Nature Culture

  • Uploaded by: Ross Macleay
  • 0
  • 0
  • April 2020
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Nature Culture as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 167,000
  • Pages: 340
nature culture

nature culture

ross macleay

north bank

North Bank Institute of Independent Studies Published by Ross Macleay, 2005 PO Box 153, Bellingen, NSW 2454, Australia [email protected] Copyright © Ross Macleay 2005 Printed by Griffin Digital National Library of Australia Cataloguing-in-Publication entry: Macleay, Ross, 1954- , Nature culture. Bibliography: Includes index. ISBN 0 9757636 0 1. 1. Restoration ecology – New South Wales – Bellinger Valley 2. Natural history – New South Wales – Bellinger Valley 3. Bellinger Valley (N.S.W.). I. Title. 333.7153

Contents

I

Natural History 1.

1

The Island, The First Time As Tragedy….……..…...…................….3 The fate of a rainforest remnant in the post-colonial lowlands of the Bellinger Valley

2. 3.

Imagining The Pristine………………..…………….......................….11 What was the Bellinger Valley like before 1860, can we know, and does it matter?

Tallowwood Country.….………...…..……………..…..…..................33 The evolution and ecology of the eucalypt forests and rainforests of the Bellinger Valley and eastern Australia

4.

Lantana……………………………………..….……….................…..…85 Portrait of a weed and what it does to the bush infested with it

5.

The Fan…………………………….…………………….....................…95 The restoration of a bit of bush

6.

Belonging And Naming………………………….….............…...........99 One person’s relation to a bit of bush

7.

Ecology………………………………...………………........................103 The ecology of a house in the bush

8. 9.

The Dream; Or Unconscious Nature………….…....................…..117 How society fashions its nature and its image of nature, unaware of itself; and how nature comes back to haunt it.

The Natural History Of Culture.…………………........................…125 A theory of cultural evolution outlined as the basis of understanding the current state of our culture of nature

II The Image of Nature

135

10. Shallow Ecology, Or The Philosophy Of A Science....................137 The science of ecology, its concerns and its limitations

11. Out There In The Community Ecology, Or Natural Resource Managerialism……………………………….................................….167 The contemporary culture of ecosystem management and Landcare

12. The Image Of Nature……………………….……..…….....................185 How nature is represented not only in painting, photography, cinema, TV, national myth, pop culture and environmentalism, but also in national parks and wilderness. 12.1 …in Art......186 12.2 …as The Image of Australia......196 12.3 …as Environmental Issue......203 12.4 …as Environmental Norm......211 12.5 …as Bushfire......220 12.6 …as Nature-in-Itself......231 12.7 …as Sheer Appearance......234

III The Poetics of Nature

241

13. The Nature Critic…………………….………………..................…....243 Nature considered as an object for criticism

14. Natural Beauty………………………………………..................….....255 The aesthetics of nature explained

15. Works Of Nature…………………………………...…........................279 A proposal for an art and a poetics of ecological management

16. The Island, The Second As Farce…………………...…..............…293 The restoration of a rainforest remnant

Selected Source Notes…………………......……....……..............… 314 Bibliography…………………………………...…….........................315 Index…………………………………………..…..................….......323

I Natural History

1

2

1 The Island, The First Time As Tragedy The fate of a rainforest remnant in the post-colonial lowlands of the Bellinger Valley

…to grasp historic being in its utmost historic definition, in the place where it is most historic, as natural being, or to grasp nature, in the place where it seems most deeply, inertly natural, as historic being. —Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics

Let’s just call it The Island. It’s had more than one name: Bellingen Island, Bat Island, Paradise Island and others, official and unofficial. It’s been more than one island: an island in the Bellinger River, sometimes south sometimes north of the main channel; an island in time, the last bit of a fabulous past left behind after the flood of modern history stripped the rest of the lowlands down to grasses and weeds; an exemplary ecological island, a rainforest remnant, alone, adrift and run to ruin in a floodplain of pasture and gardens, 4 or so hectares made for students of the theory of island biogeography; and an island city of grey-headed flying foxes—a Manhattan of bats. It’s even an island that isn’t an island. It only becomes onedividing the Bellinger there at its tidal limitwhen the river rises and floods around it. And when a real flood tops it two or three times a decade, it goes underwater, briefly and altogether ceasing to be. For a day or so it’s a mirage of rainy forest and wet bats moored over the swollen stream Somehow it didn’t just disappear forever in the overflow of history. It was saved, but at a price. Everything had changed and everything had to be worked on now, forever. All through the lowlands, grass had to be slashed or grazed, forever. Weeds had to be controlled, trees had to be planted, forests tended, lawns mown, gardens sown, animals fenced, ferals poisoned, forever. This was the curse. The Island, which had looked after itself for a thousand years, now had to be the work of human labour too, if it was not to fall into utter ruin. It had all been Gumbaynggirr country once. About 1862 huts began to cluster in the new clearings on the south bank of the Bellinger, just below The Island. It was a year after the Premier John Robertson got his Crown Lands

3

Acts through the NSW Parliament, permitting citizens to select, occupy and then purchase the freehold of land out beyond the towns and city. In the late 1840s and 1850s, the Europeans who came to the Bellinger had camped close to the coast on the accessible estuarine reaches, a place to handle and dispatch red cedar logs cut from the brushes on the lower river, and to run a few sheep and cattle. There was conflict with the Gumbaynggirr and at one stage police from the Macleay ordered the cedar getters back to civilisation and safety. Boat Harbour, the new settlement, was a few miles upstream from an older one down on the brackish reach at Fernmount. It was in the middle of the lowlands on a red terrace above the river, as far up from the ocean as down from the junction with the Rosewood at the bottom of the Dorrigo Mountain; as far up as shallow boats could go before shoaling started, and as far downstream as freshwater went. At a certain phase of settlement—before coastal and river travel gave way to road and rail—north coast towns had a habit of falling into such places: Wingham, Wauchope, Kempsey, Bowraville, Grafton. You could look from a ridge in the new clearings and see the escarpment 1000m high to the north and west, a forest tableau of illuminated spurs and plunging brushes changing from morning to evening, from sunlight to stormlight, thrown up steep and high around the lush bowl of the Never Never, the northern tributary that flowed down to meet the Bellinger a few miles upstream from The Island. The never never was beyond the back blocks then, now it’s the North Shore of the Bellinger Valley. A few more miles up into the scrub, above the junction with Rosewood, the course of the Bellinger narrowed into a meander between the upper valley walls, along a floodplain where the small flats lie only on the inside bends. In 1869 a Police Station and Court House were built in Boat Harbour. Afterwards all the main public and commercial buildings in the valley were built there, and moves were made to call the town Bellingen. Bellingen had at first been understood or misunderstood as the Gumbaynggirr name for the river. By the time the town’s new name was official, the river had come to be called the Bellinger. Both names had sprung from a source in Gumbaynggirr and been taken into the current of English usage. The river, taking the inflection of an active player, flowed better with that er ending. Some say the Gumbaynggirr word for the river was Baliijir, others Bundarryuron. The more memory, the more names. Back when the town was founded The Island was a long load of deep alluvium along the southern bank, curved like a huge fish steadying itself against the flow. A dry chute channel, the bearer only of floodwaters, separated it from the town proper, which was on a higher terrace to the south and east. That terrace had been laid down as fresh floodplain 100,000 years earlier and, as the river cut lower, the ancient alluvium had weathered into a bright red soil. The southern chute channel had itself been the course of the river a little over 1000 years ago. During the intervening millennium The Island had been built in layers of sandy silt each time floodwaters lapped out of the main northern channel and spread south. It was a big fresh cake only a thousand years old. 4

Within a generation of the European arrival all the land around it was taken up as freehold and cleared. The Gumbaynggirr tenure, of course, had been spirited away. The Island itself was left with the title of Crown Land. It was flood prone, and it lay in the long risky commonwealth of the river, right there beside the town, a place unwanted but for sundry public uses, like collecting red cedar logs that had been floated downriver for rafting the rest of the way to the mouth. Just before 1900 most of The Island was put up for sale. The story goes that someone thought it had potential as a market garden, but no serious buyers came forward. No one seemed to want to buy an asset that could wash away. People had a good sense that it was just a cake of sandy loam, a delicacy for the appetite of the river. Less than an acre on the upstream end was all that was ever sold. A small patch had already been cleared on the downstream end around about 1885 and it had several feet of soil stripped from it in the next floods. Perhaps the same thing had happened when most of the upstream freehold was cleared. It is now a metre or so below the uncleared public land immediately downstream of it. Through much of the 20th century, people would drive to this clearing from town and park their vehicles there. Meanwhile, weeping willows were planted around the public downstream clearing, and by 1900 the townspeople sought respite there from the hot summer that opened the new century. By intention or the lack of it most of The Island6 acres in the middlemanaged to keep its old brush of lowland rainforest: buttressed white booyongs and giant strangler figs, pepperberries, giant stinging trees, wild persimmons and maiden’s blushes, red cedars, giant water gums, red and yellow carabeens, socketwoods, dark laurels and weeping lilly pillies, bangalow palms and lawyer palms, vines, lianas, ferns and orchids, pothos and giant pepper creeping over the trunks and branches, hanging in long garlands, a high canopy with flocks of birds feeding and caroling way above, fruits falling through the dark foliage down to the soft earth. For those who arrived in the early 1860s the Bellingen country was all dense thick scrub and the only place you could see the sun was on the river bank. Between 1860 and 1890 nearly all the lowland alluvial forests were cleared, except for this last patch on The Island. In 1900, after the attempt to sell it failed, the lower end of the Island was reserved for public recreation and the preservation of native flora. Trustees were appointed. The rainforest that had overwhelmed selectors in the youth of arrival had disappeared by their middle age, too fast for listless social consciousness to register what was happening until after the fact. The Island was the one memento people managed to rescue as the noise of history woke them from the dream of their past; and it was to stand there now next to the town where fate had left it constructed, as monumental as any museum. Already by then, public-spirited people were spending time and money, fencing the western boundary. They were clearing paths across the Island, cutting ramps to the swimming holes, enhancing nature with ornamental trees, and letting the 5

odd beast wander through to tend the undergrowth in a bucolic parkland. It was mooted as a suitable nucleus for Botanic Gardens. All around, new farms were cropping a flush of corn from loam that had cured for a thousand years before the plough revealed it to the sun. They were milking cows, fattening pigs, and sewing green pastures right down to the riverbanks and, with the advent of paspalum around 1900, right back up the ridges under the standing columns of ringbarked gums. Already though, with each flood, the river’s course was changing, and its bed was shoaling as the channel widened and scoured into a shallow stream flowing over gravely beds. And on The Island, those public spirits were already removing lantana and noxious weeds. 70 years later The Island was still a cultural site. Toilets, dressing sheds, paths, footbridges, swings and swimming holes had marked out its meanings on the landscape. Establishing a culture in the process, people had mown lawns, cleared vines, slashed weeds, planted trees, and spent summer days swimming along the river, picnicking along the bank, creating memories. In most of these signs and actions, the sense of it all needing up-keep was implicit. Weeds brought from far away continents were tangling up the edges. Trees were falling, floods were licking out big dollops of soil as soft as wet biscuit, and right from the start, management problemsthe native vines growing in sunny gaps and edges, the vicious barbs of lawyer palm, the hooks of cockspur, the plate-sized leaves of stinging trees, and the chattering flying foxes hanging like gargoyles in the nooks of the canopymust have seemed like signs of nature’s own propensity to fall from grace. Those who liked their nature idyllic and who had a sense of history worked on it according to the time, inclination and methods of their day. They used brush-hooks, axes, slashers, fire, guns and tree planting. On one occasion scores of azaleas were planted to enhance the parkland. Their flowers were to be pastel relief from the serious excess of green. Or at least it is said they were planted; none lasted. What lasted were things like oranges and lemons, camphor laurels, mulberries, privets, jacaranda, coffee, willows, white magnolia, celtis, Madeira vine, Wandering Jew and a few species from other parts of Australia, like lemon-scented gum, silky oak and black bean. It may have been a museum to the primeval forest, but like all museums it was a kind of fantasy, partly an image of paradise, partly a chimera of unreconciled desires and social antagonisms reflecting its own times as much as the past, a fantasy whose conception was only half realised against the relentless forces of time and nature and society. After the floods of 1974, a couple of strangler figs, massive things 50 metres tall and buttressed 10m wide at the base, fell in the middle of the remnant, smashing everything underneath and opening a big sunny gap. Weedy exotic vinesthe chief being Madeira vinegrew over the wrecks. They must have lain across The Island like the rotting carcasses of beached whales. With a bit of help from a fallen river oak and a bulldozer driven by a future mayor—worried about erosion to a mate’s property, or so the story goesthe river changed course around to the chute cut-off on southern side of The Island, where gravel mining had already prepared the way. This became the main channel, a wide 6

shallow reach cutting back during each flood into the living sandy loam of The Island’s high south bank. Meanwhile, under the giant river oaks and weeping lilly pillies on the northern bank, the old swimming holewhere no one had ever touched bottomfell into disuse and silted up. The low footbridge over the river there was swallowed by silt and weeds. Old photos taken from the Red Lead bank on the northern river terrace show kids in mid dive, their feet just leaving the footbridge timbers, their fingers breaking the surface of the clear green water, memories slipping into the past, behind them a lawn and then a wall of jungle edged with planted red poinsettias. Others show half recognizable members of the Society for Growing Australian Plants, the men in grey trousers and white shirts, the women in summer frocks, sitting on rugs and lawn, drinking tea and eating sandwiches and patty cakes. That was before. Now fewer people came to the place, and the old island began to drift out of the present and down the river into memory. It was so little visited by the late 70s that the odd metropolitan settler was tempted to grow a little dope there. One was arrested and got a mention in the Sydney papers. The grey-headed flying foxes, who had long been visiting and camping on The Island, had the place largely to themselves. Haunted by thousands of them, The Island was allowed to disappear into the darker unconscious of the town. Only their humid odour and their dark swarms flying out at dusk reminded people of the place, lying there dying of shame. Most of the old structure became a ruin of rotting columns covered in Madeira vine. It had a kind of monumental grandeur standing up out of an impossible tangle of exotic vines, scrub nettles and cunjevois, but it was the poignant, decaying kind. Under curtains of vine, there was a shell of old, rotting trees surrounding the widening, weedy hole in its heart. Across the ground, a knee-deep carpet of Wandering Jew or a head high sward of palm grass stopped any native seedlings from surviving. Even so, The Island at this stage may have had more plant species than ever. Along with the relics of the past, there was now an astonishing catalogue of subtropical weeds from all around the world: Madeira vine, Wandering Jew, balloon vine, palm grass, mistflower, ageratum, crofton weed, taro, castor oil, celtis, lantana, cape ivy, yellow ginger, wild tobacco, privet, camphor laurel, queen palm, devil’s trumpet, coffee, canna lily, green cestrum, turkey rhubarb, to mention a few. Once a stately museum of the primeval, now a crazy run-down bat palace and weeds-of-the-world theme park. Only a few people still worked on it, a bit like those science fiction survivors of a nuclear war, working to shore up memories among the ruins of their destroyed civilization. They organized the occasional working bee, brush-hooking vinesnative or exoticlighting fires to burn off the aerial tubers on the hanging vines, clearing undergrowth to replant trees. Most called for an end to the bats and the destruction they wrought. The bats were easy targets, defoliating and breaking anything that could still be called canopy, shitting everywhere, panicking, fighting and fuckingnoisy, stinking, rotten batsalways there to blame, these ridiculously inverted parodies of humans.

7

For most people it was easier to ignore the place. After all, like all the north coast towns, Bellingen had always turned its back on the river. It was built to face the other way, onto the main street where the proper business of the everyday was done, and away from the idle stream. Except for a few public places at crossings and swimming holes, all but landowners, cattle and trespassers were cut off from most of the Bellinger. It was hardly a public asset, and landowners and lessees were able to exploit it where need be for water and gravel. And in order to seize and hold every last bit of grassy freehold they would cut down the detested casuarinasthe river oaks that had once grown to such an uncommon size on the Bellinger and sung like harps in the windand they would cut the other trees that grew along the banks too, and then despise the lesser weeds that grew back in their place. For millennia—at least since the flush of wet climate that had followed the last ice age—the river had been flowing through a narrow channel. Usually there was a bank of deposited Holocene floodplain on one side and an older Quaternary terrace or much older Permian bedrock on the other. The riverbank trees were cleared and cattle waded and snacked on the mat rushes that held the toes of the banks and the undermined banks crumbled into the floodwaters and the channel widened with each big flood. Where the flooding river had once lapped over its banks, dissipating its energy and dropping its silt through the floodplain forest, now the widened channel held much more water and in each flood a torrent barrelled down it, ripping it wider and wider. In a hundred years millions of cubic metres of landscape and cadastre went down the river. Where there had once been the odd grand river oak poking out of a gallery of weeping lilly pillies and rainforest, now the oaks colonised the wide gravel beds in droves, several to the square metre, with scarcely room for the rushes and sedges to grow between them, racing to two metres tall in two years and making a 30m open forest in 30. When new floods came, landowners resented the regrowth. It seemed to be holding the gravel beds in the channel and sending turbulence back to eat out their grassy freehold. On high banks they would see the odd old survivor undermined, tipping in and taking a hunk of paddock with it. They hated the things, they fought them where they could, but with little hope of beating them. To wage war against the river oaks was to play into their hands; they were born to rise and prosper in the devastation that the war on the riverbanks created. The river became the most ambiguous bit of local nature. It was the most tormented by the curse that the modern world had brought upon itself and its landscape. It remains a perennial object of desire and the valley’s central symbol both of gratification and purity. Ever flowing, it could promise to each new generation the endless beauty and bounty of natureeven as it decayedbecause its beauty was great enough and its decay slow enough, for each generation, in ignorance of the past, to briefly experience the childish sense that it still flowed the same as ever. As if any river could ever be the same river twice. You could still find a swimming hole, laze like an eel under the weeping lilly pillies, with the fresh of water in your nostrils and the din of 8

cicadas in your ears, still catch a bass or discover a platypus. Hence, even as sorrow welled up for its fading beauty, people would still exploit it with a childish faith in the endless grace that only such beauty could offer. Besides, fading beauty can be the most bewitching, and it had never got quite as seedy as the other north coast rivers. Delusions could arise and flourish, contradictions could seem like the happiest of reconciliationsthe kind that could only flow from the grace of a paradisal stream. Works of exploitation and restoration were deemed to coincide: mining gravel out of the bed was thought to be the obvious way to restore the deep channel; clearing the casuarinas from gravel islands was the way to stop them sending floodwaters back onto eroding banks; cutting trees from the banks was the way to stop them tearing away soil when floods undermined them; grazing cattle right down into the stream was the proper way to control the weeds that so cruelly colonised the cleaned-up banks. Keeping the wound open would heal the sore. It suited people to have a good argument about itthe river was a birthright, and a matter of passion and expertise for everyone. Everyone was a bush hydrologist and aquatic biologist. Everyone was a connoisseur and riverine aesthete, and everyone could reminisce. But the turbulence of antagonistic beliefs and disputed tastes made the unruly society of river politics seem just as wild as riverine nature. Both nature and political culture were too powerful for puny human agency, so apart from the tyranny of piecemeal exploitation and dicky restoration, adult society mostly ended up leaving the river to cattle and kids and to the odd insignificant moments of extra curricula life, while the wild and abundant nature of the river mutated into malignant growth. The Island epitomised the world of the river. There nature erupted into its most weedy and ruined form. There, kids could get away from the parental law and cut down trees, build cubbies, catch snakes. They still do; and they grow dope, litter bongs and discard condoms under the flying foxes. Its many names trace its places in social history: Paradise Island, briefly, for the moment of its circumscribed beauty at the time of the fall; Jarrett Park, arbitrarily, because most places in Australia have been obliged to wear an Anglo-Saxon eponymin this case that of the first white child born in the valley; Bat Island, with attempted drollery, for its gothic ruins; just The Island, in familiarity, for those to whom it is the island; and Bellingen Island, politely, for those for whom it isn’t, or from elsewhere. By the mid 1980s it had become obvious to the experts, that if anything was to be done to save it, it would have to be done fast, it would have to be done big, it would have to be ruthless, it would have to be done with cash and herbicide, and if something wasn’t done immediately it would all be lost. With instructions to investigate the feasibility of returning The Island to parklandsuch was the imagination of the pristinethe Bellingen Shire weed inspector flew over the disaster area in (it was said) the helicopter the police used to find dope growers, and he brought back the expected news from his reconnaissance. Everyone knew. What was the point of doing anything if no one did anything about the bats? They would just 9

destroy whatever you managed to restore. And what was the point if the whole course of the river was left full of the same weeds? They would all just come back in the next flood. What was the point if you did not do everything, everywhere in the catchment? What was the point if you did not do it forever? What was the point of spending a fortune in time and chemicals on such a dump? The best thing to do was bulldoze it all, make a few football fields and return it to parkland.

