Kenneth L. (1987), ‘Clemency in Economic and Retributive Models of Punishment’, 7 International Review of Law and Economics, 79-88. Avio, Kenneth L. and Clark, C. Scott (1976), Property Crime in Canada: An Econometric Study, Toronto, University of Toronto Press. Ayres, Ian and Levitt, Steven D. (1998), ‘Measuring the Positive Externalities from Unobservable Victim Precaution: An Empirical Analysis of Lojack’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, forthcoming. Baldry, Jonathan C. (1980), ‘Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment: A Note’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 617-619. Baldry, J.C. (1984), ‘The Enforcement of Income Tax Laws: Efficiency Implications’, 60 Economic Record, 156-159. Basu, Kaushik, Bhattacharya, Sudipto and Mishra, Ajit (1992), ‘Notes on Bribery and the Control of Corruption’, 48 Journal of Public Economics, 349-359. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘Optimal Sanctions When Individuals Are Imperfectly Informed About the Probability of Apprehension’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 365-370. Bebchuk, Lucian Arye and Kaplow, Louis (1993), ‘Optimal Sanctions and Differences in Individuals’ Likelihood of Avoiding Detection’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 217-224. Beccaria, Cesare (1770), On Crimes and Punishments, and Other Writings. Bellamy, Richard (ed.), Davies, Richard, et al. (trans.), New York, Cambridge University Press, 1995. Becker, Gary S. (1968), ‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach’, 76 Journal of Political Economy, 169-217. Becker, Gary S. and Landes, William M. (eds) (1974), Essays in the Economics of Crime and Punishment, New York, Columbia University Press. Becker, Gary S. and Stigler, George J. (1974), ‘Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-18. Ben-Shahar, Omri (1997), ‘Playing Without a Rulebook: Optimal Enforcement When Individuals Learn the Penalty Only by Committing the Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 409-421. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1995), ‘Blaming the Victim: Optimal Incentives for Private Precautions Against Crime’, 11 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 434-455. Ben-Shahar, Omri and Harel, Alon (1996), ‘The Economics of the Law of Criminal Attempts: A Victim-Centered Perspective’, 145 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 299-351.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

331

Benson, Bruce L. and Baden, John (1985), ‘The Political Economy of Government Corruption: The Logic of Underground Government’, 14 Journal of Legal Studies, 391-410. Benson, Bruce L., Kim, Iljoong and Rasmussen, David W. (1994), ‘Estimating Deterrence Effects: A Public Choice Perspective on the Economics of Crime Literature’,61 Southern Economic Journal, 161-168. Bentham, Jeremy (1789), ‘An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation’, in The Utilitarians, Rept. Garden City, NY, Anchor Books, 1973. Besanko, David and Spulber, Daniel F. (1989), ‘Delegated Law Enforcement and Noncooperative Behavior’, 5 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 25-52. Block, Michael K. (1991), ‘Optimal Penalties, Criminal Law and the Control of Corporate Behavior’, 71 Boston University Law Review, 395-419. Block, Michael K. and Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1986), ‘The Spillover Effect of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Review of Economics and Statistics, 122-131. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975a), ‘Crime and Punishment Reconsidered’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-247. Block, Michael K. and Lind, Robert C. (1975b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crimes Punishable by Imprisonment’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 479-492. Block, Michael K. and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1980), ‘The Cost of Antitrust Deterrence: Why Not Hang a Price Fixer Now and Then?’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1131-1139. Block, Michael Kent, Nold, Frederick Carl and Sidak, Joseph Gregory (1981), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Antitrust Enforcement’, 89 Journal of Political Economy, 429-445. Bone, John (1985), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Crime’, 5 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-246. Bose, Pinaki (1995a), ‘Anticipatory Compliance and Effective Regulatory Activity’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 151-159. Bose, Pinaki (1995b), ‘Regulatory Errors, Optimal Fines, and the Level of Compliance’, 56 Journal of Public Economics, 475-484. Bowles, Roger and Garoupa, Nuno (1997), ‘Casual Police Corruption and the Economics of Crime’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 75-87. Brown, William W. and Reynolds, Morgan O. (1973), ‘Crime and “Punishment”: Risk Implications’, 6 Journal of Economic Theory, 508-514. Burnovski, Moshe and Safra, Zvi (1994), ‘Deterrence Effects of Sequential Punishment Policies: Should Repeat Offenders be More Severely Punished?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 341-350. Cadot, Olivier (1987), ‘Corruption as a Gamble’, 33 Journal of Public Economics, 223-244. Cameron, Samuel (1988), ‘The Economics of Crime Deterrence: A Survey of Theory and Evidence’, 41 Kyklos, 301-323. Cameron, Samuel (1989), ‘On the Welfare Economics of Capital Punishment’, 28 Australian Economic Papers, 253-266. Campbell, Donald T. and Ross, H. Laurence (1988), ‘The Connecticut Crackdown on Speeding: Time-Series Data in Quasi-experimental Analysis’, in Overman, E. Samuel (ed.), Methodology and Epistemology of Social Science: Selected Papers, Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press, 222-237. Carlin, Paul and Sandy, Robert (1990), ‘The Value of Time and the Effect of Fines on Child Car Safety Seat Usage’, 22 Applied Economics, 463-476.

