Phenomenological Theory Of Representation

  • August 2019
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Phenomenological Theory Of Representation as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 1,457
  • Pages: 2
Mental Representation and Consciousness. Towards a Phenomenological Theory of Representation and Reference. Source: The Review of Metaphysics Publication Date: 09/01/1995 Author: Sokolowki, Robert One of the major points in Husserl's philosophy is his insistence that consciousness is structured. He denies that consciousness is simply an undifferentiated awareness and that all the differences occur in the content or object of consciousness. He claims that consciousness itself is articulated; it has parts ordered into different kinds of wholes. The most vivid examples of this articulation are found in "representational" forms of consciousness such as remembering or imaging an experience. Let us say that I remember getting into a taxi last evening. My remembering is dual and involves the memorial reenactment of a prior perceptual activity. I "relive," so to speak, myself getting into the taxi yesterday evening, and I do so now, while sitting in a chair in my office. This dual pattern of consciousness, however, this parallelism between my present remembering and my past experience, is entirely focused on one object, on the taxi as being perceived and entered by me. We might put this structure into a simplified notation such as the following: "I {remember [perceiving] (x)}." The symbolism, like that of symbolic logic, would have the advantage of condensing a long verbal analysis into a simple notation and of reminding us of certain important structural elements, such as the fact that although there are two acts, one (the prior perception) nested inside the other (the present remembering), the whole memorial experience has only one target, one (x), the taxi being perceptually entered by me. However, my simplified notation would not take into account all the elements involved in remembering. One would have to add something to symbolize other aspects implied in my present act of remembering, such as the marginal awareness I have of my present surroundings, the awareness I now have of my own bodily condition, the reenacted awareness of the past surroundings and body, and the identification of my own self that occurs within remembering. What Eduard Marbach does in the book under review is to provide a full notation for all the relevant factors in many forms of human consciousness. As in Husserl, the paradigm for conscious structure is taken to be memory and imagination, but Marbach also examines pictorial consciousness and perception itself. In other words, he works mainly with perception and its modifications. He develops an extremely sophisticated notation for these conscious structures. It is too complicated to reproduce in this review, but it is presented as an analogue to the Begriffsschrift that Frege introduced for logical structure. Given the rivalry between Frege and Husserl, and the rivalry between the traditions that emanated from both thinkers, it is highly appropriate to provide such a notation for Husserl. The notation is not focused on logical structure; it is focused on the intentional acts that constitute logical and other structures. There is a great rhetorical advantage in providing such a notation because our somewhat mathematical age is comfortable with mathematical-looking expositions of philosophical doctrines, but the advantage of the notation is not only rhetorical; it also helps us to condense Husserl's philosophical teaching and to be able to see relationships and contrasts that are hard to discern on the basis of verbal descriptions alone. One of the best examples of such clarification is Marbach's demonstration that imaging cannot involve the experience of "inner pictures." The presentational form of imagination is structurally different from the form of viewing pictures, and a comparison of the symbolisms for each bring this out very effectively; Marbach develops this point in debate with the work of Stephen Kosslyn on mental imagery. I should also mention that an important theme brought out in Marbach's notation is the role played by the modes of belief and neutrality in the generation of these various modes of intentionality. Another benefit of providing notation for presentational or intentional forms of consciousness is that this effort will help advance a certain systematization of phenomenological analysis. Husserl always hoped that his philosophy could become expressed as a systematic, ordered whole of description. This goal could never be fully achieved, but some steps toward it could be made by a "catalogue," in symbolic notation, of the descriptions that have been accomplished. The definite contributions of phenomenology would more vividly be presented if they were symbolically collected. Such a presentation would provide a solid platform for further work. Marbach's background prepared him very well for this extremely original effort. He wrote his thesis, which later appeared in Phaenomenologica, on Husserl's concept of the ego, and he edited a volume of Husserliana dedicated to pictorial, memorial, and representational consciousness. He has worked extensively in cognitive science and in the psychology of Piaget, and has empirically studied the development of pictorial consciousness in children. Marbach's own work is very much influenced by an

excellent book by Iso Kern, Idee und Methode der Philosophie, a work that is not nearly enough acknowledged in contemporary continental thought. Marbach's present book comes at a very opportune moment in philosophical controversy. John Searle has recently argued, in The Rediscovery of Mind, that consciousness is irreducible and must be taken into account philosophically, not neglected or eliminated as it has been by much of recent cognitive science; he says that recent philosophy of mind has been sterile because of its neglect of consciousness. Marbach vividly shows how consciousness can be structurally analyzed; we do not have to refer to it merely in global and vague terms. Another author to whom Marbach's work can be related is Gerald Edelman, whose book The Remembered Present bears a title that fits beautifully with Marbach's project and the work of Husserl. I would like to suggest still further avenues of exploration for the work that Marbach has done. First, Marbach gives notations for perception, memory, anticipation, imagination, and pictorial consciousness. These are forms of intentionality that underlie full categorial consciousness. It would be especially important to provide notation for categorial articulation, for the kind of intentionality that constitutes states of affairs and propositions. This level of notation might provide a fruitful link between Husserl and Frege, and would help us understand now categoriality emerges out of precategorial experience. Second, once various forms of intentionality have been symbolized, one can ask about the philosophical differences between this symbolic notation and that of Frege. Does the Husserlian notation allow any sort of inferences? Is there anything analogous to inference in it? Is there anything analogous to contradiction in certain forms and their combinations? Can the notation be used in automation in any way? What benefit would such automation bring? Or is it only an instrument in more purely theoretic explorations? Third, I would suggest that the many ways in which we intend the absent deserves to be codified in notation, a notation that will bring out clearly that we do not need surrogate images when we "emptily" intend something. Fourth, it would be interesting to devise a notation to express the intentionality at work in reading and writing. The role of the notation in "systematizing" Husserl's phenomenology would be shown if we were, for example, to examine the difference between the intentionality at work in reading a text and that involved in looking at a picture. We could simply compare the symbols for each and the differences would spring to light. The systematization would not mean that the various intentional forms are to be derived from certain basic forms as though from axioms; the systematic order of phenomenology is not deductive but interwoven, as one form is seen to blend with or give way to others. Marbach's book is an important milestone in Husserlian studies, because it leads us away from the stale issues that seem to be repeated over and over again in phenomenological work: the problem of the lifeworld, the problem of reduction, the problem of the noema. Husserl's major contributions occurred in his actual descriptions of intentionality; the achievement is in the details. Marbach brings these analyses to the fore with his notation and shows that Husserl's philosophy has made major, specifiable contributions. Husserl did not just wave his hand at intentionality and say that it is a "consciousness of" something; he showed how it is structured, and his analyses have very much to offer to current debates about the mind. Marbach makes these analyses vividly present to us. His edition of Husserl's Phantasie, Bildbewusstsein, Erinnerung is now being translated into English by John Brough, and when the translation appears, the present volume might serve along with it as a major stimulus to detailed and productive advances in phenomenology in the English-speaking world. - Robert Sokolowski, The Catholic University of America COPYRIGHT 1995 Philosophy Education Society, Inc.

Related Documents