10

2 Imagining The Pristine What was the Bellinger Valley like before 1860, can we know and does it matter?

…to seize hold of a memory as it flashes up at a moment of danger —Walter Benjamin, Theses on the Philosophy of History.

Like Australia, like everywhere, the Bellinger Valley has been discovered many times. Therefore, its pristine beauty may well have faded before the eyes of beholders, many times, like the past itself. There is the story that long ago a man named Birigundah or Ulitarra came ashore from the direction of the sunrise into the Gumbaynggirr country. He walked through the country north of the Bellinger across to the ranges where he met a woman, strange or perhaps misshapen in her form, whom he called Cowoongamba. She was already here before him, but the story does not tell when she came or what was here before her. Another story survives, telling how a station worker named William Myles and two unnamed sawyers discovered the Bellinger in early 1841. It is now just a story, the barest bones of one.

The sublime surveyor. History, as the telling of what has happened, is the tyranny of what survives. This is all we have to tell us about the other history—history as it actually was. Like Birigundah, the oldest story of this country comes out of the sunrise, from generations of lost voices, crossing a gulf of uncertain comprehension at the end of the 19th century, there to be recorded in the monstrous form of writing, thereafter to survive through the subsequent generations of an anthropological journal and an academic compendium (Ryan, 1988). Arbitrary and fragmented, selected or discarded by generations of retellings, always ripe for reinterpretation, history is never irrevocable.

11

In March 1841 Clement Hodgkinson, the Government Surveyor on the Macleay River, travelled north to the Bellinger Valley with a party that included two unnamed guides from the ‘Tanban tribe’, and William Myles. Cattle, escaped convicts, exotic diseases, shepherds, stockmen or cedar cutters usually went before official surveyors, but the surveyors were commissioned clerks and they documented their deeds. Hodgkinson’s account was published in London in 1845. It is the oldest written description of the Bellinger. On the title page the author declared that the region was first explored and surveyed by him. As a rule, in the thrill of discovery, people seldom remember how unlikely they are to have been the first. Here the forgetfulness was a self-serving and well-known symptom of the unconscious of European Enlightenment. To the state of the land at that moment when western culture made its discovery of the Gumbaynggirr countrythat state now forever lost, but briefly described, and constantly re-imaginedwe latecomers still like to apply the adjective pristine. Cause precedes effect, precedent governs what follows, and in the intimacies of love, ownership, and contract priority claims priority. It rules in logic and causation, ethics and the law, affectively and effectively. For narrative animals like humans, in a world where time has only one direction, what comes first commands attention. It can usefully fascinate us and, in turn, so easily bewitch us. Throughout the history of its use and reuse, the sense of the term pristine has drifted from the Latin meaning former to take on the bewitching connotations of primeval, untouched, unspoiled and perfect. Pristine nature is supposed to be the pure state of nature. Authentic nature. Natural nature. Hodgkinson recorded his very first view of the valley as sublime, the same kind of view that we still expect to experience at lookouts, the kind that Gertrude Stein once said she likedbut would prefer to turn her back on. The view from the range was magnificent. At our feet was the narrow glen of the Bellengen, choked up with dark, impervious brush, whilst immediately opposite us on the north side of the river, a gigantic range rose up in perpendicular buttresses, three thousand feet high, and the total altitude of the range could not be less (judging from analogy) than five thousand feet. Opposite the point we had attained, the outline of this high range was a level table land, but nearer the coast it became broken into an undulating outline of steep, conical summits. Exactly opposite us, in a deep cleft, a beautiful cascade dashed down several hundred feet perpendicular, like a long band of silver, glittering in the rays of the declining sun; to the east we could discern the dim outline of the horizon over the Pacific Ocean; and turning to the west, mountains rose in varied contour, whilst snow-white clouds floated in serpentine wreaths among the narrow glens, and dark mountain recesses. (38-9) Distant mountains, snow-white clouds. Apart from that impervious brush and the Pacific, it could almost be any ranges, anywhere. Height and distance 12

abstract enough detail to make sublime views all much the same. They are less a view of nature than, as Wordsworth advertised, ‘the emblem of a mind sustained by recognitions of transcendent power.’ Sublime sensibility had become a received way of seeing mighty nature as sheer spectacle, at once apprehending the dreadful power of it and feeling the elation of being above it all. In fact it had become a way for exhilarated viewers to get an exalted view of themselves, an ecstatic aid to self-construction. What we get here is Hodgkinson’s reproduction of a generic prose that can scarcely be called his alone. He is able to use the cadences supplied by custom to climb to a lofty selfperception. Sublime experience was all too tempting. It had already become a set piece in the rhetoric of surveyorsand all well before Eugène von Guérard gave us the painted images of what would become its definitive Australian colonial form. Descriptions like this now remind me of Paul Keating’s linethat unless we latecomers woke up there would ‘always be the feeling that we didn’t quite belong, that we’re not serious, that we’re just here for the view.’ Modern society’s first take on the Bellinger signaled the coming usurpation of an old order. What distinguished that pristine world was not in the sublime apprehension but in the detail that Hodgkinson momentarily transcended as he paused there above it all before his descent into the valley. It was some of this difficult detail that his kit of ‘scarlet woolen shirt and light kerseymere trousers doubled in kangaroo leather down the leg (50)’ was designed to keep at baythe ticks, the mosquitoes, the leeches, the stinging trees. And later, with the aid of time and writing and the considered acts of description, depiction and publication, he would rise above it all again. The descriptions in the journal are mundane and conventional. Fascinating in their brevity, their omissions, the familiar arbitrariness of their selection, and their vanished subject matter, rather than in any abundance of extraordinary content, they flicker before us like some old phantasmagoria. Anyone seeking an image of the past pores over them trying to decipher the dream landscape of this discovery, trying to recover the fleeting image of the dream, searching for more meaning. We stare at the text, reduced to gleaning whatever detail we can, hoping to save something of what was here before, and as it actually was. Yet these few fragments of text are almost all we have, like the few remaining fragments of the original floodplain forests. All we seem to save is the precious, melancholy sense that there is nothing left beyond the text. That tableland was the Dorrigo PlateauDundurriga in the Gumbaynggirr language, but according to a white legend, named after a Don Dorrigo, a South American military adventurer who come upon it from the direction of the Great Dividing Range and who was the first to take red cedar from the plateau. Those steep, conical hills were The Dome, McGrath’s Hump, Dibbs Head, Moombil, Goobergooberyam, Roogatargah, Wondurrigah, Tucker’s Knob in the distance, and Coramba, alone and tucked back out of site as the escarpment slides around and down and into the sea from the depths of which the remaining peaks surface here and there as the Solitary Islands. James Cook called the islands 13

that when the Endeavour sailed past in 1770, and he called it a hilly country with the lands near the shore of a considerable height (Evans, 1969). That cascade must be the one on Water Gum Creek at Darkwood dropping down from Mountaintop. The exultant surveyor must have been standing somewhere up on Diehappy Ridge. It’s quite a long way up the valley. Why did Hodgkinson strike out from the Nambucca across all that rough, difficult ridge country to that particular point? When you stand at Mountaintop now and look back over it, ridge after forested ridge ranges back into the hazy distance. Why didn’t Hodgkinson just walk up the sandy beaches and then follow the Bellinger up from its mouth? Grazing land was always an official goal, so he hoped to be able to judge ‘if it were a stream of some importance (27)’ and perhaps come upon some hidden grassy valley amongst all that rugged forest. The route he chose precisely avoided the grassier coastal forests, forests that were kept that way, in parts at least (although this is a moot point) because they were occupied more intensively by the Dunghutti and Gumbaynggirr and fired for hunting, health, thoroughfare, camping and ceremony. Perhaps the coastal route seemed too easy, or already discovered, and as modern adventurers still do, he wanted to create an experience worthy of the words he’d write. Such adventure had to be given an original and sacred purpose: to cross the ranges, to visit the unvisited, to view a promised or undiscovered land, to discover an important river and its source.

Selective quotation How reliable are the words Hodgkinson wrote? On the descent into the valley the party ‘traversed a thicket swarming with fire-flies.’ Fireflies today keep to the calendar. In the valley they first appear on a warm September evening, maybe after a shower of rain. Their winking constellations fill the thickets of nightfall, but these evening shows last no longer than a month. On the cooler plateau the little flashing beetles have their fairy-month in midsummer. Hodgkinson says he saw them in the late summer month of March. Are these the same species of lampyrid beetle that still now light up spring evenings in the forest, members of the genus Atyphella? Has a species become extinct? Are the seasons all changed? Is Hodgkinson elaborating his tale, compounding events from different seasons? What about the ‘pretty bush with crimson flowers’ that Hodgkinson found on his second visit twelve months later. This time he had travelled from the coast, up the estuary to ‘the fresh running stream…as clear as crystal in a narrow bed of large shingles.’ The pretty bush was growing ‘in those parts uncovered by water' (59). Was it a red bottlebrush, a small tree that grows on the gravel benches of some of the other coastal rivers, and that is now a standard native plant of Australian gardens? Nowadays I doubt if they or any other pretty bush with crimson flowers grows wild on the Bellinger. Although I

14

have seen one flowerless candidate near the Never Never junction, cropped low by cattle almost beyond recognition, I wonder whether they ever did. And how reliable are words like Hodgkinson’s when others select them? Like the landscape itself, the modern imagination of the pristine is a battle of interpretations. How pristine is pristine? Before the whites? Before the Gumbaynggirr? Before fire and eucalypts? Before the break up of Gondwana? Was Australia in 1788 a landscape of big well-spaced trees in open forests and grassy woodlands, tended and kept clear by Aboriginal burning? Did the impenetrable forests of the east coast come up after the big old timber was logged or cleared and the land was abandoned to European mismanagement? Could you ride your horse through it all at a canter? In the contest to describe pristine Australia the running has been made by two main versions: grassy forest and dense treesprobably because social conflict induces arguments that line themselves up on one of two sides. If you hint at agreement with one claim of one side, the other side will line you up on it to attack you. Behind this battle loom different ideologies of land management, and especially one big question: to burn or not to burn. In a recent battle over the pristine Benson and Redpath (1997) boxed quote for quote with Ryan, Ryan and Starr (1995) taking a few swipes at Tim Flannery (1994) as they went. Implicated in or drawn into this dispute are the credentials of green and anti-green ideologies. Literary writers on Australian nature like Eric Rolls (1981) and Les Murray (1997) have favoured the open forest story. They say the dense forests of the east coast only came up after the Kooris were dispossessed. Behind this question about whether to burn or not to burn there is another (for some) bigger one: how untouched was the Aboriginal landscape? Did Aboriginal people transform the landscape with fire? Had their forebears migrated to Australia and burnt out the habitat of the ancient megafauna and hunted them to extinction? These questions go right to the notion of unhusbanded terra nullius. They seem to threaten the modern notions of wilderness. Is wilderness just terra nullius for greens? Was the pristine landscape a great culturescape whose continuous transformation at human hands now licenses the transformations of industrial agriculture against the preciousness of greens? These days almost no one knows a wet grassy forest on the east coast because so many of the moist eucalypt forests are choked by lantana, or by introductions from East Asiathe privets and camphor laurels that come up in thickets on formerly cleared ground. And where there were brushes of rainforest or open forests of eucalypts on the alluvial flats, there are now agricultural grasslands. Get rid of the lantana though, and the tall moist eucalypt forests that grow in the ridge and gully country surrounding the Bellinger floodplain start to look a bit like some of the places in Hodgkinson’s description. They become accessible. Even without traditional burning, the floor is often covered with dwarf panic and basket grasses, blady grass and ground ferns. This is pronounced on the ridges and as you descend into the gullies where the soil moisture persists, understorey trees and shrubs, and then 15

rainforest trees, shrubs and vines become denser. When it’s not snagged up with lantana there is a structured understorey of red ash, blackwood, cheese tree, native laurels and myrtles, palms, native grape vines, giant raspberries and prickly sarsaparilla. It’s easy to quote Hodgkinson to make it seem that the pristine vegetation was grassy foresteven in the Bellinger valley: ‘We found ourselves on a beautiful grassy forest bank, overlooking the river Bellingen' (39). As Hodgkinson ascends the upper Bellinger he describes The small clear plains, covered exclusively with coarse broad-bladed grass, growing as high as a man’s middle, and having the appearance of small wheat fields; the grassy forest flats were principally wooded by that species of eucalyptus called Forest Mahogany. I halted for the night on a grassy flat on the brink of the Bellingen. (40) This sounds like blady grassImperator cylindricaa fire tended species that grows throughout subtropical and tropical Australia and Asia. It follows slash and burn farmers around, taking over old gardens. Its underground rhizomes are sweet with stored sugars. Burning it would flush out sheltering reptiles, and bandicootsthe small marsupial that sneaks up and steals the campfire in a Gumbaynggirr story. Afterwards the rhizomes send up green shoots, and a rough salad of woody seedlings sprouts that attracts red-necked pademelons and swamp wallabies out of the brush to browse the glade at dawn and dusk. Hodgkinson’s eucalypts sound like tallowwoods or maybe white or red mahoganies. There is no mention here of dense undergrowth or prickly raspberry, or climbing lawyer palms and sarsaparilla vines. A few days later, on his way back to the Macleay, Hodgkinson describes …the steep slopes of the range we were upon, the dazzling whiteness of the branches, and the upper parts of the trunks of the huge blackbutt trees, and the grassy slopes bathed in mellow moonlight… (44) On his second visit, this time down on the Bellinger estuary somewhere near where the Pacific Highway now crosses it, he writes I struck across the country to the northward, and arrived on the main branch of the Bellengen, exactly opposite a verdant plain of very pleasant aspect, about 200 acres in extent, covered with broad bladed grass and high reeds. (56) And from a vantage looking further north: The high range, dividing the Bellengen and the Clarence river, throws off, near the mouth of the former, a low range of hills, extending along 16

the coast, and which continued past the Solitary islands. The country between these hills and the sea appeared to be grassy forest land. (65) This must be where Bongil Bongil National Park now is. A place then where old growth eucalypts dominated everything elseexcept perhaps in the moister rainforest gullies or where trees had fallen. Or so it seems from the cursory descriptions. Between 1870 and 1916 the best timber was cut outall the straight logs without barrels up the middle hollowed out by termites or fires, the legacy of centuries. By the time the Forestry Commission was established in 1916, Pine Creek was regarded as cut-out’. Under new management, foresters went through the bush highgrading it by ringbarking all the gnarled, hollowed over-mature trees that were suppressing younger, straighter, regrowth. Those trees were also providing nesting places for greater gliders, yellow-bellied gliders, sugar gliders, quolls, possums, owls, parrots, cockatoos, and tree creepers. Then came the big cuts of the Second World War, the plantations of the 1950s and 60s, the battle for Bongil Bongil in the golf course and resort bubble of the 80s, and the koala wars of the 90s. Now it’s a place sometimes choked with lantana, sometimes a clear run of blady grass and soft ground fern and gristle ferns under blackbutts, sometimes red ash gully rainforest and flooded gums and tallowwood, sometimes hoop pines on Pine Creek, sometimes foredunes of coast banksias loud with Little Wattle Birds, sometimes dense littoral rainforest of tuckeroos and riberries, sometimes paperbark and swamp mahogany forest on coastal creeks and lagoons, running all the way through the coastal foothills from Urunga to Bundagen to Muttonbird Island, the most southerly of the Solitaries. The breeding home to thousands of wedgetailed shearwaters, Giidayn Miiral is Muttonbird’s Gumbaynggirr name. Its pregnant lens of black rock is mantled green with kangaroo grass, red-flowered coral pea and blue-flowered commelina, succulent and bright and fertilized by the bird shit. The island used to be a few hundred metres offshore, cradled by a bay that curved north from a headland called Garrambila or Corambirra. Garrambila looked at Giiday Miiral across blue water and imitated the rounded mass of its partner. Now there’s no longer an island. It’s at the end of the Coffs Harbour breakwall, an umbilicus of rock gutted from Garrambila and thrown out straight from the beach. At the same time, from the broken carcass of Garrambila itself, what the poet Robert Gray calls another rough intestine of stone was drawn forth by the quarriers, only to fall short of the island. It is the southern wall of the harbour. It goes nowhere. When James Cook and his crew passed the Solitaries, they steered along the shore all night 3 leagues from shore, having advantage of the moon. Giidayn Miiral had long been a revered place where the crippled Moon, covered in sores and carried by his people, bathed before dying and being buried. The moon rose again, waxed and waned and only men could go out there to gather the gibbous eggs of the shearwaters from their burrows among the tufts of grass.