332

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Carr-Hill, R.A. and Stern, N.H. (1979), Crime, the Police and Criminal Statistics: An Analysis of Official Statistics for England and Wales Using Econometric Methods, London, Academic Press. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1979), ‘Crime and Punishment with Possible Post-Offense Compromise’, 17 Academia Economic Papers, 131-167. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1990), ‘Plea Bargaining with the IRS’, 41 Journal of Public Economics, 319-333. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1991), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Proceedings in Civil-Law Countries’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 111-116. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus (1993), ‘Oscillatory vs. Stationary Enforcement of Law’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 303-315. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus and Jiang, Neville (1993), ‘Are Fines More Efficient than Imprisonment?’, 51 Journal of Public Economics, 391-413. Chu, C.Y. Cyrus, Hu, Sheng-cheng and Huang, Ting-yuan (1997), ‘Punishing Repeat Offenders More Severely!’, Manuscript. Chwe, Michael Suk-Young (1990), ‘Why Were Workers Whipped? Pain in a Principal-Agent Model’, 100 Economic Journal, 1109-1121. Clotfelter, Charles T. (1977), ‘Public Services, Private Substitutes, and the Demand for Protection Against Crime’, 67 American Economic Review, 867-877. Clotfelter, Charles T. (1983), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Rates: An Analysis of Individual Returns’, 65 Review of Economics and Statistics, 363-373. Coffee, John C., Jr (1980), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Non-Chicago View of the Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 419-476. Cohen, Mark A. (1986), ‘The Costs and Benefits of Oil Spill Prevention and Enforcement’, 13 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 167-188. Cohen, Mark A. (1987), ‘Optimal Enforcement Strategy to Prevent Oil Spills: An Application of a Principal-Agent Model with Moral Hazard’, 30 Journal of Law and Economics, 23-51. Cohen, Mark A. (1989a), ‘The Role of Criminal Sanctions in Antitrust Enforcement’, 7 Contemporary Policy Issues, 36-46. Cohen, Mark A. (1989b), ‘Corporate Crime and Punishment: A Study of Social Harm and Sentencing Practice in the Federal Courts, 1984-1987’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 605-660. Cohen, Mark A. (1992), ‘Environmental Crime and Punishment: Legal/Economic Theory and Empirical Evidence on Enforcement of Federal Environmental Statutes’, 82 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 1054-1108. Cook, Philip J. (1977), ‘Punishment and Crime: A Critique of Current Findings Concerning the Preventative Effects of Punishment’, 41 Law and Contemporary Problems, 164-209. Cook, Philip J. (1980), ‘Research in Criminal Deterrence: Laying the Groundwork for the Second Decade’, in Morris, Norval and Tonry, Michael (eds), 2 Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research, University of Chicago Press, 211-268. Cook, Philip J. (1983), ‘Costs of Crime’, in Kadish, Sanford H. (ed.), 1 Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice, New York, The Free Press, 373-378. Cook, Philip J. (1986), ‘The Relationship Between Victim Resistance and Injury in Noncommercial Robbery’, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, 405-416.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

333

Cook, Philip J. (1987), ‘The Economics of Criminal Sanctions’, in Friedland, M.L. (ed.), Sanctions and Rewards in the Legal System: A Multidisciplinary Approach, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 50-78. Cook, Philip J., Molliconi, Stephanie and Cole, Thomas B. (1995), ‘Regulating Gun Markets’, 86 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 59-92. Cooter, Robert D. and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution’, 27 Journal of Economic Literature, 1067-1097. Cox, Gary W. (1994), ‘A Note on Crime and Punishment’, 78 Public Choice, 115-124. Craswell, Richard and Calfee, John E. (1986), ‘Deterrence and Uncertain Legal Standards’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 279-303. Daniel, Kermit, and Lott, John R., Jr (1995), ‘Should Criminal Penalties Include Third-Party Avoidance Costs?’, 24 Journal of Legal Studies, 523-534. Das-Gupta, Arindam and Mookherjee, Dilip (1995), ‘Tax Amnesties in India: An Empirical Evaluation’, Institute for Economic Development, Boston University, Discussion Paper No. 53. Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G. (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Criminal Law as a Preference-Shaping Policy’, Duke Law Journal, 1-38. Davis, Michael L. (1988), ‘Time and Punishment: An Intertemporal Model of Crime’, 96 Journal of Political Economy, 383-390. Dickens, William T. (1986), ‘Crime and Punishment Again: The Economic Approach with a Psychological Twist’, 30 Journal of Public Economics, 97-107. Diver, Colin S. (1980), ‘A Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 28 Public Policy, 257-299. Dye, Ronald A. (1986), ‘Optimal Monitoring Policies in Agencies’, 17 RAND Journal of Economics, 339-350. Earnhart, Dietrich (1997), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Protection Laws Under Communism and Democracy’, 40 Journal of Law and Economics, 377-402. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972a), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Criminal Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 259-276. Ehrlich, Isaac (1972b), ‘Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation’, 80 Journal of Political Economy, 521-565. Ehrlich, Isaac (1975), ‘The Deterrent Effect of Capital Punishment: A Question of Life and Death’, 65 American Economic Review, 397-417. Ehrlich, Isaac (1981), ‘On the Usefulness of Controlling Individuals: An Economic Analysis of Rehabilitation, Incapacitation and Deterrence’, 71 American Economic Review, 307-332. Ehrlich, Isaac (1982), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws and the Concept of Justice: A Positive Analysis’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Ehrlich, Isaac (1996), ‘Crime, Punishment, and the Market for Offenses’, 10 Journal of Economic Perspectives, 43-67. Ehrlich, Isaac and Brower, George D. (1987), ‘On the Issue of Causality in the Economic Model of Crime and Law Enforcement: Some Theoretical Considerations and Experimental Evidence’, 77 AEA Papers and Proceedings, 99-106 Eide, Erling (1994), Economics of Crime: Deterrence and the Rational Offender, Amsterdam, Elsevier. Eide, Erling (1995), ‘RDEU Models of Crime’, University of Oslo Working Papers, WP No. C1.

334

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Eide, Erling (1997), ‘Economics of Criminal Behavior: Survey and Bibliography’, University of Oslo Working Papers, WP No. C5. Elzinga, Kenneth G. and Breit, William (1976), The Antitrust Penalties: A Study in Law and Economics, New Haven, Yale University Press. Epple, Dennis and Visscher, Michael (1984), ‘Environmental Pollution: Modeling Occurrence, Detection, and Deterrence’, 27 Journal of Law and Economics, 29-60. Evans, William N., Neville, Doreen and Graham, John D. (1991), ‘General Deterrence of Drunk Driving: Evaluation of Recent American Policies’, 11 Risk Analysis, 279-289. Faith, Roger L. and Tollison, Robert D. (1983), ‘The Pricing of Surrogate Crime and Law Enforcement’, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, 401-411. Feinstein, Jonathan S. (1990), ‘Detection Controlled Estimation’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 233-276. Fenn, Paul and Veljanovski, Cento G. (1988), ‘A Positive Economic Theory of Regulatory Enforcement’, 98 Economic Journal, 1055-1070. Forst, Brian and Brosi, Kathleen B. (1977), ‘A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of the Prosecutor’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 177-191. Fowles, Richard and Loeb, Peter D. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 916-921. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1995), ‘Negotiated Enforcement and Criminal Deterrence’, University of Bologna, Manuscript. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997a), ‘Amnesties, Settlements and Optimal Tax Enforcement’, University of Bologna, Manuscript. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (1997b), ‘Tax Evasion and Tax Compliance’, preliminary version, forthcoming in International Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. Franzoni, Luigi Alberto (forthcoming), ‘Punishment and Grace: On the Economics of Permanent Amnesties’, Public Finance/Finances Publiques. Friedman, David D. (1981), ‘Reflections on Optimal Punishment, or: Should the Rich Pay Higher Fines?’, 3 Research in Law and Economics, 185-205. Friedman, David and Sjostrom, William (1993), ‘Hanged for a Sheep - The Economics of Marginal Deterrence’, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, 345-366. Furlong, William J. (1987), ‘A General Equilibrium Model of Crime Commission and Prevention’, 34 Journal of Public Economics, 87-103. Garoupa, Nuno (1995), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Imperfect Information’, University of York, Discussion Paper 95/96. Garoupa, Nuno (1997a), ‘The Theory of Optimal Law Enforcement’, 11 Journal of Economic Surveys, 267-295. Garoupa, Nuno (1997b), ‘The Economics of Organized Crime and Optimal Law Enforcement: the Urge for a Tougher Policy’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript. Garoupa, Nuno (1997c), ‘The Role of Moral Values in the Economic Analysis of Crime: A General Equilibrium Approach’, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Manuscript. Garoupa, Nuno (forthcoming), ‘Prison, Parole and the Criminal Justice Act 1991', 18 Research in Law and Economics. Gibbons, Thomas (1982), ‘The Utility of Economic Analysis of Crime’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 173-191. Gibbs, Jack P. (1975), Crime, Punishment and Deterrence, New York, Elsevier.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

335

Goel, Rajeev K. and Rich, Daniel P. (1989), ‘On the Economic Incentives for Taking Bribes’, 61 Public Choice, 269-275. Graetz, Michael J., Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1986), ‘The Tax Compliance Game: Toward an Interactive Theory of Law Enforcement’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 1-32. Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1989), ‘Statutes Versus Enforcement: The Case of the Optimal Speed Limit’, 79 American Economic Review, 932-936. Graves, Philip E., Lee, Dwight R. and Sexton, Robert L. (1990), ‘A Note on Drinking, Driving and Enforcement Costs’, 56 Southern Economic Journal, 793-796. Greenberg, Joseph (1984), ‘Avoiding Tax Avoidance: A (Repeated) Game Theoretic Approach’, 32 Journal of Economic Theory, 1-13. Grieson, Ronald E. and Singh, Nirvikar (1990), ‘Regulating Externalities Through Testing’, 41 Journal of Public Economics, 369-387. Grossman, Gene M. and Katz, Michael L. (1983), ‘Plea Bargaining and Social Welfare’, 73 American Economic Review, 749-757. Gyapong, Anthony O. and Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1988), ‘Factor Substitution, Price Elasticity of Factor Demand and Returns to Scale in Police Production: Evidence from Michigan’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 863-878. Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1987), ‘Economies of Scale in Municipal Police Departments: The Case of Florida’, 69 Review of Economics and Statistics, 352-356. Gyimah Brempong, Kwabena (1989), ‘Functional Substitution Among Crimes: Some Evidence’, 15 Eastern Economic Journal, 129-140. Hannan, Timothy H. (1982), ‘Bank Robberies and Bank Security Precautions’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 83-92. Harel, Alon (1994), ‘Efficiency and Fairness in Criminal Law: The Case for a Criminal Law Principle of Comparative Fault’, 82 California Law Review, 1181-1229. Harris, Milton and Raviv, Artur (1978), ‘Some Results on Incentive Contracts with Applications to Education and Employment, Health Insurance, and Law Enforcement’, 68 American Economic Review, 20-30. Hawkins, Gordon (1969), ‘Punishment and Deterrence: The Educative, Moralizing, and Habituative Effects’, 1969 Wisconsin Law Review, 550-565. Hawkins, Keith O. (1982), Environment and Enforcement, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hellman, Daryl A. (1980), The Economics of Crime, New York, St. Martin’s Press. Hellman, Daryl A. and Alper, Neil O. (1990), Economics of Crime: Theory and Practice, Needham Heights, Simon and Schuster, Ginn Press. Henszey, Benjamin N. and Roadarmel, Richard L. (1981), ‘A Comparative Analysis of State Individual Income Tax Enforcement Procedures’, 34 National Tax Journal, 207-216. Hui-Wen, Koo and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Private Security: Deterrent or Diversion?’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 87-101. Hylton, Keith N. (1996), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement and Victim Precaution’, 27 RAND Journal of Economics, 197-206. Jacob, Herbert (1980), ‘Deterrent Effects of Formal and Informal Sanctions’, 2 Law and Policy Quarterly, 61-80. Jones, Carol Adaire (1989), ‘Standard Setting with Incomplete Enforcement Revisited’, 8 Journal of Policy Analysis and Management, 72-87.