17

People like grass. They tend their grasslands with fire for hunting, their pasture with their cattle or slashers, their lawn with mowers. The Aborigines, it is said, kept many a forest and woodland grassy. In the service of grass they burnt along their thoroughfares on the coastal plains, river flats and along travelled ridges leading up to the escarpment, broadcasting fire in their travels and shaping the bush to their economic and ceremonial ends. They burnt grassy headlands for vantage points, grassy forests for hunting, burrawang groves for fruiting, campsites for protection and ceremony. It was the Wintarn people of the new, green blady grass who took compassion on the disembowelled Moon and carried him to his gunyah. Surveyors like Hodgkinson had an eye for the grass and sought it out. And nowadays most of what used to be the forested floor of the Bellinger valley is grassland. People wanted it that way, and put a lot of work into it. They still do. They have to. It takes a touch of sublime transcendence, a little aesthetic distance, to fancy the dark romantic brushes with the leeches and ticks and giant stinging trees. The brushes were what Hodgkinson had to get away from before he could turn them into subject matter in his adventurer’s tale. Nowadays, few could endure the psychic effort needed to like or ignore the weedy scrub that colonizes neglected pastures on the floodplain. Few could endure the social stigma of letting it all go and turn into rubbish. A ‘beautiful grassy forest bank overlooking the Bellinger’probably made and tended by the Gumbaynggirr and the native herbivoresis a place where Hodgkinson’s party could simply find themselves, as if on a spiritual quest. Where they see grass, people take comfort in it. They find words or words find them. Leaning and loafing back on it, Walt Whitman called grass the flag of his disposition. The Europeans had the whole of the pastoral tradition back to Virgil and Theocritus and beyond from which to draw pleasant associations. And on hearing the news that that they would be returning home to Tanban, Hodgkinson’s Dunghutti guides ‘indulged for two or three hours in loud singing as they lay extended on the grass' (43). These passages about grass are selective quotation. The images of grassy Aboriginal forests and woodlands are retrospeculation. Historical accounts are always selections, and what gets selected is not simply a matter of the writer’s authority. The author’s dedication to truth notwithstanding, selection can go on over his or her head. In the battle to imagine the pristine, the comforts and profits of grass always had a habit of colonizing the colonial imagination. But romantic sensibility and the sublime aesthetic had also colonized the European imagination. A stage in modernity’s aesthetic self-formation, they had defined themselves precisely in antagonism to the older pastoral aesthetic comforts. For Immanuel Kant it was a matter of ethical self-formation: sublime transcendence was primarily a matter of self-transcendence. Years before, Edmund Burke had already theorized and sanctioned its place in English culture. From Hodgkinson’s journal, by which time Romanticism and Enlightenment had become official culture, we can easily fill in the ‘luxuriant vegetation’, the dense rainforest ‘brushes’, and the undergrowth that selective quotation can clear away. In a drawing of ‘Natives spearing fish in the Bellengen River’ 18

Hodgkinson shows a luxuriant, quasi-tropical lagoon. In the foreground, beside a group of Gumbaynggirr fishermen, bangalow palms arch over giant flowering spider lilies. Across the estuary, in the middle ground blackbutts climb above littoral rainforest and mangroves. A little further away grassy woodland runs up a slope. You can see the shadows of the individual trees there thrown over the broad open ground. And in the background conical peaks loom out of the mist, a multiplication of the single cone of Nunguu Miiral, looking all too much like a range of volcanoes. The hair of the men, tied in plumes on top of their heads emulates the artifice of those peaks or the extravagance the palm fronds. It’s a European vision of the South Pacific. Just how much is matter of fact, how much artifice, how much romance, how much an artifact of faltering execution, it is difficult to say. As a whole it is a picturesque combination, but it is a combination of certain matters of fact, of brushes and grasslands, of estuarine foreground and rugged background. Most of the contemporary citations that I have read from Hodgkinson seem to be selected as testimony to the rainforest of the pristine Bellinger Valley. You come across them in local histories and environmentalist documents. Sure, they are traces of romantic sentiment. Searches for the pristine or the past as it actually was—forested, grassy or whatever—seldom avoid that. In 1912, a generation or more after the fact, the District Forester, E.H.F. Swain estimated ‘the area of the original softwood brushes of the Bellinger River was probably something like 60,000 acres of the richest soils of the whole 300,000acres of the watershed' (8). The rainforest romance is rooted in fact. Hodgkinson himself wrote: In the brushes here [on the southern Kalang arm of the Bellinger] I saw the finest cedar and rosewood I had yet noticed; I also saw several creeping plants, climbing among the trees, which were quite new to me. (37) Or, from the main arm of the river: In a straight line of ten miles, we crossed and recrossed the river no less than twelve times; this was unavoidable on account of the steep, inaccessible forest banks, which formed tangents to the convex bends of the river on either side. Our course, therefore, lay from necessity along the alluvial land, which consisted of brush, cedar plains and forest flats. The brush contained the finest cedar and Rosewood I have ever seen; the trunks of these trees were often six feet in diameter, and ninety feet high, before they threw out a single branch. (40) This is the most common image of the pristine on the Bellinger—a place of rainforest brushes and big timber, of Red Cedars and Rosewoods. I note that, just as in the latest Macquarie Dictionary, there is no mention of booyongs. Buttressed white booyongs would probably have been a typical tree in the 19

floodplain rainforests. With deep red-brown timber, strong, heavy and straight grained, they were sometimes called ironwoods or stavewoods. Slow growing denizens of mature, complex forests, with their silver trifoliate leaves and plump fruits winged with platinum foils, they still grow on Bellingen Island— they dominate the place—and on some little protected flats up on the Rosewood River, but they have been wiped out on the nearly all the floodplains now, and with that, they’ve gone from the Australian vocabularyalong with socketwoods, carabeens, red beans, cudgeries, muskwoods and pepperberries. As the symbols of a legendary, plundered wealth, it is only the red cedars (Toona ciliata) that prevail. Many think they are rare these days, standing in name alone. However these close relatives of the Indian toon grow throughout warm rainforests from the NSW south coast to Indonesia. Certainly big ones are scarce. The cedar and rosewood grew to a very great size on the banks of the Bellengen; the red cedar, (Cedrela toona,) was remarkably tall and straight, for this kind of tree is in general more gnarled than the common Australian trees. One cedar, which was lying prostrate, was measured by my men, and its straight trunk was found to be eighty feet in length before it threw out a single branch. (58) Since the fall from the pristine, the age of giants has passed. You can still find a rare old grove hidden away on some creek above the upper Bellinger, protected by terrain, secrecy or honour. However the red cedar tip moth, Hypsipyla robusta, can now manage to find all the Bellinger seedlings. Its caterpillar eats out the growing shoots, making that ‘gnarled form’ the norm in most places cedars now grow or are grown. Among the few giants that remain from the old floodplain forests are the strangler figs. There are several kindssmall-leaved, black, deciduous, Port Jackson, and Moreton Bay. Each has its funereal foliage, the Moreton Bay’s brushing back light and rusty in a breeze. They became a standard in early colonial horticulture. Sydney’s parklands are still full of them. Old farms on the Bellinger often still have one somewhere, the branches cropped to cattle height, throwing a wide deep shade. In the forest they start life as epiphytes in high branches and drop roots to the ground like big cello strings against the bole of the host tree. Eventually the strings filigree into a network, they thicken, and then they enclose the host. Because they grow from the top down, those planted in the open or those that have sprouted on cut tree stumps tend to have shorter trunks supporting their broad crowns. They grow fast, so most of those on the floodplain now have probably grown on stumps since the valley was cleared, but a few relics remain toothe tallest ones. There are still a few of them looking down over the little patch of rainforest on The Island, unsteady on their tilting or rotting trunks. Hodgkinson describes Moreton Bay stranglers on the Nambucca.

20

The enormous fig-tree was very common here; the fruit was now ripe, and scattered in great quantities on the ground. We ate plentifully of these figs, as their flavour was agreeable enough, being of an acid sweetness. Large numbers of the crested flock pigeon were feeding on this fruit. (33) And along with flying foxes, fig birds, bower birds, parrots, pigeons, doves, honeyeaters, possums, lizards, fruit-fly, you name it, they still do—although nowadays you usually see the flocks of topknot pigeons feeding in the camphor laurels that have come up as weeds wherever the cleared land has been neglected. Nowadays few people would dream of eating the seedy fruit of wild figs. The sweet maggoty flesh ferments on the ground. And as far as the banality of contemporary horticulture is concerned, figs are now just too preposterous. With their big, buttressed bases, wide branches, vast greedy roots, great height, and soft wood, they crack open drains, lift foundations, swallow up backyards, and drop limbs on cars and children. And that ferment of fruit and fauna is all too much. Some other surviving floodplain giants go unseen because they go against legend. Like selective quotations, many an oral landscape myth has been selected to imagine the pristine in a convenient ideological form. On the Bellinger today, and on the other nearby coastal rivers, it is solemnly held that the casuarinas or river oaks are not native to the area. Rural myth has denied this species the prestige and authenticity of the pristine or the nativeit’s tantamount to saying it’s just another weed. I have even read Landcare literature that calls them weeds. The pressures for this process have been strong. Many despise these trees. They could only belong to a world after the fall. Since the clearing and erosion of the floodplain, they have successively colonized riverbanks and gravel benches left raw by flooding. They are seen as redirecting floodwaters away from the channel that they have colonized and against adjacent, privately owned banks. When they become big trees they can topple and rip out hunks of alluvial land, reminding people of a wild and changing nature that defies cadastral order and the inalienable rights of property. Yet Hodgkinson saw them there in the Gumbaynggirr country where he first came upon the Bellinger. He marveled at them. Like so many things in the land of former times they were giants. The Casuarina also grew to such an uncommon height, and its foliage assumed such an unusual form, that I thought at one time it was a species of pine. (40) The next day he saw ‘narrow, lightly wooded flats, with patches of Swamp oak (Casuarina paludosa) growing among the shingles of the stream' (41). He and his contemporaries merged swamp oak and river oak into one species. Despite pine-like forms, the name oak was applied because of the oak-like grain of the timber. Neither oak nor pine, the casuarinas are Casuarinas for the way 21

their fine branchlets hang like the feathers of cassowaries. Sometimes casuarinas are called she-oaks to distinguish them from the venerable patriarch of European timbers. Swamp oak (now called Casuarina glauca) grows on the estuaries. River oak, Casuarina cunninghamiana, grows upstream on the fresh water reaches. Hybrids grow where it is brackish and the two species overlap. There are still a few of the old river giants standing on the banks of the Bellinger and the Never Never. The river oaks are a bit like other elements of the pristine that selective social consciousness has liked to erase. The image of the past must pass through the filter of ideology. In so many historical accounts of eastern Australia, the two great categories might be brush and grassy forest, but this is itself an image filtered into the black and white of an enduring ideological antagonism. There to be noticed in Hodgkinson is the record of a mosaic of vegetation types, even though the simple contrast is also implicit in Hodgkinson’s own interpretation: for his horses, for his camps, for thoroughfare, and for agriculture, Hodgkinson sought out the grass; the brush and everything else was to be endured. But then that everything else that is endured is eminently suitable for embellishing his explorer’s journal. On the other side of the Algomerra, we entered a dense brush, which continued unbroken for several miles. Here we had to dismount, and assist the blacks in cutting a passage for our horses through the masses of briers and creepers, that bound the trees together. On emerging from this brush, we continued crossing a never-ending succession of densely wooded ranges, and brushy gullies, containing small gravelly water-courses, and at length reached one of the main streams flowing into the Nambucca. It was about one hundred feet wide here, being a limpid, shallow stream, with a gravelly bed. On entering the brush bordering on this river, we experienced considerable annoyance from the great quantity of nettletree saplings. My hands and arms soon ached from the poisonous touch of its leaves, and our horses suffered very much; one of them threw himself on the ground, snorting convulsively with pain. The nettle tree attains a very large size at the Macleay and the Nambucca, being often six feet in diameter, and of a corresponding height; its wood is very soft and spongy, and its leaves, which are of great size, resemble in shape the leaves of a mulberry, and at the same time possess the bright green velvet appearance of a geranium leaf. The slightest touch of one of these leaves occasions a most acute stinging pain; but horses suffer infinitely worse than men from contact from the leaves of the nettle-tree, as their skin rises in large blisters, and great temporary constitutional derangement seems to take place. Our blacks killed a large carpet-serpent near here, which was carefully preserved for their repast. (29-30)

22

Our course now lay along the rapidly ascending bed of this torrent for some distance, until masses of fallen trees, choked together in one inextricable mass, forced us once more to enter the brush. We found it so dense that we were obliged to cut every yard of our way; night was coming on, and to increase our discomfort, it began to rain heavily. The brush-leeches, issuing forth from the dank rotting leaves, soon attacked the calves of our legs; at length we got into more open brush, and finally reached the forest on the narrow spur we were ascending. Dwarf palms, and ferns, however usurped the place of grass; it was now night, but still indispensable that we should reach a place where grass was to be had. (35) Hodgkinson saw little of agricultural value in the place. The ecological complexity was all too much noise for agricultural design to simplify. He frequently refers to the inutility for agriculture, ‘being nothing but alluvial brush land, or heavily timbered abrupt mountains' (60). Before you could get anywhere you would have to go back to a clean slate. If agriculture were sufficiently profitable in New South Wales to cover the expenses of clearing land of heavy brushes, the rich narrow glen of the Bellengen, might in that case be highly available, especially if rice, cotton, tobacco &c. were the objects of cultivation. (70) Agricultural designs had driven the colony west across the Blue Mountains into the grassy woodlands of the western slopes. In many cases the graziers just followed the paths blazed by the wandering cattle themselves. Along the north coast from Port Macquarie to Moreton Bay, it was the cedar getters who first cut their way like miners into the brushes of the dark valleys. Just before he left the north coast, Hodgkinson heard that cedar dealers had got a boat over the Bellinger bar, and sawyers had gone over from the Nambucca to cut cedar. Hodgkinson himself went on to become Assistant Commissioner of Lands in Victoria where in 1866 he set up the first state forests. In less than a century, the great alluvial brushes and the forested ridges of the Bellinger had been logged of their cedars and cleared for farming. Never cultivated for rice, cotton or tobacco, they were cropped for maize, grazed by cattle, scoured by floods, and, having proven to be of dubious agricultural utility after all, forsaken to forest regrowth, subtropical weeds, hobby-farm beef cattle, and a late twentieth century metropolitan diaspora.

Re, re, re, re, Restoration of landscapes, regeneration of vegetation, rehabilitation of rivers, re-establishment of wildlifein the modern culture of nature, the end of 23

each undertaking is imagined, almost without hesitation, as a return to some imagined pristine state of nature, some paradise lost. Otherwise whatever is still sort of pristine is locked up in a reserve. Such is the norm that defines the poetics of nature. It exerts a force that binds scientists, environmentalists, technocrats, managers, engineers, and community volunteers against the centripetal force of their otherwise relentless specialization. Even when I read restoration ecologists getting circumspect about the pristine and talking about ecosystem condition and function instead, I sense they are still benchmarking their condition and function with the pristine. Strange that the technocratic, managerial society of nature suffers this epidemic melancholia. Nostalgic for the past and the natural, it indulges its furtive aesthetic unconsciously under the guise of functional ecosystem management. This is perhaps an understandable ploy—given that loggers, land clearers and so called developers seem to use the concept pristine even more often now than environmentalists, but in negative formulations to assert the fallen state of whatever bit of regrowth they want to exploit. At a seminar on wetland management a thoughtful participant diagnosed the nostalgia for the pristine before suggesting that we should not be trying to restore wetlands as they used to be; we should be creating them anew. The response to such a notion though is that complexes of co-evolved species fit and work together, but that made-up complexes are unlikely to. It is with good reason that instrumental ecologyand ecology is always an instrumental sciencelooks to the past as it actually was in order to create the future. Walter Benjamin once said that recognizing the past ‘as it actually was…means to seize hold of a memory as it flashes up at a moment of danger' (1970, 257).

Palimpsest The past is always just an image of the past. Little that is empirical is left in historythat is, little that anyone can witness again for themselvesother than the surviving documents. Until there were durable linguistic documents there were only words written in air. History as we now know it and as opposed to its older sister myth could not get properly started. But, of course, there have long been other non-written signs that have more or less enduredall documents in their own way. Things like images in stone or wood or pigment, and the tools of everyday lifethe more durable forms of what anthropologists call material culture. Even the words of oral poetry were made in such a way that they endured by using the pleasing mnemonic technologies of song and prosody to make myth more than just the ephemeral, spoken word. And then there was landscape. To those who can read it, landscape is a catalogue of stories and concepts. The comings and goings of oceans, volcanoes, glaciers, tsunamis, rivers, the works and relics of ancestors, the scares of war and agriculture and industry, lines of travel and transport, the style and locations of camps, towns and cities, the distribution of wealth. We have always needed to write our memories onto 24

the stuff of landscape because there was never enough room in our brains; but it is not just a case of landscape and memory. It is landscape and memory, myth, lore, history and science. Everywhere places have their portion of spirit and eventfulness: here Birigundah met Coowoongamba, there, at the head of navigation, the town of Bellingen appeared, this hill was once one of Birigun’s yams, that is an unknown grave. Every bend in a road or river, every house in a street, every hole in the ground, every tree, every blade of grass tells something to someone. In Australia the whole melancholy landscape looks like a battlefield where wars have been fought between industrial agriculture and the Aboriginal country, between conservationists and exploiters, between fire and rain, eucalypts and rainforest, grass and trees, pasture and bush, native vegetation and exotic weeds, nature and culture. Yet somehow modern society has an extraordinary capacity to forget itself or hide from itself. It has an unconscious like Freud’s Wolfman. People are astonishingly practiced in not seeing this great battlefield, yet it is as stark as the line the highway cuts through the bush, deep into the geological strata. People think that only Aboriginal society sings and recites its landscape, but all societies do thisalthough perhaps more prosaically. Aboriginal landscape culture should remind us of what is universal in cultures: Humans store information in their surroundings. They can remember more then. The classical rhetoricians didn’t invent the technique of memorizing things by associating them with places and images. They just developed their own formalized art of memory by working with the kind of memory nature bequeathed humans. When people find out about the riches of traditional Aboriginal landscape culture, the landscape culture of modern societyalready an unapprehended default settingslips further from recognition. At best it is understood as modern society’s functional division of the landthat is town, that city, that bit is rural, that bit forest, that bit national parkbut uncomprehendingly this is not taken as a story signified in landscape. It is just the present and ‘planning’ and given. Perhaps there is a kind of repression going on here, as if people cannot bear to contemplate the atrocities and vandalism wrought by the society they think of as theirs. Or perhaps the functional differentiation of post colonial life has alienated landscape from us latecomers by voiding it of dreaming and allowing it only the most profanely functionalist of functions, one of which, namely recreation and tourism, must impossibly bear the burden of surrogate for sensed lost meaning. When European monks were copying manuscripts in the Middle Ages, they sometimes took an existing manuscript, erased it and then reused the erased parchment to write a new text. The new text was called a palimpsest. In a landscape, stories are erased and written over with new stories. In Australia the palimpsest of modern society has been written over great swathes of the traditional landscape. Even where a bit of the old meaning remains it has often been translated into a modern idiom. What has been lost? Fascinated and frustrated by this question, modern society falls into answering it obsessively with its imagination of the pristine. The pristine, however, is not to be 25

understood primarily as referring to untouched nature. That is a secondary and partisan meaning, one that has often prevailed in the battle over the imagination of the pristine and been grafted on by the romantic evaluation of extra-human nature, and one therefore that may well be in cahoots with the colonial convenience of terra nullius. So as well as the written text there is landscape. It is mundane and conventional. By virtue of the familiar arbitrariness of its selection, it reads now like a phantasmagoria of mute damaged nature. We pore over it trying to decipher the dream landscape of the pristine, searching for more meaning, hoping to save something of what was here before and as it actually was. All we seem to save though is a sense of melancholyespecially since the linguistic culture that would give it words in which to speak and reveal its historical character as a catalogue of stories and concepts has by now been almost completely silenced.