336

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Kahan, Dan M. (1997), ‘Social Influence, Social Meaning, and Deterrence’, 83 Virginia Law Review, 349-395. Kambhu, John (1989), ‘Regulatory Standards, Noncompliance and Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Regulatory Economics, 103-114. Kan, Steven S. (1996), ‘Corporal Punishments and Optimal Incapacitation’, 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 121-130. Kaplow, Louis (1990a), ‘A Note on the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions,’ 42 Journal of Public Economics, 245-247. Kaplow, Louis (1990b), ‘Optimal Deterrence, Uninformed Individuals, and Acquiring Information about Whether Acts are Subject to Sanctions’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 93-128. Kaplow, Louis (1990c), ‘Optimal Taxation with Costly Enforcement and Evasion’, 43 Journal of Public Economics, 221-236. Kaplow, Louis (1992), ‘The Optimal Probability and Magnitude of Fines for Acts that Definitely are Undesirable’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-11. Kaplow, Louis (1994), ‘The Value of Accuracy in Adjudication: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, 307-401. Kaplow, Louis (1996), ‘How Tax Complexity and Enforcement Affect the Equity and Efficiency of the Income Tax’, 49 National Tax Journal, 135-149. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994a), ‘Accuracy in the Determination of Liability’, 37 Journal of Law and Economics, 1-15. Kaplow, Louis and Shavell, Steven (1994b), ‘Optimal Law Enforcement with Self-Reporting of Behavior’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 583-606. Karpoff, Jonathan M. and Lott, John R., Jr (1993), ‘The Reputational Penalty Firms Bear from Committing Criminal Fraud’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 757-802. Katyal, Neal Kumar (1997), ‘Deterrence’s Difficulty’, 95 Michigan Law Review, 2385-2476. Keeler, Theodore E. (1994), ‘Highway Safety, Economic Behavior, and Driving Environment’, 84 American Economic Review, 684-693. Keenan, Donald C. and Rubin, Paul H. (1982), ‘Criminal Violations and Civil Violations’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 365-377. Kenkel, Donald S. (1993a), ‘Do Drunk Drivers Pay Their Way? A Note on Optimal Penalties for Drunk Driving’, 12 Journal of Health Economics, 137-149. Kenkel, Donald S. (1993b), ‘Drinking, Driving, and Deterrence: The Effectiveness and Social Costs of Alternative Policies’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 877-913. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985a), ‘Legal Theory and the Economic Analysis of Torts and Crimes’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 905-920. Klevorick, Alvin K. (1985b), ‘On the Economic Theory of Crime’, in Pennock, J. Roland and Chapman, John W. (eds), Nomos XXVII: Criminal Justice, New York, New York University Press, 289-309. Klitgaard, Robert (1988), Controlling Corruption, Berkeley, University of California Press. Knoeber, Charles R. (1978), ‘Penalties and Compensation for Auto Accidents’, 7 Journal of Legal Studies, 263-278. Kobayashi, Bruce H. (1992), ‘Deterrence with Multiple Defendants’,23 RAND Journal of Economics, 507-517.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

337

Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1992), ‘Low-Probability-High-Penalty Enforcement Strategies and the Efficient Operation of the Plea-Bargaining System’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 69-77. Kobayashi, Bruce H. and Lott, John R., Jr (1996), ‘In Defense of Criminal Defense Expenditures and Plea Bargaining’, 16 International Review of Law and Economics, 397-416. Kornhauser, Lewis A. (1982), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Choice Between Enterprise and Personal Liability for Accidents’, 70 California Law Review, 1345-1392. Kraakman, Reinier (1986), ‘Gatekeepers: The Anatomy of a Third-Party Enforcement Strategy’, 2 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 53-104. Kramer, Samuel (1990), ‘An Economic Analysis of Criminal Attempt: Marginal Deterrence and the Optimal Structure of Sanctions’, 81 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 398-417. Landes, William M. (1971), ‘An Economic Analysis of the Courts’, 4 Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1975), ‘The Private Enforcement of Law’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-46. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Landsberger, Michael and Meilijson, Isaac (1982), ‘Incentive Generating State Dependent Penalty System: The Case of Income Tax Evasion’, 19 Journal of Public Economics, 333-352. Lave, Charles A. (1985), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit’, 75 American Economic Review, 1159-1164. Lave, Charles A. (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Reply’, 79 American Economic Review, 926-931. Layton, Allan P. (1983), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behaviour’, 19 Logistics and Transportation Review, 261-266. Layton, Allan P. (1984), ‘The Impact of Increased Penalties on Australian Drink/Driving Behavior - A Procedural Note’, 20 Logistics and Transportation Review, 187-189. Lee, Dwight R. (1983), ‘On Substituting a Socially Costless Penalty for Costly Detection’, 3 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-185. Lee, Dwight R. (1985), ‘Policing Cost, Evasion Cost, and the Optimal Speed Limit’, 52 Southern Economic Journal, 34-45. Leung, Siu Fai (1991), ‘How to Make the Fine Fit the Corporate Crime? An Analysis of Static and Dynamical Optimal Punishment Theories’, 45 Journal of Public Economics, 243-256. Leung, Siu Fai (1995), ‘Dynamic Deterrence Theory’, 62 Economica, 65-87. Levitt, Steven D. (1997a), ‘Private Information as an Explanation for the Use of Jail Sentences Instead of Fines’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 179-192. Levitt, Steven D. (1997b), ‘Using Electoral Cycles in Police Hiring to Estimate the Effect of Police on Crime’, 87 American Economic Review, 270-290. Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming a), ‘Juvenile Crime and Punishment’, Journal of Political Economy. Levitt, Steven D. (forthcoming b), ‘Why do Increased Arrest Rates Appear to Reduce Crime: Deterrence, Incapacitation, or Measurement Error?’, Economic Inquiry.

338

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Levy, David T. and Asch, Peter (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55 MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 913-915. Lewin, Jeff L. and Trumbull, William N. (1990), ‘The Social Value of Crime?’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 271-284. Linder, Stephen H. and McBride, Mark E. (1984), ‘Enforcement Costs and Regulatory Reform: The Agency and Firm Response’, 11 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 327-346. Lott, John R., Jr (1987), ‘Should the Wealthy be Able to “Buy Justice”?’, 95 Journal of Political Economy, 1307-1316. Lott, John R., Jr (1990a), ‘The Effect of Conviction on the Legitimate Income of Criminals’, 34 Economics Letters, 381-385. Lott, John R., Jr (1990b), ‘A Transaction-Costs Explanation for Why the Poor Are More Likely to Commit Crime’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 243-245. Lott, John R., Jr (1991), ‘When Does Learning about a Crime Produce External Benefits?’, The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, Manuscript. Lott, John R., Jr (1992a), ‘An Attempt at Measuring the Total Monetary Penalty from Drug Convictions: The Importance of an Individual’s Reputation’, 21 Journal of Legal Studies, 159-187. Lott, John R., Jr (1992b), ‘Do we Punish High Income Criminals too Heavily?’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 583-608. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1989), ‘Why Comply: One-Sided Enforcement of Price Controls and Victimless Crime Laws’, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, 403-414. Lott, John R., Jr and Roberts, Russell D. (1995), ‘The Expected Penalty for Committing a Crime: An Analysis of Minimum Wage Violations’, 30 Journal of Human Resources, 397-408. Lui, Francis T. (1986), ‘A Dynamic Model of Corruption Deterrence’, 31 Journal of Public Economics, 215-236. Luksetich, William and White, Michael (1982), Crime and Public Policy: An Economic Approach, Boston, Little, Brown. McChesney, Fred S. (1980), ‘On the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1103-1111. McPheters, Lee R. and Stronge, William B. (eds) (1976), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, Springfield, IL, Thomas. Malik, Arun S. (1990), ‘Avoidance, Screening and Optimum Enforcement’, 21 RAND Journal of Economics, 341-353. Malik, Arun S. (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Choice of Policy Instruments for Controlling Pollution’, 30 Economic Inquiry, 714-720. Melumad, Nahum D. and Mookherjee, Dilip (1989), ‘Delegation as Commitment: The Case of Income Tax Audits’, 20 RAND Journal of Economics, 139-163. Miceli, Thomas J. (1991), ‘Optimal Criminal Procedure: Fairness and Deterrence’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 3-10. Miceli, Thomas J. (1994), ‘Prison and Parole: Minimizing the Cost of Non-monetary Sanctions as Deterrents’, 16 Research in Law and Economics, 197-211. Miceli, Thomas J. (1996), ‘Plea Bargaining and Deterrence: An Institutional Approach’, 3 European Journal of Law and Economics, 249-264. Montesquieu, Charles (1748), The Spirit of the Laws, Rept. edn, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1977.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