Natural justice For the colonists, the place was fallen right from the start. If it wasn’t the difficult terrain and the brush, there was the melancholy truthto be put out of mind if at all possiblethat there was another people living in this place. The coastal Aborigines were friendly to Hodgkinson, but he did not meet anyone at all up in the valley. On his second visit in 1842, he left the coast and started to go up the Bellinger again. As well as being accompanied by guides from Yarrahapinni, a local coastal man nicknamed Bellengen Billy took the opportunity to join the party. Only a day’s walk above the tidal limit, and still well downstream of where he had reached the previous year, the surveyor struck a problem. The guides, who were well out of their country, and the coastal man who could hardly have left his, pressed Hodgkinson to turn the expedition around and head home. They had seen fresh tracks and were worried about the hostile intentions of people who had come down from the Dorrigo plateau. There might not have been any Aborigines who spent most of their time in the deep steamy valley. It seems to have been a wildish place secluded between the coast and the plateau, perhaps a place for thoroughfare, seasonal uses or ceremonial visits. There are still stories that the Kooris called it sickness country, but I have only heard them from white, metropolitan immigrants of the 1970s who, new to living in the bush, seemed to suffer more than their share of infected sores and diarrhoea. Whatever its origin—black or white dreaming— the story explained the authentic trauma of the sores and diarrhoea. It could be used to complain about one’s lot while ignoring hygiene or avoiding antibiotics. Complete with its own claim to Aboriginal authority it was ripe for the invoking. Meanwhile for the first white immigrants, whether on the coast or the plateau or even in the more secluded valley, the Aborigines had got here first, way back in the dreamtime of prehistory.

26

So in this alienated landscape, an unpeopled pristine was a dream from the first moment. If only the place had been as empty as the desire transferred to the expediency of terra nullius would have had it. Sure, the ‘corees’ were helpful for the most part. For a couple of red flannel shirts, or ‘the promise of a tomahawk … and plenty of tobacco’ Hodgkinson could engage men as guidesbut only after waiting through ‘a grand corroberree.’ ‘At length, … a cessation took place in the obstreperous singing, and frantic gesticulations, which create such intense excitement in the Australian savage during his dance, and the performers … cast themselves down exhausted before their fires' (51). Hodkinson appreciated the natives relish for their country and its provisionsfrom the fat cobberra, (a wormlike, shell-less mollusk they dug like marrow from rotting snags in the estuary) to the fish, snakes and lizards they snaffled along the way. Yet, as the description of the corroberree indicates, their interests and his were often frustratingly at odds. Otherwise the natives were a hostile disappointment or a lurking danger in the thousands of little undeclared wars by which the white invasion proceeded, best ignored if possible and played down by a kind of stoic, British dispossession into a bureaucratic bother. By Swain’s account—third hand history written in 1912— the bush on the Bellinger around 1850 ‘was infested by aborigines, numerous encounters occurred, and eventually the police came over from the Macleay and ordered the intrepid adventures back to civilization and safety' (12). Hodgkinson reports (second hand) one scene in the many theatres of the colonial wars About that time [March 1842] the blacks, from the sources of the Nambucca and the Bellingen, had committed several outrages on the sawyers, who had lately proceeded to the former river to cut cedar. One sawyer had been murdered most cruelly by the savages, who attacked him and his companion whilst felling a tree. When his body was found, it was ascertained that he had received more than fifty spear wounds in different parts; one spear had transfixed his kidneys, and even the soles of his feet had been pierced. His arms were dreadfully fractured, evidently whilst he was in the act of raising them to protect his head from the clubs of the natives. A retaliatory expedition was accordingly organized to pursue the aggressors, and endeavour to seize those who had been chiefly concerned in this murder. In the course of the chase, the sawyers, aided by some of the MacLeay river blacks, succeeded in approaching the encampment of the natives in the dead of night; and the next morning, on their making resistance, the whites poured a volley of ball and slug among them, and killed and wounded several. If I may credit the report of an eyewitness, most of the wounded blacks sprang into the water, where some of them were apparently seized by sharks attracted by their blood. Several other affrays had taken place about this time, between

27

the natives and parties of white men, in which the former were the aggressors. (48-9) Hodgkinson’s might not be the first European report of the Bellinger valley. In the autumn of 1841 similar events were taking place on the tablelands immediately to the west. ‘Squatters’, hemmed in by the daily encroachment of their agricultural neighbours, bought out by monied land proprietors, or pressed by their own rapidly-increasing flocks and herds; sought in more distant regions of the interior of this great ‘terra incognita’ those broad acres of hill and plain, so absolutely essential to the success of their pastoral avocations. (Eldershaw, 62) This is a quotation form Finney Eldershaw’s Australia As It Really Is, published in London in 1854. Eldershaw was one of this ‘adventurous band’ that had squatted on the northwestern New England tablelands. He has left an account of how, after ‘hardships and privations’, the squatters became settled. However, having themselves been pressed by economic and agricultural necessities, the squatters had in turn pressed upon the lands of their Aboriginal neighbours. Eldershaw’s account never entertains such a thought. It is as if the unknown character of this terra incognita was an inducement to suspend reflection and thereby empty the country of any others who might belong to it or to whom it might belong. Such was the social unconscious of colonialist society, effortlessly emptying cognitive, ethical, legal and geographical experience of Aboriginal societyat least until a crunch came. When the Aborigines resisted encroachment by spearing sheep and cattle, and eventually ‘massacred’ three shepherds and carried off two thousand sheep, Eldershaw concluded that ‘patience and conciliating care’ were no longer enough against ‘the horrors and atrocities’ which resulted from the ‘peculiarly treacherous and unequal warfare’ with the Aborigines. Ten of the squatters undertook the ‘painfully imperative task’ of pursuit and vengeance. The Aboriginesadults and childrenwere slowed down by the task of driving sheep. Using fire, spears, boomerangs and ambush, they had to fight off their pursuers in a series skirmishes as they fled east across the tablelands. Eventually the two parties arrived at the high cliffs where the tableland falls away into the coastal valleys. Nowadays it is said that where the cliffs are highest, at Nguloongeer on the rim of the upper Bellinger Valley, the Darkies Point massacre took place. Here a scene of most astounding wildness was presented to our gaze; a perfect amphitheatre lay beneath us formed by a mass of perpendicular rocks, whose bare and rugged faces would have afforded scarcely sufficient room for an eagle’s nest. Except that about midway from the smooth bottom of the glen, on which the campfires dimly blazed, and the height on which we stood, there appeared to be a rough projecting 28

ledge running around nearly the entire of two opposite curves of this strange quarry like spot. A few moments examination revealed to our wondering senses the wily stratagem by which these savage warriors had intended to beguile us into almost inevitable destruction. The projecting ledge of rock, which was about a hundred feet below us, and apparently about a similar height above the floor of the gap, was thickly thronged with the fighting men of the tribe, each armed powerfully with heavy spears, but most of them carrying a boomerang and a waddie. Huge stones, also, lay piled about, apparently from their position destined for warlike purposes; and we but in this instance approached with the incautious haste which usually distinguishes the white man’s way of dealing with these much despised Aborigines, our total destruction could hardly, in all human probability, been avoided. Hurriedly edging our way towards the mouth of the apparent ascent to the rocky platform, we were startled by the discharge of a gun proceeding from the party below. An ominous stir among the Blacks in the direction of this spot alarmed us for the safety of our friends, and reminded us of the necessity for immediate action. Pouring in, therefore, upon the eager but unconscious crowd below the contents of ten barrels, a fearful change was effected in their savage glee; a scream of mingled consternation and surprise, a rush in reckless despair towards the only means of escape from their exposed and dangerous elevation; a murderous and tumultuous struggle amongst themselves; their yells of mingled hate and agony, as grappling together in the last grasp of death the foremost of them fell, urged over the ledge’s brink by the pressing crowd behind that madly hurried on, into the yawning sepulchre beneath, was all of the horrid scene that the increasing darkness of the night enabled us clearly to perceive. We now reloaded, and our party from below pushing forward to the scene of the conflict, poured in a deadly volley upon the thronging crowds that lined the rocky entrance to this fatal ledgeback flew the despairing retches from that dreadful spotagain a volley from our party on the heights dealt frightful havoc upon their ranks. The utmost wildness of despair now seized upon them all; some actually dashed themselves in frantic violence to the depths beneath, in utter heedlessness of life. One solitary tree grew in this fatal glen; its topmost limbs reaching almost to the level of their feet; with faint remains of hope, some of the youngest and most active of the tribe sprang at its fragile boughs in vainfew grasped its treacherous aid, where, quivering for a moment on its yielding branches, their latest shrieks of dying agony, mingling with the mass beneath, too plainly told the dreadful fate they sought to shun, but only had anticipated. Sick of the horrid carnage below, I fain would have retired from the 29

dreadful spot, but all my efforts, entreaties, threats, were utterly useless. Shot after shot, with curses wild and deep, the excited fellows launched at their hated foestheir butchered comrades’ blood was that night fearfully avenged! (71-72) There are several similarities in these descriptions of massacres. In the same year, events seem to mirror one another at either end of the Bellinger valley. In each case, the colonial law is ignored, blame is unilaterally attributed to those not writing the history, and the instruments of vengeance and terror are invoked in the name of justiceas often happened in the remote parts of the colony. We may conclude that such actions actually happened, and in both places. They were part of the past as it actually was. However, there are also many similarities in the ways of telling these stories, similarities that indicate a mythic reconfiguration of events right from the first telling of history. Hodkinson’s own phrase—if I may credit the report of an eyewitness—is already a hint to be on the lookout. In each story, avenging Nature, as it were, enacts the retribution. In each case it is Nature that is responsible for the otherwise unspeakable deed of torture, so that the civilized avengers can esteem themselves as sublime observers of a cruel spectacle. In each case the Aborigines are reduced to a hopeless and pathetic fate. In each case they are massacred. In each case there is an enthrallment by the dangers of the natural world, a fascination with the abjection and humiliation of other humans suffering and panicking, and an emphasis on the cruelty of human, specifically Aboriginal, malice. Just which of these features indicate actual events and which indicate narrative poetics is a moot point. However the number of features is surely evidence of the kind of generic confabulation that empirical historiography must consider not only as a problem for the truth of its own stories, but as part of the very subject matter of those stories. The generic deeds, events and plots have been selected by social pressures brought to bear during the telling, variation and retelling of narrative accounts: to hive-off responsibility for the cruelty of massacre onto Nature itself; to justify the terror as natural justice in which Nature is both judge and executioner; to tell an historical allegory foretelling the final and inevitable victory against an enemy whose fate is hopeless; to advertise the success of the reprisals; to teach an emphatic lesson of terror; to amplify the esteem for those who undertook the ‘imperative task’ and who lived to tell the tale by enlarging the passion and drama of their experience; and to invoke the old emotive drive of the poetics of violence.

Johnny-come-lately The fascination with the pristine is not new. Those colonizing Anglo-Celts carried with them the images of Arcadia and Eden, of pristine paradise, and paradise lost at that—images at least as old as writing. The once and future 30

golden age had long been imagined, as in Virgil’s fourth eclogue, where ‘soil will suffer hoes no more, nor vines the hook.’ Pastoral and then Romantic nature have probably been symptomatic of an urban hankering after the charms of nature. The charms of nature might not have been uppermost in the minds of timber getters and selectors, but it was not long before the bush turned into a sentimental custom, and the old subsistence practices into rites. But, in most places, the bush was a paradise lost right from the starta kind of fallen, melancholic nature of hard-leaved eucalypts, brooding grey-green open forests, endless, drab or dry. It took a bit of sublime apprehension, or the relief of a creek or river or a ferntree glen even to start to love ita bit of poetry or painting or hunting, shooting, fishing or bushwalking. Whether the imagination of the pristine haunted traditional Aboriginal society is another question. It's there in modern Aboriginal society, but is it a symptom confined to modernity? There is a beautiful story that has been told in several of the languages of Northern Australia—admittedly a world away from Gumbaynggirr country. A northern Gunwinggu version told by Jimmy MidjauMidjau is retold by Ronald and Catherine Berndt (178): Dog, Durug and big red Kangaroo, Gulubar, were men at Adbaldi. Kangaroo said, ‘You try to paint my body to make me look attractive.’ So Dog got his ochres and clay and painted him to look like a kangaroo. When he had finished, he said it was Kangaroo’s turn to paint him. ‘I have drawn you well. Now make me look as pretty as I have made you.’ So Kangaroo set to work and began painting Dog. But he did it in a different way, and made him look like a dog. When Kangaroo had finished, Dog looked at himself in the water and thought how ugly he looked. He was angry: ‘I drew you well, made you pretty; but you have made me like a dog, ugly!’ And he continued, ‘Now that you’ve made me like this, I will bite you: it’s your own doing, you made me like thatwith a long nose, a long tongue and long teeth. I’ve got to chase you and bite you. Constant telling, variation and retelling have refined this moral tale into a polished narrative of ideas. I venture to say that is about how self-description is mediated by others descriptions of oneself and by the social means available for self-description, and how, in turn, this alienated description of oneself is made real in one’s own ethical self-construction. This, though, is just one complicated interpretation. Distillation to utter clarity has left a story transparent to many readings. Yet, apart from the poetic perfection, the story seems still to register something of its genesis in the contingencies of the ecological history of Aboriginal Australia. Surplus historical contingency is just the sort of thing that the refinements of oral poesis might have discarded in the selection of what is ethically and metaphysically illuminating. The historical detail that seems to 31

have left its trace in the story of Kangaroo’s Deceit is the late arrival of the dingo or wild dog in Australia. Compared to marsupials like the kangaroo, the dingo is a johnny-come-lately with no autochthonic credentials at all. This diminished native status was much referred to when justifying dingo culling after a couple of them recently killed a child on Frazer Island. Other placental mammals, like flying foxeslate-comers compared to the marsupialsget tarred with the same brush when it suits cullers. Dingoes have probably been here a mere 5000 years. We humans have been here much longer. Kangaroos much longer again. The pretty face of the kangaroo is just the kind of thing that goes with the refinements of the old order. The ugliness and troublesomeness of dingoes are just the kinds of things that disturb that pristine order. Yet this disturbance of the old order is occasioned by its authentic dwellers, by Kangaroo’s own deceit. Time also enters this story in another way. This is a story about how deeds in an ancestral past have left their mark on the world. Time in this case might be so-called Dreamtime, time eternalized by narrative poesis acting under the pressure of metaphysics’ hunger for timelessness, or time detemporalized by cultural forgetfulness confronting its immemorial duration, but time nevertheless, and pregnant with itself as well as its issue. And like the imaginations of the pristine, this too is a story about a fall from grace, and about loss and regret and knowledge. Only in time do we see the consequences and so the meaning of actions. It seems to be the case that the further modern society sees itself severed from the nature in which it senses it must have originated, or deprived of the nature that it senses it must have sacrificed, the more that natureand especially the still standing indices and ruins of itseems to take on a aura. In Australia, three values at least coincide in this: the dazzling wealth and beauty of all those living thingsthe ‘value of biodiversity’ according to the rhetoric of environmental managerialism; the inalienable right, glory and authenticity of the first, the former, the primordial; and the value of the sacrificed thingthat value that may only be experienced as regret or, at best, as a promise of redemption. Common to all stories about the pristine is the melancholy sense of time that haunts the ever after: that only in time may we understand meaning, but therefore too late and therefore as loss.

32

3 Tallowwood Country The evolution and ecology of the eucalypt forests and rainforests of the Bellinger Valley and eastern Australia.

Depth casually beginning all around, at a little distance. Sky sifting, and always a hint of smoke in the light; you can never reach the heart of a gum forest. —Les Murray, The Gum Forest Eucalyptus microcorys F. Muell. Tallowwood Tree to 40m (occasionally 60); bark persistent, red-brown or brownblack, flaky-stringy (with included mica-like flakes)…Abundant in wet forest or rainforest margins on moderately to highly fertile soils often on slopes; north from near Cooranbong. NC, CC; Qld. —Flora of New South Wales, vol. 2.

Where I am writing is tallowwood country. Eight species of eucalyptus grow herewithin a few hundred metres, here in these ridges between Bellingen and the sea. All of them could be called gum trees, and so could four more species that are almost eucalypts: bloodwood, angophora, brushbox and turpentine. For the record, there are three or four hundred other plant species here as well. But it’s tallowwood—Eucalyptus microcorys—that is the signature tree. It’s on all the ridges and in all the gullies. To distinguish these timbered hills from the river flats down along the Bellinger, people usually call it ridge country. Fine sediments were laid down 250 million years ago under a Permian sea and afterwards pressed, twisted and fractured into micaceous slates. Here and there, wrung from these tortured metasediments, seams of white quartz have pooled and congealed. The present ridges and gullies have been carved back out of this amalgam. Dark brown topsoil covers slaty clays. The clay is yellow on the drier ridges, red and dispersive where moisture has done a lot of leaching, dense and pale like kaolin