339

Mookherjee, Dilip (1997), ‘The Economics of Enforcement’, in Bose, Amitava, Rakshit, Mihir and Sinha, Anup (eds), Issues in Economic Theory and Policy, Essays in Honor of Tapas Majumdar, New Delhi, Oxford University Press, 202-249. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, Ivan (1989), ‘Optimal Auditing, Insurance, and Redistribution’, 104 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 399-415. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1990a), ‘Eliminating Corruption: An End in Itself?’, John E. Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics Working Paper No. 90-23. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1990b), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Progressivity of Income Taxes’, 6 Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 411-431. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1992a), ‘Monitoring vis-à-vis Investigation in Enforcement of Law’, 82 American Economic Review, 556-565. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1992b), ‘Rights and Regulations: How and How Much to Enforce?’, John E. Anderson Graduate School of Management at UCLA, Business Economics Working Paper No. 92-1. Mookherjee, Dilip and Png, I.P.L. (1994), ‘Marginal Deterrence in Enforcement of Law’, 102 Journal of Political Economy, 1039-1066. Mookherjee, Dilip, and Png, I.P.L. (1995), ‘Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should they be Compensated?’, 105 Economic Journal, 145-159. Nagin, Daniel and Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘The Effects of Criminality and Conviction on the Labor Market Status of Young British Offenders’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-126. Nash, John (1991), ‘To Make the Punishment Fit the Crime: The Theory and Statistical Estimation of a Multi-Period Optimal Deterrence Model’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-110. Newman, Harry A. and Wright, David W. (1990), ‘Strict Liability in a Principal-Agent Model’, 10 International Review of Law and Economics, 219-231. Ordeshook, Peter C. (1990), ‘Crime and Punishment: Are One-Shot, Two-Person Games Enough?’, 84 American Political Science Review, 573-575. Parker, Jeffrey S. (1989), ‘Criminal Sentencing Policy for Organizations: The Unifying Approach of Optimal Penalties’, 26 American Criminal Law Review, 513-593. Pashigian, B. Peter (1975), ‘On the Control of Crime and Bribery’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 311-326. Png, I.P.L. (1986), ‘Optimal Subsidies and Damages in the Presence of Judicial Error’, 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-105. Png, Ivan P.L. and Zolt, Eric (1989), ‘Efficient Deterrence and the Tax Treatment of Monetary Sanctions’, 9 International Review of Law and Economics, 209-217. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980a), ‘Private versus Public Enforcement of Fines’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 105-127. Polinsky, A. Mitchell (1980b), ‘Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting’, 70 American Economic Review, 363-370. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1988), ‘The Deterrent Effects of Settlements and Trials’, 8 International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1989), ‘A Note on Optimal Public Enforcement with Settlements and Litigation Costs’, 12 Research in Law and Economics, 1-8.

340

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1991), ‘A Model of Optimal Fines for Repeat Offenders’, 46 Journal of Public Economics, 291-306. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1979), ‘The Optimal Tradeoff between the Probability and Magnitude of Fines’, 69 American Economic Review, 880-891. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1984), ‘The Optimal Use of Fines and Imprisonment’, 24 Journal of Public Economics, 89-99. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1991), ‘A Note on Optimal Fines When Wealth Varies Among Individuals’, 81 American Economic Review, 618-621. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘Enforcement Costs and the Optimal Magnitude and Probability of Fines’, 35 Journal of Law and Economics, 133-148. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘Should Employees Be Subject to Fines and Imprisonment Given Existence of Corporate Liability?’, 13 International Review of Law and Economics, 239-257. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1996), ‘Repeat Offenders and the Theory of Deterrence’, John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business, Harvard Law School, Discussion Paper No. 188; John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics, Stanford Law School, Working Paper No. 134. Polinsky, A. Mitchell and Shavell, Steven (1997), ‘On the Disutility and Discounting of Imprisonment and the Theory of Deterrence’, John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics and Business, Harvard Law School, Discussion Paper No. 213; John M. Olin Program in Law and Econ., Stanford Law School, Working Paper No. 146; Forthcoming in Journal of Legal Studies. Posner, Richard A. (1980a), ‘Optimal Sentences for White-Collar Criminals’, 17 American Criminal Law Review, 409-418. Posner, Richard A. (1980b), ‘Retribution and Related Concepts of Punishment’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 71-92. Posner, Richard A. (1985), ‘An Economic Theory of the Criminal Law’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1193-1231. Pyle, David J (1983), The Economics of Crime and Law Enforcement, London, Macmillan. Pyle, D.J. (1995), ‘The Economic Approach to Crime and Punishment’, 6 Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics, 1-22. Rasmusen, Eric (1995), ‘How Optimal Penalties Change with the Amount of Harm’, 15 International Review of Law and Economics, 101-108. Rasmusen, Eric (1996), ‘Stigma and Self-Fulfilling Expectations of Criminality’, 39 Journal of Law and Economics, 519-543. Ray, Subhash C. (1989), ‘Legal Control of Drunken Driving: A Time Series Study of California Data’, 5 International Journal of Forecasting, 515-522. Reder, M.W. (1974), ‘Citizen Rights and the Cost of Law Enforcement’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-455. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1988), ‘Plea Bargaining and Prosecutorial Discretion’, 78 American Economic Review, 713-728. Reinganum, Jennifer F. (1993), ‘The Law Enforcement Process and Criminal Choice’,13 International Review of Law and Economics, 115-134. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1984), ‘An Equilibrium Model of Tax Compliance with a Bayesian Auditor and Some “Honest” Taxpayers’, California Institute of Technology, Social Science Working Paper.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

341

Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1985), ‘Income Tax Compliance in a Principal-Agent Framework’, 26 Journal of Public Economics, 1-18. Reinganum, Jennifer F. and Wilde, Louis L. (1988), ‘A Note on Enforcement Uncertainty and Taxpayer Compliance’, 103 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 793-798. Reynolds, Robert J. (1980), ‘The Economics of Antitrust Enforcement: Theory and Measurement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1121-1130. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1975), ‘The Economics of Corruption’, 4 Journal of Public Economics, 187-203. Rose-Ackerman, Susan (1978), Corruption: A Study in Political Economy, New York, Academic Press. Ross, H. Laurence (1975), ‘The Scandinavian Myth: The Effectiveness of Drinking-and-Driving Legislating in Sweden and Norway’, 4 Journal of Legal Studies, 285-310. Ross, H. Laurence (1977), ‘Deterrence Regained: The Cheshire Constabulary’s “Breathalyser Blitz”’, 6 Journal of Legal Studies, 241-249. Ross, H. Laurence (1984), ‘Social Control Through Deterrence: Drinking-and-Driving Laws’, 10 American Review of Sociology, 21-35. Ross, H. Laurence (1992), ‘The Law and Drunk Driving’, 26 Law and Society Review, 219-230. Ross, H. Laurence and Blumenthal, Murray (1974), ‘Sanctions for the Drinking Driver: An Experimental Study’, 3 Journal of Legal Studies, 53-61. Rottenberg, Simon (ed.) (1973), The Economics of Crime and Punishment, Washington, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research. Rubin, Paul H. and Zwirb, Robert (1987), ‘The Economics of Civil RICO’, 20 U.C. Davis Law Review, 883-912. Rubinstein, Ariel (1979), ‘An Optimal Conviction Policy for Offenses that May Have Been Committed by Accident’, in Brams, S.J., Schotter, A. and Schwödiauer, G. (eds), Applied Game Theory, Wurzburg, Physica-Verlag, 406-413. Rubinstein, Ariel (1980), ‘On an Anomaly of the Deterrent Effect of Punishment’, 6 Economics Letters, 89-94. Russell, Clifford S., Harrington, Winston and Vaughan, William J. (1986), Enforcing Pollution Control Laws, Washington, DC, Resources for the Future. Sah, Raaj K. (1991), ‘Social Osmosis and Patterns of Crime’, 99 Journal of Political Economy , 1272-1295. Schmidt, Peter and Witte, Ann D. (1984), An Economic Analysis of Crime and Justice: Theory, Methods, and Applications, New York, Academic Press. Schroyen, Fred (1997), ‘Pareto Efficient Income Taxation Under Costly Monitoring’, 65 Journal of Public Economics, 343-366. Schwartz, Warren F. (1980), ‘An Overview of the Economics of Antitrust Enforcement’, 68 Georgetown Law Journal, 1075-1102. Scotchmer, Suzanne (1987), ‘Audit Classes and Tax Enforcement Policy’, 77 American Economic Review, 229-233. Scotchmer, Suzanne and Slemrod, Joel (1987), ‘Optimal Obfuscation in Tax Enforcement’, Graduate School of Public Policy, University of California, Berkeley, Working Paper. Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992a), ‘Defining Efficient Sanctions’, in Tietenberg, T.H. (ed.), Innovation in Environmental Policy, Aldershot, Edward Elgar, 53-73.

342

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Segerson, Kathleen and Tietenberg, Tom (1992b), ‘The Structure of Penalties in Environmental Enforcement: An Economic Analysis’, 23 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 179-200. Seidman, Louis Michael (1984), ‘Soldiers, Martyrs, and Criminals: Utilitarian Theory and the Problem of Crime Control’, 94 Yale Law Journal, 315-349. Shapiro, Perry and Votey, Harold L., Jr (1984), ‘Deterrence and Subjective Probabilities of Arrest: Modeling Individual Decisions to Drink and Drive in Sweden’, 18 Law and Society Review, 583-604. Shavell, Steven (1980), ‘Strict Liability versus Negligence’, 9 Journal of Legal Studies, 1-25. Shavell, Steven (1982), ‘On Liability and Insurance’, 13 Bell Journal of Economics, 120-132. Shavell, Steven (1985), ‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 85 Columbia Law Review, 1232-1262. Shavell, Steven (1987a), ‘The Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent’, 77 American Economic Review, 584-592. Shavell, Steven (1987b), ‘A Model of Optimal Incapacitation’, 77 American Economic Review , 107-110. Shavell, Steven (1987c), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. Shavell, Steven (1990), ‘Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts’, 19 Journal of Legal Studies, 435-466. Shavell, Steven (1991a), ‘Individual Precautions to Prevent Theft: Private versus Socially Optimal Behavior’, 11 International Review of Law and Economics, 123-132. Shavell, Steven (1991b), ‘Specific versus General Enforcement of Law’, 99 Journal of Political Economy, 1088-1108. Shavell, Steven (1992), ‘A Note on Marginal Deterrence’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 345-355. Shavell, Steven (1993), ‘The Optimal Structure of Law Enforcement’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 255-287. Shavell, Steven (1997a), ‘The Fundamental Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Use the Legal System’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 575-612. Shavell, Steven (1997b), ‘The Optimal Level of Corporate Liability Given the Limited Ability of Corporations to Penalize Their Employees’, 17 International Review of Law and Economics, 203-213. Shleifer, Andrei and Vishny, Robert W. (1993), ‘Corruption’, 108 Quarterly Journal of Economics, 599-617. Sigman, Hilary (1995), ‘Midnight Dumping: An Empirical Analysis of Illegal Waste Oil Disposal’, Department of Economics, UCLA, Manuscript. Skogh, Göran (1973), ‘A Note on Gary Becker’s “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach”’, 75 Swedish Journal of Economics, 305-311. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982a), ‘A Contractarian Theory of Property Rights and Crime’, 84 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 27-40. Skogh, Göran and Stuart, Charles (1982b), ‘An Economic Analysis of Crime Rates, Punishment, and the Social Consequences of Crime’, 38 Public Choice, 171-179. Slemrod, Joel and Yitzhaki, Shlomo (1987), ‘The Optimal Size of a Tax Collection Agency’, 89 Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 183-192.