33

in low waterlogged places. There is a glut of aluminium and iron, a lack of phosphorous, calcium and magnesium. It is richer than much of the tired old geology of the Australian continent, but not as rich and yielding as the estuarine and alluvial loams a few hundred metres away down on the flats. Occasionally, jagged clots of the quartz, stained reddish by iron, find themselves at the weathered surface, like little asteroid belts wandering through geological time. Washed white by rain they sit like tokens on the forest floor. Few people know that if you pick them up and rub them together in the dark they shimmer like summer lightning. Triboluminescence. At odd locations, a spade sunk into the soil will strike a hunk of foreign river stone, one side smoothed by water the other flaked to a sharp edgea tool left up here on a ridge in what is now forest, generations agoor a shard of willow pattern, a horseshoe, a length of fencing wire, a rusty horse drawn plough, a steel Flag Ale can, an oil filter from a bulldozer, a dope grower’s watering gear, or the gutted body of a 1960s Holden. Time transforms artifacts from useful to eyesore to ruin to archaeology to geology. That single tine plough has become beautiful. The rusty EH Holden is being redeemed. Archaeologically, it is already curious; aesthetically, it is already amusing. We visit it on our walks there at the head of Wreck Gully, and stand around it reading the number plate and wondering. If we were kids we might sit in it and turn the steering wheel. Upside down. The flaked stones wait in dreamtime, forever useful and intriguing—almost geological. Alongside the tallowwoods you will sometimes find (and, if you are me, sometimes confuse them with) white mahoganies. Tallowwoods have longer, stringier bark with, here and there, little wafer thin tiles of bark plated over the fibres. Beneath the weathered grey-brown of the outer fibres their bark is a bright tan, and from beneath that tan, tallowwoods glow a gorgeous honey, as if the colour of the timber or of the clay beneath the tree is shining up through it. It has a deep like fat says someone in a poem of Les Murray’s. The white mahoganies emanate a more sombre brick red and the colour of their timber is a paler honey. You will also find Sydney blue gums (Eucalyptus saligna and hereinafter simply called blue gums), flooded gums, blackbutts, grey gums and ironbarks; and, down where the gullies run out into coastal wetlands, swamp mahoganies. There are the eucalypts’ closest relatives, the pink bloodwoods, and on the highest driest ridges the smooth coast angophoras; and the cousins, the lush brushbox and the tough turpentine. All tall forest trees. All seeming to pick up their hues from the palette of the earth and the sky: barks of slaty blue, grey and black, kaolin white, ochre and red, evening pink and storm mauve, all touched by the blue-grey wash of hard light, weather and age, and all changing too, so that what is drably called grey gum can be bright burning orange or cool lime when new trees step out of old; or what is coolly called blue gum can be hot pink and lemon as well as steel, sky, slate and ocean blue and all in one month; timbers brick red, honey brown and earth brown, ochre and pink; leaves draining from an ungreen country whatever fraction of colour they need to turn the surfeit of sunlight into sugars for themselves and for lerps, cicadas, gliders, flying foxes and honeyeaters to suck on. When you are standing in it, this 34

country just looks like eucalypt forest, mainly tallowwood forest, all around you. Whatever rainforest there is here is rainforest-with-eucalypts. From a distance the country looks like eucalypt forest too; and nearly every spring it is all mottled with the heads of the tallowwoods in creamy flower. No other tree seems to flower with such regular profusion. As if to mark the flowering, tweeting scarlet honeyeaters and kok-kakking little wattlebirds arrive in the ridge country. They join the resident eastern spinebills, little and dapper in their busy flight, and the Lewin’s honeyeaters, who more or less own the place or act like they do and who announce the flowering, like they announce everything, with staccato fanfares. The honeyeaters can’t lick much nectar from the dry cups of tallowwood flowers though. Instead it is insects that get among the stamens and pollen, bugs and beetles that are there for the picking of songbirdsthe loud little thornbills and warblers, the golden whistlers, and the suave grey thrushand for any peckish honeyeaters busy feeding nestlings and fledglings and looking for a bit of insect protein. The honeyeaters, as honey eaters, are all celebrating the tallowwood flowering by feeding on the chandeliers of flowering mistletoe, the Amyema miquellii that hangs from the eucalypts and caricatures their foliage. Each of the eucalypts finds its places among the others and according to the peculiarities of its physiology. Communities of various species seem to defineat least for the sorting habits of human reasonkinds of plant communities, but fuzzy kinds. People say, with confidence, this is tallowwoodblue gum forest, that up there on the ridge is blackbutt forest, down there in the gully it is flooded gum forest, down on the lower floodplain along with the rainforest, the swamp mahogany, the paperbarks and the swamp oak forests there were once red gum forests. The ecological peculiarities of each species seem roughly to predict their layout across the country, and then the flukes of history leave their traces like a million imperfections in the general plan. Where a fire got started and licked up that spur from the bottom of the gully, clearing it of scrub, and where there was a surfeit of seed from two old flooded gums and of sunlight on the clean dirt, there now grows a stand of flooded gums, young at only 50, 35 metres tall, straight and polished. The Flooded Gums we call themloud with summer’s cicadas, the sound of the heat says Robert Gray. The witching hour is noon in the gum forest says Les Murray. The Flooded Gums is a monoculture broken only by a couple of pink bloodwoods and a tallowwood, although that is ignoring the vines and shrubsthe morinda, sarsaparilla, orange thorn, saw sedge, grey myrtle, hard quandong and fairy’s paintbrush, and many others that grow as understorey. 100 metres further up the spur the flooded gums give way to tallowwoods, blue gums, bloodwoods and white mahoganies. There is a slightly different understorey here, and there is one single Symplocus in itthe only one for miles around. A few old black ironbarks, that must have once spread there branches here over open ground, mark the changeover to the forested ridge that we now call The Symplocus Ridge. This ironbark is Eucalyptus ancophila, a scattered species found only in the moist low ridge country of the Bellinger and Nambucca valleys. 35

In the next gully to the west, where a road was cut across the hill 20 years ago, tallowwoods came up in the mineral soil next to mature trees. Follow the same road around the contour to the shadier western side of the gully and there you strike young blackbutts, 20m tall, offspring of big trees seeding on the ridge above. Blackbutts tend to be in drier or better drained sites. They dominated the dry main ridge just above, so it was mostly their seed that happened to fall on the open subsoil. Even then, if the soil had not been open and ample enough to accommodate the blackbutt’s rooting demands the seedlings might not have prevailed. Their trunks are rough on the bottom and smooth-barked from halfway up. The rough barked butts are often left burnt black by fire. None around here less than 40 years old bears this sign. The Big Blackbutt on the West Bank has been hollowed out on its northern side by hundreds of years of fire and termites. Scribble moths incise intricate doodles in the smooth pale upper barkas they do on the several species of scribbly gumswriting out the journey of their lives on the decorticating parchment. Up on the ridge-lines and high spurs, the blackbutts are interspersed with little gatherings of grey gum, their old grey bark peeling back to expose smooth patches that sparkle orange and lemon and alabaster in the summer rain. Among the gums, there are carpeted groves of feathery forest oak (Allocasuarina torulosa) and declining colonies of Maiden’s wattle, and still plenty of tallowwood, the odd white mahogany, occasional brushbox, and, at the very top on the slaty primary ridge, the dimpled pink torsos of a few coast angophoras, far from the Sydney sandstone that I think of as their home. The buttery timber of tallowwood with its tight interlocked grain, is beautiful for anything that must take wear and weather, even without treatment for preservation. Hard, very strong, very durable, easy to polish and comparatively easy to work, it makes the strongest scantlings, frames and bridges, the most enduring fences, the sleekest outdoor deckings, railings and furniture. Indoors, it reveals its genius in the tight spring of the best dance and gym floors, and in the lines of fine furniture. The architect Richard le Plaistrier calls it the doyen of North Coast hardwoods. Unless it’s green you can’t nail it, but he uses it well-seasoned, second hand in fact, and takes the time to join it so cleanly it could be dismantled and live on in a succession of buildings. Unless you are a termite or you like your hardwoods soft, it is the most prized of hardwoods, especially from a tree that has been given time to fully grow. But growing it frustrates the expedient spirit of forest managerialism. And like most eucalypts around here it languishes under the cruel greenish gentility of ‘selective logging’. Eucalypts can need a bit more disturbance than that. Leaf litter and the fungi that it incubates are death to eucalypt seedlings. So is excessive shade. Foresters resort to fire, soil disturbance and more extensive felling, and that can work with blackbuttsbut it all depends on the heat of the fire, the amount of soil disturbance, the drainage of the soil, the area of the felling coup, the availability of ambient seed, exposure to frosts, the seasons of herbivores, and other factors too numerous to be enumerated, let alone controlled. Tallowwood is too capricious for the managerial spirit, which deems 36

it too slow, too frost prone, too susceptible to insects, or too something or other. The growth of postcolonial weeds defeats tallowwood too. Do the seedbed preparation and the conditions are perfect for the lantana, broad-leaved paspalum, and native vines that make life difficult for seedling and juvenile tallowwoods. Where there are, as yet, few weeds and no lantana, up on the Eastern Dorrigo say, I have seen blue gum and tallowwood forest erupting in the wake of a fierce fire the way lowlanders can only dream of, or the way they think only blackbutt can grow. Down in the valley though, there is no sure, oneoff action to get them growing, the economies of managerialism can only afford what is one-off, and it ends up that no one wants tallowwoods anymore. They just complicate things. For practical purposes, very little is actually known about the life cycle of any but a handful of species. Under unconscious, or at least seldom acknowledged pressures, forestry has evolved into fast and relatively predictable blackbutt regeneration (It is only fast and predictable on certain sites). Otherwise it’s plantations of blackbutt, the fast growing flooded gum, or oddities like the exotically fast and faddish Dunn’s white gum, a tree from distant pockets on the Nymboida and the Border Ranges. Industrial forests are sown to haunt the future, the nightmare landscapes of an unconscious society, generated when alienated timber demands, abstract growth expectations, projected sawmill demand, fashion and promotion come up against the uncomprehended ecology specific to every metre of ground and every species. And as with dreams, the whole process is rationalized retrospectively, heedlessly: everyoneforesters, managers and criticsthink they have understood everything all along.

Laurels And Myrtles John Milton began Lycidas, his formal, pastoral elegy on the drowning of a fellow Cambridge scholar, with botany. Yet once more, O ye laurels, and once more, Ye myrtles brown, with ivy never sere, I come to pluck your berries harsh and crude, And with forced fingers rude Shatter your leaves before the mellowing year. Verse like this is supposed to have become almost incomprehensible. Samuel Johnson had already said as much about Milton back in the 18th century; and literary critics have kept on saying it. Some of them in the late 20th took pride in lamenting that, to untrained readers, an elegy like Lycidas epitomizes artificial, ornate, alien verse, beyond passion. For most of us, they said, it was as dead as the subject matter of the elegy itself: the drowned scholar with the pseudonym of a dead shepherd, and the fossilized flora excavated from the Greek of Theocritus and the Latin of Virgil. In order to melt meaning from 37

the frozen European metaphors and thaw the references to botany, pastoral elegy and classical myth, readers would be condemned to persevere with a kindling of footnotes, allto make what use we still can of Milton‘canker to the rose’ of poetry. A particular problem in Australia, supposedly, is that all the stuff about European vegetation seems irrelevant for antipodean readerslike Christmas in summer. Complaints about the irrelevance or foreignness of European nature culture are still an everyday part of the pop analysis of Australian culture. Really though, it is nature that has become foreign and incomprehensible. With the functional division of landscape, and the specialist division of intellectual labour, nearly everything has become incomprehensible to nearly everyone, nearly everywhere. Nature is just one other uncomprehended, alienated and unnatural department of modern life, like Miltonic verse. It would have occurred to only a few then, here in the Bellinger valley or elsewhere on the east coast of Australia, that the most common local family of plants is the myrtle family. And their berries are harsh and crudewooden, in fact. Eucalypts are myrtles and their fruits, the gumnuts, are like woody berriesprotective capsules with a few little valves engineered on top to let the seeds out when they and the time are ripe. Eucalypts are the most common myrtles here or anywhere, the generic genus of Australian trees. Pink bloodwoods and smooth angophoras are myrtles tooso closely related to eucalypts and so patently ‘gum trees’ that they are allowed the name of eucalyptus, in the broad sense at least. And there are still other local myrtles with woody brown fruits: brushbox, bottlebrush, paperbark and turpentine. This is their country too. With more succulent berriessome harsh, some crude, some quite palatablethere are rose myrtles, plum myrtles, native guavas, rhodamnias and the lilly pilliesblue, purple and plain. Outside my window crooning regent bowerbirds are tousling the branches of a rhodamnia, picking the berries as they ripen red and blackred like the dot on the regent’s golden brow and black as the feathers that frame its flashing golden wings. A Lewin’s honeyeater is sneaking among them too, stealing the same fruit. Last night flying foxes were squealing in the same tree, down low and feeding on the fruitunusual for them but this is a dry, unfruitful year. A month ago the sunny air was electric with the odour of rose myrtle flowers and loud with feral bees. In a month’s time the fat black tree skinks will be gleaning the red berries dropped by the Lewin’s and they will be leaving the seeds on our veranda in their juicy droppings. We will be sampling the blue lilly pillies, making jam from the brush cherries that grow on the creeks and behind the beaches and eating the jam we made at Christmas from the riberries that grow down in the littoral rainforest. All up, within a birdcall of here there are 24 species of myrtle belonging to 12 genera. And maybe 60 species within a bat flight. There are also 9 species of laurels in 5 genera. Like the myrtles that have succulent fruits, the laurels are rainforest trees. Pluck their dark, oily drupes before the pigeons or bower birds do, shatter their leaves in your hands, and 38

you can smell the rainforest in the nearby gullies, the aroma of jackwood, murrogun, white bolly gum, and the native cinnamomum. So if it’s the flora of death and poetry you wantmyrtles and laurelsyou could forget Milton’s Arcadia and come here. Or better, read Milton and recognize it all around youornate and alien. The third big family of trees in the local forests is less well known. Its formal name is the Sapindaceae. Its uncommon common name is the Soapberry family. It is the lychee family, or the native tamarind family. Like the sapindaceous lychee, many of the fruits in this family have a smooth seed with a juicy aril wrapped wholly or partly around it. The aril and its seed are enclosed together in a thin shell that splits and peels back to show the aril off. Birds go for the bright aril and drop the seed. There are 11 species of them here, belonging to 10 generamainly small to medium sized trees: guioa and foambark both very common, native and green-leaved tamarind, steelwood, blunt steelwood, red and yellow mischocarpus, and alectryon all at home in lowland rainforest; a few tuckeroos, a tree of coasts and estuaries here at the end of the estuarine influence, and maybe still a few shrubby hopbushes last relics of an almost forgotten fire. Related to lychees they may be, but the only one that we eat from this forest is the native tamarind. Their straight sinewy trunks manage to hold crowns of big compound leaves above the tangles of viny scrub at the ends of gullies. The panicles of fruit are nearly always too high to pick. Plentiful on the tree, we get the dropped ones the birds waste while they’re feeding, enough to make small jars of golden jam. They are not related to the leguminous tropical tamarind; the sour fruit must have evoked the name. Besides the 24 myrtles, the 9 laurels and the 11 species in the Sapindaceae family, there are also 15 grasses the second largest family in factlurking in this supposedly grassless forest, and 13 orchidsthe third largest, yet seldom seen, so ingenious is their cryptic artcontriving fleeting beauties in improbable places. 300 or so indigenous plant species belonging to 100 families are at home just around here in this ridge and gully country, this tallowwood country. In the last century or so, 50 more exotic species have also found a home here. The myrtles with succulent berriesalong with the local laurels, the Sapindaceae and too many other species to listare usually called rainforest trees. They are seldom as big as the eucalypts, which, with the other woody fruited myrtles, make a tall open forestthe so-called eucalypt forest. This non-rainforest is what people would just call the bush. The other conspicuous trees in this local bush are casuarinas (the forest oaks) and the acacias. The acaciasblackwoods, black wattles and Maiden’s wattlesare short-lived down here in the valley and can dominate the earlier stages of regenerating forest. Up on the cooler Dorrigo plateau, as in Tasmania and Victoria, the blackwoods grow into forest trees with a purplish timber, hard and bright as glass. Down here, their growth is forced in the humid subtropics, and the larvae of the turquoise diamond weevils do not give them much more than a dozen extravagantly fast growing years. Although they burn bright and clean in a 39

stove (once it is burning hot), they are ecologically much less bushfiery than the eucalypts, and in large parts of Australia acacias replace the eucalypts. In the mulga it is too arid. In brigalow, they can form a scrub unkindled by eucalypt litter. All around here the fiery eucalypt forest and the un-fiery rainforest are a pair of ecological antagonists playing off against one another. At one extreme on the ridges there are those hard leaved or sclerophyll forests that get too dry for the rainforest plants to establish and thrive, that are too given to fire if and when there is a spark of ignition. At the other, in the deep moist gullies, the southern slopes, the richest soils, the beachside fringe, and the watered river flats there is rainforest. In between, which is nearly everywhere, is the strange, contingent wet sclerophyll forestcalled wet because of the rainforest understorey and the metre and a half of rainfall, and sclerophyll because of those hard-leaved wooden towers of eucalyptus rising above everything else and kindling it all with their dropped sticks. It’s a forest that lacks an essence, that lacks a simple history, so old and enduring it exceeds individual human observation, so young, so contingent, so given to catastrophe it defies determinate description, so big, so everywhere, you try but cant ignore it, a probabilistic complex of tall myrtle fire forest and sombre laurel and myrtle scrub, qualified by wattles and forest casuarinas and more species than you can poke a stick at. I can walk out my front door and walk for days from here near sea level right up the escarpment to Tuckers Knob and around the rim of the valley to Point Lookout and never get outside this distinctive matrix of eucalypt forest with rainforest gullies. After reaching Point Lookout I could probably walk through eucalypts all the way to Melbourne, following the Great Dividing Range for a thousand miles.

Eucalyptus sensu lato Australians travel hundreds of kilometres and see the same trees over and over and over again. Eucalypts. Roadside landscape is experienced as unrelenting repetition. James Cook’s comment on sailing up the east coast was that the country did not produce any great variety of trees. The young Charles Darwin, fresh off The Beagle in 1836, saw ‘extreme uniformity…so wearisome to the traveller’s eye.’ From the backseat of the car the word is boring. Australians though could travel anywhere and see different trees everywhere eucalypts so astonishing in their evolutionary variation on the one theme that Darwin, comfortable deciphering the diversity of his Galapagos finches, must have been dazzled beyond discrimination. Like Darwin, Australia is just passing through. It lives elsewhere, distracted in its own imaginary nation. This eucalypt country is its antipodes, good mainly for the export of icons, metaphors and national frisson back home from its tedious wilds. Roadside bush beyond the 60km/hour zone is not popular culture. It is not an easy read. Only if you practice and work at it does the depth and intricacy of 40

this minimalist text begin to reveal itself. Otherwise it is needless packaging between the cities, farms and tourist attractions, as interesting as shredded paper. In nature, as in art, people often mistake overwhelming complexity for minimalism. Mathematicians know that noise is just another name for complexity that defies interpretation. In the bush, it takes an effort to decipher all that hard green noise. When you work at it though, the order and beauty is bewildering. Too bewildering. You have to get out of the car sometimes to take a closer look at the most charmless roadscapes, or behind the flora highwayensis that the Road Traffic Authority decorates its dual carriageways with to reassure travellers they have not left the Australian imaginary. Drive from Sydney to the Bellinger and as the country passes by, the kinds of eucalyptus change with soil type, moisture, elevation, fire regime and the accidents of history. Down on the Hawkesbury sandstone it’s the burly torsos and lushish crowns of smooth angophoras, fire charred red bloodwoods, scribbly gums graphed with bush sine waves. On the creeks and estuaries beyond the Hunter its flowering forest red gums full of friar birds, blackbutts singed by fire, or, beyond the big mini Uluru, swamp mahoganies and prickly paperbarks on the Boolambayte Overflow, leafy primitive phantoms fenced away from cars and modernity. From the Wang Wauks north, in the tall wet forests it is straight flooded gums, their trunks smooth as pale steel above palmy gullies, and blue gums, and tallowwoods, orange in the sun, black and red in the rain. If you travel the high road instead, the New England Highway along the Great Dividing Range, you get far enough from the coast to see white boxes and some inland red gums, high enough to see snow gums and black sallee. On the high country near Armidale graziers tried too hard to carve their imagined England into the bush and ended up with a landscape where the eucalypts could no longer grow back. In disbelief that their recalcitrant, century long foe could so suddenly give up the ghost, people inferred the existence of a new disorder, called it eucalypt dieback, and sought its cause. Research was overwhelmed by beetles, grubs, wasplessness, fungus, fertilisers, climate, grazingindeed by all the diverting diversity of ecological causationand, as such matters at hand displaced agricultural history and fading memory, blame was distributed over the handy hypercomplexity of immediate causes. After turning east at would-be-English Armidale, you pass by permutations of peppermints and stringybarks, mountain gums and snow gums on the high Snowy Range, brown barrels, messmates and white gums on the Dorrigo volcanics, and, as you drop down off the Dorrigo and into the tall subtropical forests of the Bellinger, a signal band of white-topped box marks the 600m elevation between the top and bottom waterfalls on the steep road. No matter which way you go, wherever you pass, there are several species togetherusually several that are hard to differentiate. The mix of species changes; it changes proportion or one species disappears or another appears. Trees of any one species change their appearance throughout a year or in

41

different places or under different conditions, but only enough to make that species look like another species that looks much the same anyway. It is hard to say how many species of eucalyptus there are. It depends on who is counting and just what they think a species is. Some would put it closer to a thousand, but let’s just say that there are over 700 hundred species of eucalyptus in the broad sense, that is, including the 100 or so bloodwoods and the dozen or so angophoras. Only 12 of them grow as natives outside Australiain New Guinea, Timor, Sulawesi and Mindanao; and only 4 of those are not native to Australia at all. Only one, Eucalyptus deglupta, lives beyond the line that Alfred Russell Wallace drew in the 19th century through the Lombok and Makassar Straits, and the Sulawesi Sea to mark the separation of Australian from Asian biota. It might also be the only eucalypt to have crossed the line between fiery sclerophyll forest and rainforestalthough that depends on what you are prepared to call rainforest. The norm (if not the fact) seems to be: if it has eucalypts in it then it can’t be rainforest. Here on the east coast though, there are many places where eucalypts that germinated centuries ago in the ashes of some ancient fire now tower over dense rainforests that have grown up underneath them, the ferment of the wet forests slowly consuming the aging gums. But I am getting ahead of myself. The acacias, with over 750 Australian species, could be said to rival the eucalypts as the typical Australian species; and with another 450 acacias spread over every continent except Europe, they presently make up the biggest single genus of trees and shrubs. Compared to the eucalypts though, no genus is so distinctively of one continent. Few genera so dominate their forests and woodlands. No flowering plant grows as tall, as hard, as tough. Nothing could forge so much hard wood out of nothing but ash and hot sun and hard dry earth. Nothing could thrive so much on the drama of firethe fiercest element, and so much the destroyer of life that many are unable to concede that evolutionary theory could allow a living thing to be adapted to it. Over 20 of the 40 tall forest eucalypts grow in the little valley of the Bellinger. Over 60 species grow here on what people from New South Wales call the North Coast. To identify a eucalypt the first thing you are likely to look at is its bark. Does it have smooth bark, like that of the pale flooded gum that peels away every summer and drapes the understorey in streamers of tan ribbons, or is it smooth bark shed in scales, flakes or patches? Although the term gum tree is used for any eucalypt, in its strict sense it designates the smooth barked ones. If the bark is rough, is it stringy or fibrous or hard or fissured or tessellated? Is it rough on the butt and smooth on the upper trunk of the branches? After the bark there are other things to look for. You are probably going to have to find the woody fruits to identify a particular specimen. Eucalypts can be very sparing with their fruit though and what fruit there is might only be on branches 20 metres above the ground. Many times I have scraped around on the ground under a tree looking for fallen fruit, fruitlessly. Professional seed collectors sometimes resort to high-powered rifles to blast limbs off. Others use bows to shoot ropes on arrows over the limbs, pull up saw chains and fiddle about 42

pulling each end of the rope trying to cut the limb off. For identification, the questions to ask of the fruit are: how wide is the woody capsule, how round, how deep set the valves, how many valves, how wide the rim, does the rim slope up or down? A lot of plant recognition comes down to rough familiarity, to just knowing without being able quite to articulate the distinguishing features. Like chicken sexing, you look for the look. Some people like to see the colour and texture of the timber, or to look at it in the ground and see if it has withstood termites and fungi for a hundred years, or only five. Rough familiarity provides many opportunities for reckless claims to knowledge. Around here any bit of deep red hardwood, especially on an old house, gets called red mahogany. Were there once forests of this species that are all cut down now? Or is some of it blue gumblue gums have red wood tooor what? Maybe attractive red timber attracts an attractive name. Sticking to the external appearance, I often find that I call something a tallowwood, a messmate or a white gum and afterwards someone points out it’s a white mahogany, a brown barrel or a blue gum. There is the taleapocryphal, cautionary or gloatingabout a specialist in classification, a taxonomist, who had presided over the hair-splitting of what had been thought of as one species of ironbark into several new ones with new names. Taxonomists, as a species themselves, are split into splitters and lumpersthose given to splitting species up and those who lump them back together. This man was given two specimens picked from a single ironbark belonging to one of the species that he himself had distinguished and named. He identified the separate specimens as two different species. He was a real splitter. In 1853, after only one year in Australia, the Liverpudlian collector William Swainson claimed to have identified 1520 species of eucalyptus in Victoria alone. He had managed to up the total from the paltry 160 known when he had arrived. According to this arch botanizer each species could be read as an indicator of the particular nature of the country where it grew (Hay, 2002). He claimed species grew along lines that traced the mineral veins running through the earth beneath, and, with gold fever running high in the colonies, he predicted that gold could be discovered by the gum species that grew above the seams. His fiction had a vein of truth: there is no doubt that when you are trying to identify a eucalypt it helps to bear in mind where a tree is growing and what kind of country it belongs to. In Murray Bail’s novel Eucalyptus, specimens of every species in the genus are brought from all over the country and planted on the one property. For the hand of the owner’s daughter, suitors have to identify every species. Like Bail’s plot, such an arboretum is a kind of monstrous contrivance. It is a strange violence, an alienation of the spirit of eucalypts. People acquainted with their eucalypts usually know them by where they grow: they know the ones in their part of the country; or they can identify a species by knowing where it comes from. A eucalypt planted away from its natural country is a nameless anomaly, a failure to appreciate spirit of place. 43

The tiny seedlings of most gums come up with kidney-shaped or y-shaped cotyledons. Cotyledons are the ‘first leaves’. They emerge from a seed the size of a grain of sand. Identifying seedlings is a challenge in itself. The juvenile leaves that appear next in the seedling’s development are typically quite different from the adult leaves. They are opposite one another on the stem, often round or symmetrical, and often dusted with a protective glaucous bloom. Juvenile leaves might also sprout as new growth after fire or injury, as well as on seedlings. To complicate matters, many species display several intermediate stages between juvenile and adult leaf forms. Adult leaves are no longer opposite one another, the pairs having become separated by uneven growth rates on either side of the branches. They are usually slightly curved, broadest at the base, and asymmetrical about the mid-vein. The upper and lower surfaces can be almost indistinguishable. They hang side-on to the sun, their hard blades slicing the hot rays and holding on to water. In the wet forests of the Bellinger though, the most common species have the luxury of leaves with distinct upper and lower surfaces. Even so, a lot of light streams through the crowns of the trees, washing out rich, shady hues from the understorey of the forests, while the big trees pump the soil dry beneath a litter of desiccated sticks and bark. The leaves are usually only of limited assistance in identification. They can all look pretty much the same. Gum leaves. Crush them in your hands anyway and smell the oil. Which nuance of eucalyptus is it? Is it light or lemony, heavy or peppermint? Flooded gums and blue gums can look awfully alikeas adults or seedlings. There are nuances of tallness, straightness, paleness of gum bark, height of the stocking of rough bark. The reported occurrence of hybrids makes identification more problematicor else it is used as an excuse for the inability to differentiate. The woody fruitsusually the best indicatorare not available until a plant gets old enough. A friend who runs a nursery can pick the seedlings apart by smellthe blue gums have a stronger eucalyptus smelland despite a dark predawn start and missing labels, he has been confident enough to dispatch large orders into the field on the strength of his nose. Sometimes the arrangement of the flowers may help distinguish species. The inflorescences of different plants have names that sound like fairies and spritespanicle, raceme, cyme, corymb or umbelaccording to how the groups of flowers are arranged and branched. A eucalypt inflorescence is called an umbellasterthe term for a collection of flowers arising more or less from one point at the end of a single stalk. Strictly, an umbellaster is a compressed dichasial cyme. There are usually 1,3,5,7,11,15, or 23 flowers in a fully formed umbellaster, because, as dichasial cymes, umbellasters branch according to a simple repeated process. Dichasial cyme refers, by way of its Greek etymology (cyma or wave, chasial as in chasm or gape) to the algorithm generating the fractal geometry of the umbellaster: Successive waves of flowers branch out in pairshence the di- prefixfrom beneath the flowers of the preceding wave. If we take the basic or degenerate case as 1-flowered, the next combination in the series is generated by a pair of flowers being initiated from the base of this first flower. Subsequent combinations are generated by further pairs of flowers 44

arising from the bases of flowers that were initiated in the previous combination. The next complete combination after the 1-flowered case has 3 flowers. From each of the bases of the 2 new flowers, 2 more arise to give a total of 7. From the bases of the latest 4, 2 more each arise to give 15. This gives a sequence of 1,3,7,15… as familiar to any mathematician as 2n – 1. It is a formula that haunts all of nature as, I suspect, it would haunt all possible natures—or at least the ones where they have set theory and logic. In the cases of 5, 11 and 23-flowered combinations, new flowers have been initiated from only half the available locationsa dichasial cyme being built by 2 monochasial branchings. Of course, to confuse casual observers, it is common for some of the buds to abort or drop or be dislodged, thus obscuring the underlying order. Eucalypts are experts at disguising their underlying symmetry and order. Because the flowers all branch out from the same point, rather than along the length of a stalk, the cyme is said to be compressed. Different flower numbers in different species arises from natural selection tweaking the algorithm. The local eucalypts mostly seem to have 7 flowers per umbellaster. Sometimes 11. I can’t help but expect some ingenious numerical or numerological function lies in this fact, that it is a small sign encrypting a design that exceeds human explanation; and I find it somewhat disappointing to conclude that it is may well be an evolutionary concomitant of other adaptations, say optimal presentation of flowers to pollinators, given a particular bud size and the inherited branching mechanism. Yet although this at first strikes me as a bland adaptationist rationalization, I offer it as a provisional shorthand or cipher in the hope that it may stand for inscrutable events lost in the depths of time, just as the simple and beautiful number of flowers at once indicates and occults the excess of history and incident involved in its generation and distillation precisely by its timeless and perfect mathematical end. The most prominent parts of the flowers are the stamens. Because an umbellaster is a compressed cyme, all the flowers are at the same level on their main supporting stalk and the stamens taken together present a kind of pompom for brushing pollen onto foraging birds, bats, bees and beetles. Other myrtles like the paperbarks and bottlebrushes do something similar, presenting their stamens in their own versions of pompoms. Eucalyptus flowers don’t appear to have petals at all. Nor do they appear to have sepalssepals being the row of petal-like bracts that are attached to most flowers immediately below the petals. As it turns out, the distinctive little cap that falls off an opening eucalypt bud is made of the fused petals or sepals. This cap is called the calyptra, eu-calypt being Greek for ‘well capped’. The size and shape of the calyptras can help in identification. Red gums have long, pointy cones like dunces caps; blackbutts, white mahoganies, blue gums and flooded gums have those classic acuminate or rostrate hemispheres, like the tops of tiny minarets. This pointed cupolasometimes with a bulbous basemight at first seem to be an overelaboration of the dome’s spherical perfection. It has capped Islamic buildings since the 8th century, worked its way up into the Austria via the Moorish 45

architecture of Spain, shed snow from the domes of Russian churches, orientalized Victorian follies, bonneted gumnut babes and advertised postmodern mallsoften with connotations of excess. The utilitarian eucalypts though discovered its pragmatic virtues millions of years ago; and they still do it to perfection, engineering it in miniature and in abundance all through the bush. Fashioned by evolution from the petals and sepals that nature had on hand, it is a neat shape for packing down long stamens ready to flex out as soon as the cap is lifted. Once shed and sprinkled like little seashells over the forest floor, the design still asks to be used. So bulldog and jumping ants stack them over their mounded nests. They shed weather, warn passers by of the fierce inhabitants, and please the eye. Different eucalypts, different calyptras. Angophora flowers actually hold on to their 5 petals and so have long been excluded from the Eucalyptus genus. Bloodwoods have two calyptras, one of fused petals and one of fused sepals, but they are in fact more closely related to the angophoras than they are to the rest of the eucalypts, and at the end of the 20th century they were split off into a genus of their own, Corymbia. Blue gums, flooded gums, grey gums, swamp mahoganies and grey ironbarks have two calyptras, and they belong to the largest group of eucalypts, the Symphiomyrtusa group of over 300 species. Blackbutts and white mahoganies belong to the second largest group, the Monocalyptus (over 120 species) and they have a single calyptra of fused sepals. Tallowwoods don’t have a completely fused calyptra. Theylike Eucalyptus guilfoylei in Western Australiahave free sepals and only partly fused petals, and you can see the suture lines along the junctions. They are on their own in their own group, the Nothocalyptusfrom the Greek nothos meaning ‘mock’ or ‘illegitimate’ or ‘bastard’. In genealogy, they are thought to have branched off the Symphiomyrtus line some time after it had branched from the Monocalyptus. Meanwhile, all these eucalypts in the strict sensethe Monocalyptus, Symphiomyrtus and Nothocalyptusshare a more recent common ancestor than they do with the bloodwoods and angophoras, which had already branched off the family tree long before. It is hard to make a strong case for ecological preferences based on the subgenus that a gum belongs too. It is said that the Monocalyptus tend to be able to exploit the poorer soils, and certainly blackbutt can live on sand and the impoverished soils of the local ridges as long as the soils and rock allow the extensive root penetration that the trees rely on to mine enough nutrients. White mahoganies may need a bit richer substrate but they can live where the root penetration is limited. Monocalyptus are not so renowned for drought resistance, but at least here in the wet subtropics where droughts are not so severe, the blackbutts must be numbered among the tall forest trees that thrive on the drier sites. They also seem to be particularly allied to fire, partly because they, like other Monocalyptus, are intolerant of soil fungi. The local Symphiomyrtus are on the better soils, displaying a preference that is supposed to typify the subgenus; and most seem to be able to occasionally germinate and survive without fire, suggesting that they share a Symphiomyrtus tolerance for 46

soil microorganisms. They are seldom called on to display the drought tolerance for which the subgenus is renowned, but then in dry times when everything can look pretty sad, I can hardly recall having seen a local eucalypt look anything but happy. Most of the adaptations for fire, drought, moisture, soil type and successful germination are variations on common themes that have appeared here and there throughout the eucalypt family tree. Separate eucalypt lineages have converged at similar solutions to commonly encountered ecological problems. Adaptations for these ecological functions have evolved separately in various branches of the eucalyptus genus with the result that using such features as the basis for differentiation of subgenerathat is for the differentiation of the branches of the family treeis unreliable. The homologous features in the eucalyptshomologous features being those shared traits that are the result of and indicate direct ancestral and genetic relationsneed not be those that are most obviously adaptations for the ecological nuances of fire, drought, soil, and moisture. Although regulated by somewhat arcane conventions of naming and priority, taxonomythe classification of plants or animalsis now primarily a matter of drawing a family tree. Working out genealogy though is not always a simple task when the only records that ancestors have left are those written in the physical features of their now living descendents. Species have long been identified and classified by careful scrutiny of such features, and there have always been concerns about which were the most reliable features. Throughout the history of taxonomy, features that may have been useful for identification and classification have not always proven to be useful for classification based on evolutionary genealogy; and, of course, the ideas of evolutionary biology, their importance for classification and of the very historicity of nature itself have undergone quite turbulent social evolution since the 18th century. Through most of this period, taxonomists have had to erect their systems on shifting foundations. As far as identification went, Ferdinand von Mueller, one of the first systematic European botanists to make Australia his home and to devote the time and energy needed to study the eucalypts, argued that dried specimens of collected flowers and fruits sent back to the herbariums of Europe for classification were, in the absence of bark samples, likely to be misleading. Although he had wanted to do the definitive work on eucalypts himself, Mueller could not extricate himself from his interests in Australia, and, in those days, Australia was deemed too remote from botanical society to satisfy the arcana of taxonomy. Mueller was just too busy doing eucalypt biology in Australia to go and be the authority on it somewhere else. He sent specimens to England to another botanist, George Bentham, who never visited Australia. Acknowledging the limitations of classification from afar, and his debt to Mueller, Bentham compiled descriptions of 134 different species of Eucalyptus and published them in 1866 in the third volume of Flora Australiensis. Mueller himself worked on his ambitious Eucalyptographia, a ‘Descriptive Atlas’ of the genus, and along with Joseph Maiden after him, helped produce a classification 47

system based to a large extent on descriptions of the anthers, the pollen receptacles on the ends of those long eucalypt stamens. Meanwhile, the implications of evolutionary theory were becoming increasingly important, especially for classification based on genealogical relations. It became apparent that using combinations of several featuresincluding leaf veins, seed shape, and calyptrawas necessary for classification into groups based on the principle of shared recent common ancestry. These features were a better guide than height, bark, drought resistance or lignotubers, all of which had evolved independently in different branches of the family tree. In the absence of molecular analysis though, it took taxonomists a lot of work, and a lot of argument, to establish what features and combinations of features were the most reliable indicators of shared ancestry, and why. Now, when physical observation extends to the molecular level and to inferring differences in the genetic codes for features rather than just differences in the features themselves, genetic relations can be established to a high degree of likelihood. Yet, as with human genealogy, questions remain about just where to draw the line when separating and naming the lineages of a family tree, so there are conventions to assist in making determinations that are as arbitrary as the naming codes in a patrilineal society. Once the branches of the tree are determined, questions arise about precisely how the branches of the family tree are arranged and how the arrangements should be namedwhether for example there are lineages branching off common ancestors nested within larger branches; and how names should correspond to such arrangements whether for example the members of a named group should all be descended from a common ancestor which is also a member of the group, and in turn, if such a group is split into two or more groups, which of the new groups should retain the old name. In this last case, the group to which the originally described specimen belongs retains the name by dint of priority. Unlike the lumpers, who would like to call everything Eucalyptuseven the angophoras and bloodwoodsthere have long been splitters around who would like to divide the dynasty of eucalypts into smaller branches. Mightier than the chainsaw, a stroke of the taxonomists pen can denude large tracts of country of their eucalypts. That is how, in the 1990s, the bloodwoods disappeared from the forests of Eucalyptus. The same could happen to hundreds of Acacia speciesgone from the bush forever and replaced by the Racosperma, the old name that the likes of Bentham and Mueller used for them. The first eucalypt specimen to be given a modern scientific name was red bloodwood. In the 18th century the Swedish botanist Carl von Linné proposed a system in which a species was to be designated by the name of its genus (e.g. Eucalyptus) followed by the name that designates the specieshence, Eucalyptus gummifera. Though his binomial system was adopted, the arch namer himself is best known by one nameLinnaeus. Daniel Solander, Joseph Banks’ Swedish assistant and a student of Linnaeus, applied the name Metrosideros gummifera to a specimen of red bloodwood found while the Endeavour was at Botany Bay in 1770. It looked like it belonged to the 48