8000

Public Enforcement of Law

343

Sloan, Frank A., Reilly, Bridget A. and Schenzler, Christoph M. (1994), ‘Tort Liability versus Other Approaches for Deterring Careless Driving’, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, 53-71. Snyder, Donald (1989), ‘Speeding, Coordination, and the 55-MPH Limit: Comment’, 79 American Economic Review, 922-925. Snyder, Edward A. (1990), ‘The Effect of Higher Criminal Penalties on Antitrust Enforcement’, 33 Journal of Law and Economics, 439-462. Spier, Kathryn E. (1997), ‘A Note on the Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Settle under a Negligence Rule’, 26 Journal of Legal Studies, 613-621. Stigler, George J. (1970), ‘The Optimum Enforcement of Laws’, 78 Journal of Political Economy, 526-536. Swanson, Timothy M. (1991), ‘Enforcement of Environmental Regulation’, in Weigel, Wolfgang (ed.), Economic Analysis of Law - A Collection of Applications, Vienna, Österreichischer Wirtschaftsverlag, 67-78. Sykes, Alan O. (1981), ‘An Efficiency Analysis of Vicarious Liability under the Law of Agency’, 91 Yale Law Journal, 168-206. Tauchen, Helen, Witte, Ann Dryden and Griesinger, Harriet (1994), ‘Criminal Deterrence: Revisiting the Issue with a Birth Cohort’, 76 Review of Economics and Statistics, 399-412. Thurow, Lester (1970), ‘Equity vs. Efficiency in Law Enforcement’, 18 Public Policy, 451-459. Tullock, Gordon (1967), ‘The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft’, 5 Western Economic Review, 224-232. Tullock, Gordon (1969), ‘An Economic Approach to Crime’, 50 Social Science Quarterly, 59-71. Tullock, Gordon (1974), ‘Does Punishment Deter Crime?’, 36 The Public Interest, 103-11. United States Sentencing Commission (1995), Federal Sentencing Guidelines Manual, 1995 Edition, St. Paul, MN, West Publishing. Usher, Dan (1987), ‘Theft as a Paradigm for Departures from Efficiency’, 39 Oxford Economic Papers, 235-252. van den Haag, Ernest (1982), ‘The Criminal Law as a Threat System’, 73 Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 769-785. Veljanovski, C.G. (1982), ‘The Market for Regulatory Enforcement’,Economic Journal, Supplement, 123-129. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1983), ‘Regulatory Enforcement - An Economic Case Study of the British Factory Inspectorate’, 5 Law and Policy Quarterly, 75-96. Veljanovski, Cento G. (1984), ‘The Economics of Regulatory Enforcement’, in Hawkins, Keith and Thomas, John M. (eds), Enforcing Regulation, Boston, Kluwer-Nijhoff, 171-188. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986a), ‘Market Incentives for Criminal Behavior’, in Freeman, Richard B. and Holzer, Harry J. (eds),The Black Youth Employment Crisis, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 301-346. Viscusi, W. Kip (1986b), ‘The Risks and Rewards of Criminal Activity: A Comprehensive Test of Criminal Deterrence’, 4 Journal of Labor Economics, 317-340. Votey, Harold L., Jr (1982), ‘Scandinavian Drinking-Driving Control: Myth or Intuition?’, 11 Journal of Legal Studies, 93-116.

344

Public Enforcement of Law

8000

Votey, Harold L., Jr and Phillips, Llad (1972), ‘Police Effectiveness and the Production Function for Law Enforcement’, 1 Journal of Legal Studies, 423-436. Waldfogel, Joel (1993), ‘Criminal Sentences as Endogenous Taxes: Are They “Just” or “Efficient”?’, 36 Journal of Law and Economics, 139-151. Waldfogel, Joel (1995), ‘Are Fines and Prison Terms Used Efficiently? Evidence on Federal Fraud Offenders’, 38 Journal of Law and Economics, 107-139. Weinblatt, J., Spiegel, Uriel, Hakim, Simon and Ben-Zion, Uri (1983), ‘Crime Prevention Policies and Externalities: A Theoretical Analysis’, 38 Public Finance, 110-131. Wilde, Louis L. (1992), ‘Criminal Choice, Nonmonetary Sanctions, and Marginal Deterrence: A Normative Analysis’, 12 International Review of Law and Economics, 333-344. Wilkinson, James T. (1987), ‘Reducing Drunken Driving: Which Policies are Most Effective?’, 54 Southern Economic Journal, 322-334. Wilson, James Q. (1983), Thinking About Crime, 2nd edn, New York, Basic Books. Wilson, James Q. and Herrnstein, Richard J. (1985), Crime and Human Nature, New York, Simon and Schuster. Witte, Ann D. and Woodbury, Diane F. (1985), ‘The Effect of Tax Laws and Tax Administration on Tax Compliance: The Case of the U.S. Individual Income Tax’, 38 National Tax Journal, 1-14. Yohe, Gary W. (1982), ‘Fines as Economic Incentives - An Alternative Variable Control’, 2 International Review of Law and Economics, 95-109. Zolt, Eric M. (1989), ‘Deterrence via Taxation: A Critical Analysis of Tax Penalty Provisions’, 37 UCLA Law Review, 343-387.

Related Documents