Metrosideros, a genus of South Pacific myrtles that includes the New Zealand pohutakawa. Now planted extensively along the urbanized NSW coast, Pohutakawa has flowers that look very like a red eucalypt blossom. However there are many howevers: Red bloodwood had a D’harawal namepossibly Terri’yergro (Hay, 5); Solander did not actually call it Eucalyptus gummifera; the name he used, Metrosideros gummifera, was misapplied because Solander mistook the genus, and besides, the name and a description were never published and therefore the species was not named according to the procedure demanded by convention; when a description was at last published, the official name used was Eucalyptus gummifera; and, as it has turned out, red bloodwood is no longer Eucalyptus gummifera anywayit’s now Corymbia gummifera. Red bloodwood is either a catalogue of misnomers or a wealth of aliases. The only name that stuck from Bank’s and Solander’s efforts was gum, and, indeed, red bloodwood is not a gum in the strict sense of a smooth-barked tree. The two botanists noticed that a red, water-soluble gum was commonly exuded from wounds on tree trunks and that it congealed on the bark into rough crystals of kino. They gave the general label ‘gum’ to all the trees that exuded itthe eucalypts, the angophoras and the bloodwoodsand from the beginnings of the penal colony in 1788, the term was adopted as the common common name. The classic smooth-barked, kino-exuding gum that Banks and Solander saw at Botany Bay and that First Fleeters saw at Sydney Cove wasn’t a Eucalyptus either. It was Angophora. One of the Monocalyptus group is Messmate or Eucalyptus obliqua, a tall, stringy-barked, forest tree on the cold, high basalt country west of Dorrigo, the country that looks down on the headwaters of the Bellinger. In 1777 David Nelson, a botanist on Cook’s fateful third voyage collected some Messmate from wind sheared trees much further south at sea level on Bruny Island just off the coast of Van Diemen’s Land. After his return to Europe the specimens sat in the British Museum where they were eventually examined by a French magistrate and botanist, Charles Louis l’Heritier de Brutelle. L’Heritier published his description of Eucalyptus obliqua in late 1788. This was the first published naming and description of the genus. By this time Nelson had returned to the Pacific as Bligh’s botanist on the Bounty, charged with the duty of selecting and tending breadfruit specimens. Nelson had been able to introduce the officers and crew of the Bounty to the Tahitians, with whom he was already acquainted. Apparently Tahitians, the mutineers and Bligh’s supporters all respected him. Six months after L’Heritier’s publication however, Nelson chose loyalty to the Bounty’s commander and he ended up in the long boat with Bligh and 17 others on their 6000km journey across the Pacific, around Cape York, and on to Timor. Nelson was the oldest member of the party. He came down with a fever just before the end of the voyage and he died shortly after making landfall. If ever the eucalypts were to be split into a number of generaand it has been suggestedthen, by right of priority, messmate and its immediate kind, the subgenus Monocalyptus, would win the

49

sole rights to the name Eucalyptus, and I suppose we would be calling flooded gums symphiomyrtles and tallowwoods nothocalypts. Priority of naming is one thing, priority of the thing named, another. The eucalypts probably first appeared about 55 million years ago, at the beginning of the Tertiary period, not long after the extinction of dinosaurs. There is fossil evidence of eucalyptus from Patagonia and New Zealand as well as Australia. Piecing together the history of the genus though is risky. Even the history of piecing the history together is clouded; contemporary paleobotanists have expressed skepticism about past collection, documentation and identification of fossils purported to be Eucalyptus (Hill, 411). 24 million years ago, by the beginning of the Miocene epoch in the mid-Tertiary, Eucalyptus and the related myrtlesbottlebrushes (Callistemon), paperbarks (Melaleuca), and teatrees (Leptospermum)had emerged with their typical woody fruits, hard leaves and showy stamens, and they had started to radiate across the continent. Nothofagus (southern beech) and pines like the auraucarias, Podocarpus and Dacrydium were widespread throughout the great tracts of southern rainforest. They grew with subtropical and tropical species too, forming rainforests perhaps without any precise likeness among modern forest types. Nothofagus still grows in refuges today. It grows with those Messmates up on the moist edges of the high Dorrigo escarpment covered in dripping moss and felt ferns and orchids. Araucarias grow on the Dorrigo too in the warm temperate hoop pine rainforest that is so typical of the eastern plateau. When I try to imagine the old southern rainforests I picture the Eastern Dorrigo. As the climate cooled and dried, these rainforests started to be broken up by more open forests and grasslands. Casuarinas became a feature with their wiry feathery branchlets, and acacias too started to appear. Dacrydiums such as Huon pine are now gone from mainland Australia altogether, finally exiting to Tasmania only during the last glacial period when human technology had already made the continent much more fiery. The only Podocarpus now in the Bellinger Valley is the plum pine, with its resiny, gelatinous blue fruits, growing in the lowland subtropical and littoral rainforests. In the Miocene, the rainforests still dominated but the climate was changing and grasses and sclerophyll species (like the eucalypts), whose hard leaves may well have been initially an adaptation of rainforest ancestors to low soil nutrients, were gradually finding patches of dry country to their advantage. This was the beginning of the great and enduring division of the hard leaved sclerophyll forest from the softer mesophyll rainforests. Here in the Bellinger valley I need only walk 100 metres from where I am writing to see it still written on the bush. 2 million years ago, by the end of the Tertiary period, the highlands of the Great Divide had been pushed up, creating enough topographic variation to isolate populations. There was a mosaic of soils of varying texture and fertility, and the continent was undergoing a long drying process that proceeded in fluctuations driven by glacial expansion and contraction at the Earth’s poles. These were the conditions with which natural selection worked on the incipient eucalypts, although even then the genus was still only one player among many 50

in the long drama. While the rainforests contracted and expanded in a gradual withdrawal to the moistest refugia, grassy sclerophyll woodlands and forests of casuarina, acacia, southern cypress pines (Callitris), and eucalypts (among the other myrtles) extended their dominion, expanding and contracting in complementary fluctuationssometimes isolating populations, sometimes bringing them back together. Tree lines moved up and down mountains causing similar periodic isolation. Rainfall zones and fire regime areas would shrink and fragment then regrow and rejoin. Changes from one kind of soil landscape to anothervolcanic to metamorphic to sandy sedimentary to alluvialisolated populations as well. Unless a number of individuals of a speciesa populationis isolated from the rest, it is a bit tricky for the natural genetic variation that arises during evolutionary history to be preferentially selected and so result in the adaptational differentiation of the descendents of that population from the descendents of its cut-off, sister populations. If the descendents of populations that are beginning to branch from one another interbreed, their genes all flow together again into one pool. All the individuals remain as one breeding population, and one lineage. Although each step of natural selection may be simple, the resultant process of evolution is not. There are different views on how species can and do diverge, and, for that matter, on just what a species is. Given the climatic changes and the variations in topography and soil, it is generally thought that the eucalypt species have differentiated from each other by spatial isolation of populations, followed by generation of new features and then selection of these features as adaptations in each of the different isolated environments. Such a process is called allopatric evolution, as opposed to the trickier sympatric evolution, in which a parent species differentiates into separate lineages in the absence of spatial barriers to gene flow. Allopatric differentiation of eucalypt lineages has been going on all through the great environmental fluctuations of the late Tertiary and down into the Quaternary, the present period that began less than 2 million years ago. During the Quaternary the glaciers at the earth’s poles have expanded and contracted in 20 cycles or warming and cooling, 9 in the last 700,000 years. With each glacial cycle, isolated eucalypt populations diverged from one another genetically and in their physiological features. Some were adapted to poorer soils, some to richer soils, some to sand, some to heavy clay, some to severe cold and frosts, some to wet feet, some to periodic inundation, some to salt, some to long dry periods, some to fires that were rare or cool, some to fires frequent or hot. More and more combinations of these features were expressed over a growing range of new species. When glaciers contracted to the poles during warmer periods, some eucalypt populations with common ancestors may well have been brought back together. They may well have started interbreeding, but their descendents may also have been less fit compared to the separate lineages. Hybrid crosses of modern eucalypt species are said to be common and as individuals they may well be vigorous trees. I am a bit skeptical about reports of hybrids, but not when I am looking at stringybarks in the 51

tablelands. Every stingybark up there can look like a mixture of species, which is a measure of either my inexperience or their promiscuity. Blue gums hybridize with bangalays and, some say, flooded gums. In the 1980s, the tropical bloodwood, cadagi, was the subject of a strange planting fad in the coastal subtropics. While postmodern real estate developers were besotted by the instant tropicana of progress palms (Arecastrum ramanzoffianum), plonking them around every urban subdivision, golf course, resort, mall, motel and service station, mainstream modern reafforesters were equally smitten by the fast-growing, big-flowering gum with the tropical rainforest cachet. Cadagi then became a new feral, pollinated by flying foxes and with a sticky seed spread by (of all culprits) the amiable native bee, Trigona carbonaria (Low, 2002, 195). Little and stingless, the social Trigona still manages to stuff the odd gum tree hollow with waxen blobs of raw honey, despite being harassed by the feral honey bee. Cadagi has now apparently hybridized with a local bloodwood, the northern spotted gumto the detriment of the spotted gums’ timber quality and the chagrin of foresters. Even so, hybrids often prove less fertile in seed production, or the seedlings of hybrid parents prove less hardy, so selection may still end up favouring the distinct species. The most famous environmental pressure on eucalypt selection has been fire. On no genus of trees has fire quite written its meanings with such variety and eloquence as on eucalypts. Different types of fire have selected different adaptations in different species of eucalyptus, and, as fire and eucalypts have worked in cahoots, the eventual continental dominance of fire has corresponded with the dominance of eucalypts over other species. Until as recently as 130,000 years ago, during the last interglacial period, eucalypts still had to share the stage in the drier open communities with less fire hardy species like the casuarinas and callitris. Fire from lightning ignited vegetation that had been dried out by drought, but grassy forests and woodlands of the more fire sensitive sclerophyll generacasuarina, callitris and acaciawere still widespread. Rainforest species, as well as forming rainforest proper, probably occurred in mixed plant communities with these same more fire sensitive sclerophyll species. Such forests of casuarina and callitris still occur today. Stands of river oaks (Casuarina cunninghamiana) still line streams like the Bellinger and broaden out over wide gravel beds; swamp oak forests (Casuarina glauca) spread out beyond the salt marshes and onto the sweeter soils of the estuarine fringes; Port Jackson cypress pines (Callitris rhomboidea) grow with banksias, black oaks (Casuarina littoralis) and Dorrigo white gums around some of the headwaters of the Nymboida catchment. Each community is likely to slowly accumulate an understorey and then maybe a dominance of rainforest species. In the Bellinger valley you still see impressive river oaks poking their crowns above riverine rainforest, and swamp oaks and coast banksias (Banksia integrifolia) above littoral rainforest. Even more impressive are the fat mountain banksias (also Banksia integrifolia) making a last effort to keep their crowns above an engulfing temperate rainforest up on the ranges. These though are mementos of an earlier era. Nowadays this understorey of 52

colonizing rainforest flora usually occurs with eucalypts in what, here along the east coast, is the distinctive wet sclerophyll forest. Every eucalypt species in this ridge country can at some stage find itself emerging from a rainforest, its enduring form the last vestige of a fire or some other long forgotten disturbance. Still, back when casuarinas and callitris maintained wide dominion, fire was already common enough to have become a major selection pressure on eucalypt evolution. Features like woody fruits, preferences for sunny terrain and bare soil and fungus-free seedbeds, the habit of dropping tons of flammable litter, the release of seed after the drying out of fruits, the ability to re-shoot from lignotubers and epicormic budsdormant buds on the old woodwere all useful where periodic fires struck. Those who are uneasy about saying eucalypts are adapted to fireas if nothing could rightly be said to live like the alchemists’ salamander thriving in the midst of flamethose who prefer to hedge their claims by saying that ‘no species is adapted to fire per se (Benson & Redpath, 322)’ are not saying something that applies only to adaptations for fire. In evolution, nothing much is adapted to anything much per se. Evolution is always a matter of using designs that are on hand; selection always confers the functional status of a design retrospectively. Lignotubers are woody underground stems that store resources and that are capable of re-shooting should the above ground parts of the plant be killed. Lignotubers were useful for other things besides fire. Just what their original function was is anybody’s guess. As is typical of natural selection, a feature initially selected for one function is there for the taking should it turn out to be useful for satisfying a new need or exploiting a new opportunity. Features that had probably been selected for the assistance they gave in the increasingly common dry, cold and infertile country of the Tertiary and Quaternary periods, found new functions. Most but not all eucalypts have lignotubers. Species that do, have found them useful as reserves when drought has withered their foliage or when herbivores or frosts eat them back to the ground. They turned out be useful when fire burned them back too. Woody fruits protect seed from many predators, and from dry conditions until an opportunity for likely germination arises. They also protect seed from fire. And once fire starts to act as a selection pressure on eucalypt fruits it starts to select certain fruiting features. Low shrubby eucalypts often have bigger seed capsules. Being closer to the ground they have to withstand closer, hotter flames. The tall moist forest eucalypts like tallowwood, blue gum and flooded gum have small fruits. Tallowwood fruits are almost fleshy rather than woody. Blackbutts and white mahoganies have slightly bigger and woodier fruits, and there are tribes with quite large fruits. These species sometimes grow in tall moist forestblackbutts can reach 70 metresbut they often grow in drier more fire prone places too, and those that do tend to have the larger fruits. Nearly all eucalypts are adapted to fire in some way, but there is no typical eucalypt response to fire because there is no typical fire. It is received wisdom that the bush needs fire, or eucalypts need fire, but these platitudes are such 53

appalling simplifications that they might as well just be described as wrong. Eucalypt ecology is nothing if not diverse, surprising, mysterious and defiant of banal claims. Fierce it may be, but fire has its nuances in different seasons, different times of day, different weather, different terrain, different vegetation, or different eucalypts. It might be lit by lightning, by intentions wise and foolish, or by events accidental, arbitrary or unknown. It might crawl down into a cool gully and just stop in its tracks. It might kindle in sticks, flare in grass and die in rainforest. It might send up smoke from a spot, pool it for weeks in a valley, or turn the sky brown and the sun pink. It might brood out in distant ranges and glow red at night along the ridges. It might flame up a spur, climb like the devil into the forest crown, blast firebrands and ember clouds across rivers, highways and suburbs in wild summer wind. It might rise up to become the weather as such, the volatile air alight, and as pure infernal storm sweep like an angel torching the innocent, passing-over the lucky, or persevering to torture the hapless and reduce them to nothing. It is a mongrel of the stochastic, the determinate, and the non-linear. Sometimes it just leaves a charred ground cover, sometimes a canopy of singed brown leaves, sometimes black stumps and white ash. Sometimes it colour codes the changes in topography, black on the ridges, brown on the spurs, green in the gullies. Otherwise the colours might trace the brush of wind or the fluky contours of strange mathematical attractors. The nuances of catastrophe are reflected in the adaptations of the different species of eucalypts, and fire history gets printed in the patterns of different species that grow where fire has behaved differently. Depending on how they recover from fire, eucalypts are often loosely differentiated into sprouters and seeders, but they run the range between the two. Any given species can employ a range of adaptations, depending on the rigours of the fire. Sprouting new leaves, whether from underground lignotubers or from epicormic buds protected under the thick bark of the trunks, is an adaptation for leaf loss, whether caused by herbivores, drought, frost, or fire. Most of the eucalypts around here resprout after most fires. A season after burning, young tallowwoods have sprouted all the way from their lignotubers up to the top of the pole. They form their own cylinder of foliage. After the same fire blue gums have struggled just managing to refoliate their highest branches and having to shed dangerously thick plates of scorched bark. The bloodwoods and forest blackbutts along the highway this year have tarred trunks and branches closely feathered with leaves, and they pass like lines of black dancers waving green plumes and cropped tassels. Shorter blackbutts on sandy coastal dunes can look like malleesshrubs with several stems that sprout from a lignotuber. On the big forest ones, the butts stay black for years as the crown re-establishes that signal eucalypt shape: tufts of curved leaves filtering light way out on the end of wiry, radiating branches. The seeders are so called because they tend to rely on seed for regeneration. Trees can be killed by fire. It depends on fire intensity, it depends on species, it depends on age, it depends on whether they have been hollowed out by termites and burn fiercely from the inside out like a burning chimney or whether fire 54

sweeps by them in a rush. They can be effectively ringbarked, and if they have no epicormic buds below the ring, or no lignotuber they die. Old age can reduce the likelihood of a tree’s having epicormic buds. Or sometimes one side has already been burnt out by a previous fire, and if the other side goes the tree dies. All eucalypts must be seeders eventually, and most are sowing seeds as well as resprouting, but those most obliged to rely on seed after fires are those least likely to survive the fires that burn through their forest and they have to be able to produce seed before the next killer fire. These species often occur in moister forests that are less frequently burnt. They produce a lot of wood and a lot of sticks, and when they do burn it can be as fierce as bushfire gets. Flooded gums are mainly seeders. They grow in moist forest; unlike their cousins the blue gums, they are one of the dozen or so eucalypts that don’t have lignotubers; and they are less likely than most eucalypts to re-sprout after a fire. Like most eucalypts they require a seedbed that has had the litter removed, otherwise the seedlings are susceptible to attack from microorganisms in the litter and soil. They also need sunny locations. Like all the local wet forest eucalypts, they do not thrive as seedlings under an existing canopy of their parents. Woody fruits that dry out, open their valves and release their seed, may be adapted for an area where a rainy season is preceded by hot dry weather. The same feature works when spring fire opens gumnuts before summer rain. The seeds of the tall local eucalypts are shed in hot, dry weather, or from broken branches, but they get eaten by insects, or otherwise fail to germinate. If they fall on bare open ground, with only a bit of grass they might germinate and survive, but rarely. After a big fire, the chances that the seed will drop on a sunny, litter-free, fungus-free, ash-fertilized seedbed, are pretty high. Then they can germinate in great numbers. A lot can survive, grow vigorously and compete with one another. After 10 years and 20 metres a few have won dominance, still dense as hairs on a dogs back, their crowns still pointy or monopodial, and in need of thinning to a forester’s eye. They shoot for the sun and jettison dead sticks like giant’s spears as they go. After 50 or 100 years they are big hard poles, some now skewy, still self-thinning, the crowns spreading into uneven sympodial arches. They are flowering and fruiting, still growing, dropping heavy limbs now and just starting to form hollows worthy of a bird or mammal. In the absence of fire, some kind of disturbance is needed that removes canopy and presents bare mineral soil to the suna landslip, erosion or deposition, drought, or a bulldozer. Otherwise, in the wet climate, under the shady canopy and with mouldy litter, only the rainforest species germinate, perhaps to thrive, perhaps to struggle. Every time I make some careless remark about eucalypts and fire going together, someone, rightly, cites a counter example. They have seen eucalypts establishing in pasture grass on a slashed ridge, or in an old banana plantation, or on a slip, or where a road went through, or on flood silt, or on soil made bare by a long dry. They could even, as far as I am concerned, cite plantations, which are, in the big picture just another form of natural regeneration for those 55

species that have turned out to be adapted to the particular selection pressures prevailing in modern silvicultural environments. Without underestimating the self-perpetuating dominance of the eucalypts in the fire regimes of Quaternary Australia, I suspect that the cherished view of eucalypts exclusively as fire trees underestimates them and ignores at least four things that are very important in the success of eucalypts. 1. The long time of a eucalypt’s lifemuch longer than the puny time of casual human observation, which can hastily conclude that the poor eucalypts are not regenerating without that ‘good burn’. (They can wait.). 2. The unrivalled dominance of eucalypts in size, height, and nutrient use (They make it hard for others to get what they need.). 3. Their incumbency and their numbers (Incumbency is the first step in persistence). 4 Their patient and ever-ready opportunism (They are always prepared). There are many species of eucalypt, and, very few utterly dependent on fire. When people talk about eucalypts needing fire they like to cite one famous species: the mountain ash of Victoria and Tasmaniathe tallest species of all and the one that most dramatically combines big wet forests with huge fires and massive single-age seedling regeneration. But it is only one species of many. The closest Bellinger analogue might be flooded gum. People seem to like calling them fireweeds, bestowing with fond irony the disparaging title of ‘weed’ on such a dominant tree. Eucalypts are fireweedspioneers of scorched earthbut very long-lived ones. In a long life opportunities for fire-free germination become highly likely. Give them an opportunity only once in 200 years and they will dominate like tyrants for another 200, making life difficult for many other species, especially when soils and rainfall can be less than generous. Then, so given to manufacturing dry fuel, they will keep on making fire conditions useful for their own succession yet again. Eucalypts and fire stack the odds in each other’s favour. Yet to say that they and fire go together is vague rhetoric and it should not be used to imply the necessity of fire. Strictly, eucalypts don’t need fire, and if you have eucalypts, fire need not follow nor need there have been a fire in the past. But then again, nature was never big on necessity, just contingency, and the eucalypts have had that sown up.

We might look at the flowering and fruiting of the different local gums and expect to see adaptations to different environmental requirements expressed thereinwe might assume the importance of reproduction is likely to be expressed dramatically in different flowers and fruits. However flowering and fruiting traits can seem poorly differentiated between the gums, their functions indistinct or cryptic. This is really not surprising in such a closely related group of speciesnot when the inherited floral and fruiting designs may work in a variety of different predicaments, and especially not when you consider that floral similarity and fruiting similarity epitomize the features that taxonomists traditionally used to ascertain familial relations. Like so much of the continent, the local forests are nectar forests. Nutrients may be in short supply but sunlight isn’t and these forests pump enough photosynthesized sugar around in sap and 56

nectar to feed a host of mammals, birds and insects: gliders, possums, flying foxes, honeyeaters, parrots, lorikeets, bees, cicadas, lerps. The myrtles as a family and the eucalypts as their dominant genus feed a lot of creatures, and in many cases they trade off nectar for pollination. In the case of flowering, it is the obvious variations on the common theme, in particular the variations in flowering time and nectar, that seem to attract most casual speculation about ecological functions. Here in the ridge country of the Bellinger, most of the eucalyptsflooded gum, blue gum, swamp mahogany, grey ironbark, tallowwood, white mahogany and pink bloodwoodflower more or less annually. Grey gums only seem to flower every second year. All these species get their budding and flowering over within one year, and their fruits ripen into woody capsules over the next. The tallowwoods put on a reliable display, most years between spring and early summer, but they are stingy with nectar and can probably afford the show. Flying foxes, honeyeaters and lorikeets can’t be bothered with them. There is not a lot of nectar around at all during this time and honeyeaters lick nectar from the mistletoes that parasitize the eucalypts. Flying foxes may find themselves driven to dependence upon ripening fruit in orchards. In the tallowwoods, insects have to do the work of pollination. Even so, a botanizing friend was once kept awake at night camping with his children under a tallowwood full of flying foxes. Perhaps, like many of my ‘tallowwoods’, it was a white mahogany. Down in the wetlands, where water is seldom too scarce, the swamp mahoganies can afford to be generous most wintersas can the forest red gums, in early spring, on the estuarine flats. The birds and bats rely on regular nectar-producing species like these. The wide roaming bats can exploit species that flower at irregular times too. Coast angophoras, for instance, are irregular flowerers, but when they do flower during the odd early summer their bark peels like sun burnt skin and they pile their flowers on their crowns like dollops of zinc cream. Their cousins, the pink bloodwoods, pile their flowers on too, but with yearly regularity, here in the luxurious late summer after the rainy season has arrived, and they and the flying foxes lap up the luxury. Blackbutt flowering is another story. While most species flower at set seasons, you might see a blackbutt flowering in any month of the year. The heaviest flowering seems to have two peaks, one in February and one between May and July (Law et al, 2000). The actual process of floweringfrom the formation of the tiny pin buds to full bloomusually takes more than 2 years. It may take more than 5. Eucalypts elsewhere do this too. Being able to hold flowering until rain sets off full bud development may be an adaptation to the continent’s cycles of drought. Good local flowering often comes 9 to 12 months after good rain. In most species, it is not always obvious though just what the best predictor of flowering is. Low temperatures prior to budding seem roughly to predict flower abundance in tallowwoods, white mahoganies and blackbutts. El Niño events three years before flowering have been correlated with abundant flowering in flooded gums and blue gums, but a precise causal connection here seems a bit tenuous. El Niño corresponds with dry years, so maybe the 57

flowering is initiated by the wetter La Niña seasons that follow. White mahoganies, blackbutts, tallowwoods and grey gums can hold onto their buds and flower after a low fire; they can also flower within three years of a fire that scorches their crowns. White mahoganies and blackbutts actually seem to flower well in places where there has been relatively frequent firing; tallowwoods and flooded gums don’t. In the case of the fruits, apart from the size and woodiness of capsules, a close look at the seed can sometimes be revealing. In late January the pink bloodwoods bloom in soft corymbs, like cream over their outer foliage. Around here, they are scattered everywhere through the hardwood forests. Down on the coast they grow in strips of woodland behind the coastal dunes. Look at a ridge in the distance and the flowering bloodwood crowns look like flecks and dollops thrown here and there among the rest. They have bigger gumnuts and bigger seeds than most of the local eucalypts. What is most distinctive though is that they, like many other bloodwoods have winged seeds. The bloodwoods are a mainly tropical genus. They grow in the northern woodlands where grassy understoreys burn frequently during the dry seasonbut not so fiercely as to burn the canopy trees to the ground. Pink bloodwoods are very like the red bloodwoods that so often growand with much less of a scatteralongside the coast angophoras in the dry sclerophyll forest on sandy country like that of the coastal dunes or the Hawkesbury sandstone. In both species the pink wood is insinuated with seams of red kino. Pink bloodwoods occur more often in the tall moist forests, up here, further north. They grow as short trees in the coastal woodlands as well as taller forest trees here in the gullies. This might explain why they, like the reds, have been selected to maintain large, almost identical fruits as an adaptation: both species need to protect seeds from close flames. The shortly fibrous, tiled bark on the pink bloodwoods’ trunks might look a little softer and pinker to some eyes than red bloodwood bark, and it extends further along the small branches. The surest way to tell the difference between the two species though is to look at the seeds. Like Eucalyptus seeds, red bloodwood seeds are not winged. Most of the eucalypts in the Bellinger forests, have small fruits with little seeds like grains of sand. You can collect gumnuts, put them in a paper bag to dry out, and after a day or two, the valves open and release the seed. This is the way to collect seed from any of the eucalypts, angophoras and bloodwoods. The ripe seeds that have formed after the ovules in the flowers are fertilized spill out in amongst what is mainly ‘chaff’the left overs of sterile or unfertilized ovules. If you sow the seed and chaff under a very thin cover of soil and keep things moist, the tiny seedlings with their kidney shaped cotyledons will peep up after a couple of weeks or so. They are easy to grow. When tallowwoods, blue gums, flooded gums or blackbutts drop seeds from fruit drying out on their brancheswhether from dry times, or from fallen trees or branches, or after firethe seeds scarcely scatter further from the parent than the distance of a crown height. Although I have seen odd seedlings several hundred metres from the nearest potential parents, wind will seldom carry seed far enough to find the 58

right conditions for germination. These species come up best in droves close to parent trees after a disturbance like fire. Some, such as blackbutt and flooded gum, may dominate as almost monocultural, even-aged stands over various kinds of understorey: neat blady grass under regularly fired blackbutts; palmy rainforest under either species if fire is kept at bay for long enough and moisture is reliable. The more mixed forests of tallowwood, blue gum and others, including blackbutt and flooded gum as well, are the result of a mixed history of fires in different years and seasons, of different intensity and extent, of other kinds of pre-germination disturbance, of seedlings competing with resprouting trees under different amounts of defoliated canopy, of browsing swamp wallabies wiping out isolated seedlings, of variation in substrate, soil texture, nutrients, moisture and aspect, and of seed availability dependent upon incumbent parent trees. Pretty well all these species grow at a fast rate, if they find the right conditions. If the soil is heavier and restricts roots, white mahoganies will outstrip blackbutts. If there is a bit too much dappled shade, tallowwoods and bloodwoods may out-compete most others. Where seedlings are frosted, blue gums will grow better than tallowwoods. Where fires burn through young spars tallowwoods may resprout better than blue gums. Flooded gums prefer the lower well-watered sites, but with poor drainage they will yield to pink bloodwood, red gums or swamp mahoganies. If or when longicorn borers then attack them, yellow tale black cockatoos descend on the ailing saplings, chop deep into the wood, the tops snap in the next wind and their lives are overa common fate for some of the plantations on lowland expasture country. On the Bellinger ridge country where slope, aspect, moisture, soil texture and fire conditions can change every few paces, almost anything approaching a birds-eye view looks onto a mixed forest. There has been such a finely tuned selection of the different eucalypt adaptations that they can pick out subtle and cryptic changes across a landscape that outwardly all looks the same. It can make species selection in eucalypt plantations a wonderful mystery, an onerous responsibility or an expensive mistake. Plantings can fail in droves: you do things 90% right, as a grower once said, and they go 100% wrong. Because they are winged, pink bloodwood seeds can float further on the wind. They can carry far enough through or over a forest to find a little gap. They don’t need much open ground. Like their tropical cousins that can persist as seedlings in the understorey of open northern woodlands, they seem to tolerate a little shade as seedlings and germinate even with a little grass and leaf litter lying around. Red bloodwoods, unlike their northern cousins, are so much a part of the southern dry sclerophyll forests that they have not maintained the winged seed, and instead their seed-shape has been selected for the winning strategy of seedling germination in areas cleared by fire. The scatter of pink bloodwoods through the forest here seems to be the result of a seed designed to find germination and seedling conditions that may be scattered intermittently throughout the forest after small disturbances or patchy fires.

59

When the bloodwoods are flowering and the bats fly out from Bellingen Island just on dark, they need not go far to feed. Instead of all streaming up or down the river to stands of ironbarks or paperbarks, their formations quickly break up over the forests as individuals fly low, or circle back looking for blossoms. If you sit out in the forest watching the evening sky change down its colours, in the last light you will see the big soft black wings wafting low over the canopy, and hear themwhopf, whopf, whopf. In nearby bloodwoods you will hear them chatting and grizzling. All night they will be coming and going, talking, arguing, licking nectar from among the stamens, and flying from tree to tree with pollen dusted on their noses. A clamour up close, their cries through the distance and the forest and the warm moonlight and the humid air are muted to a sweet tinkling like little bells signaling the blossoming trees. You can lie in bed and listen to it, against the white noise of the Pacific way off and sounding low like the the shell of the moony sky cupped over the earth. Because most seeds don’t move far, the mother generations are often still to be seen somewhere nearbyunless they have all gone up in fire. The fathers though may be much farther away. Eucalypt pollen is more mobile than its seed, so pollination is the main way that eucalypt genes get a spread on. Some eucalypts have a lot of nectar; bats and birds feed on them and they can transfer pollen anywhere from metres to kilometres. Beetles and bees use both nectar and pollen and have a shorter range. Grey-headed flying foxes can fly from tree to tree, from ridge to ridge and from Bellingen down to the coast or up to Dorrigo and back in a night. They can carry pollen on their furjust as they carry the seeds of rainforest fruits in their mouths and gutover long distances. For all this, and in the absence of good empirical evidence, it seems likely that, as with most dispersal adaptations, the probability of pollen moving long distances is still much less then it is of moving just a short way off. Even so, perhaps some of the eucalypts and bloodwoods have managed to evolve an intimate relation with nectar feeding bats, having emerged from the hot house of eucalypt evolution under selection pressures for species pollinated by long distance night feeders. For instance, the bloodwood and angophora habit of showy flowers at the ends of the leafy branches suggests some adaptation to larger, nectivorous pollinators with good distance or night vision. The limited dispersal range of seed makes long distance genetic dispersal by pollinators a potentially valuable feature if populations are being fragmented by fire or cold or aridity. The last glacial period began about 80,000 years ago. Things got drier and colder over tens of thousands of years. Initially rainforest araucarias like hoop pine expanded their range as dominant trees, perhaps because among rainforest genera they are hardier in cooler, drier conditions. Eucalyptus, casuarina and grasses took over more country too, and between 40,000 and 10,000 years ago, as the glacial period moved to its climax, the rainforest retreated to small refugessmaller than todayand grassy sclerophyll woodlands of eucalypts and casuarinas became dominant. Especially the eucalypts. The araucarias 60

retreated. Bunya pines were forced back to a couple of isolated mountains in Queensland. A handful of Wollemi pines managed to survive in little gullies in the Great Divide behind Sydney, undiscovered by fire, and, until a few years ago, by modernity. As well as the altitudinal movement of treelines and the reduced rainfall, there was increased fire activity. Otherwise there might still now be more casuarina and callitris forest around. Two things happened. First, the eucalypts were able to set up a kind of self-perpetuating regime. Not only did they thrive on fire, fire thrived on them. They make wood when it is wet and shed it as fuel when it is dry. The big moist forest species throw off branches as they grow. The smooth barked gums shed patches or long ribbons of bark every summer. The litter under blackbutts or flooded gums, say, is built as one would build kindling for a fire: fine bark and dry leaves, a lattice of twigs and sticks, dry branches and logs, and plenty of space for oxygen. Second, by 40,000 years ago, we humanscreatures of firehad arrived; and eucalypts were pre-adapted to us. Precisely how much selection of eucalypt adaptations has occurred in that period of occupation is unclear. Species adaptation demands evolutionary timescales and useful genetic variation. 40,000 years, or 80,000 since the beginning of the last glacial expansion is, say, 400 to 2000 tree generations, and although it may be possible to estimate how much random genetic variation can get clocked up in that time, it is more difficult to calculate how much might result in selected adaptations and species differentiation. For the rate of morphological change and speciation is tied to the temporal and geographical peculiarities of population isolation, and the more or less rapidly changing pressures of selection. The Casuarina family has only about 100 species, 65 of them in Australia. Because they disperse their pollen and seed on the wind, species are able to sustain common gene pools over greater distances than the eucalypts. As a result, with less isolation of populations, there has been less differentiation into separate species. As the common names of casuarinas suggestsriver oak, swamp oak, beach oak, forest oaka single species tends to occupy each kind of habitat, wherever that habitat occurs. Like the eucalypts they colonize disturbed sites, although chronic fire disturbance puts a casuarina species at a comparative disadvantage, perhaps to the extent of local extinction in the short term and evolutionary extinction in the long. They do well on mineral soils, and like the acacias they have symbiotic relations with bacteria that fix atmospheric nitrogen. Yet unlike the eucalypts or the acaciasboth of which have less dispersive seed and pollenthe casuarinas have a single species where the other genera may have half a dozen. Here in the Bellinger ridge country, forest oak is encountered in more types of forest than any single eucalypt, or for that matter, any single species of tree except perhaps blackwood. It is the one and only forest casuarina in this ridge country, where there are a dozen eucalypts. Despite the recent peculiar selection pressures of human industry on the eucalypts, it seems most likely that, when brought to bear on a genus with the limited seed and pollen dispersal range, all those glacial cycles over the last 2 million years and more were probably great generators of the diversity of modern eucalypts. Yet, since 61

our arrival, the appointment of forests, scrubs, grasslands and woodlands about the countrythe structures of those communities and the range of species of plants and animals that live in themhas proceeded at a thoroughly social, even if supra-individual timescale. Human technology brought a regular and persistent source of ignition and an intentional consciousness bent upon shaping country according to certain ends. Although still subject to the great temperature and moisture fluctuations of global warming, to the mighty force of a fire nature that could defy all human intention, and to an immemorial process of social evolution that far outlived individual intentions, there was now a cultural as well as a natural history of fire and the eucalypts thrived as if their creation had anticipated its coming. As the continent came out of the last glacial period, about 10,000 years ago, the rainforest crept out again from its small refuges. The long isolation of subpopulations of the various rainforest species still shows up in the genetic dissimilarities within species. It probably also shows in the impoverished biodiversity of modern rainforests. The available suite of rainforest species in a given area is still somewhat less diverse and the community structure less sophisticated than it would be if many more species had had the time or means to move further afield from their ice-age refuges (see Walker, 1990, 27). The accelerated plant movements of modern society demonstrate that many quite restricted and rare rainforest species thrive beyond their pristine 1788 distributions. Some thrive so well that they get labeled ‘environmental weeds’, although they may only be decolorizing country that they lived in before the last ice age. Most characteristic in this recent era of rainforest expansion has been the wet eucalypt forestthe wet sclerophyll forest. Those in the Bellinger are typical of the east coast. Tribes of 20 or so tall eucalypt species tower over an understorey of rainforest species that have managed a slow and halting shift out from their refuges, colonizing moist gullies, southern slopes, and richer soils.

Wet Sclerophyll Forest Ecologists are natural historians as much as they are experimentalists. They can’t help themselves. They are preoccupied by certain stories, each kind with its own timescale: the long history of natural selection; the life history of an organism; and the assembly and development of a community of organisms, like a forest. With brains and words designed for telling stories that occur at the timescale of a human life, we can be perplexed by the transformations of evolutionary time. Failure to think according to evolutionary timescale can bamboozle our chronological nous; it can make people think chickens might have preceded eggs. In evolutionary stories things can be utterly changed in kind, like the metamorphoses of mythology: one species, we say, becomes another. Yet it is all just a matter of the simple repetition of generations, of one life after another, parent and child. 62

The life story of an organism has a neat beginning, middle and end. It has a main character that tells its own story to itself and times it by the internal clock of its own growth and development. This self-reference gives an organism a natural unity. Even so, the life of a eucalypt is almost geological compared to ours, and to that extent a bit difficult for us to grasp. How long does one have to observe a population of eucalypts to get an adequate idea of a typical individual’s development, survival and reproduction? Does one have to see what happens during a slightly drier century or millennium? Almost every organism in the forest is poorly known, but even such an enormous, obvious thing as a tallowwood lives so long that it is very difficult to observe it in all its phases. It might reach 20m tall 10 years after germinating, usually a little slower than a flooded gum or blackbutt, but like all the tall forest eucalypts it can grow fast and in the right place faster than them. It might be 20, or 40 years old when it flowers. It might be 100 or 150 when it develops its first hollow, somewhere for a glider to hide, or a parrot to nest, or even an owl. At 300 or 400 it might be 40m or 50m tallnot the tallest of eucalypts by any meansand 6m or 7m around the base. It will probably be hollow up the centre, a great flue cut by termites after water and fungus have leached and fermented the heartwood long enough to make it palatable. Perhaps the hollow will be plugged with clay, or perhaps, if it can work its way in, charred and fluted by fire. Tall trees, tall stories. Here on the subtropical east coast the tallest eucalypt was said be a 76m flooded gum near Buladelahthe so-called Grandis Tree from Eucalyptus grandis. When forestry surveyors measured an anonymous 79.22m white gum (Eucalyptus nobilis) in a stand of giants up at Cunnawarra near Point Lookout, the Grandis supporters promptly saw to it that their local champ was remeasured at 84m plus. The tallest eucalypt at present is a Mountain Ash (E. regnans) in the Styx Valley in Tasmania. It is 96m tall. Mountain Ash in Victoria and Tasmania grow to 80m, have been measured at 99m, reported at 130m and made legendary at a primeval 150m. Even Mueller lent his name to that legend. The American wilderness man, John Muir had to come to Australia to dispel it and protect the reputation of the Californian Redwoods. But, the story goes, the mountain ashes bigger than the redwoods had already been cut down. Tall trees, tall stories. Legend aside, the fall back has been that the redwoods are gymnosperms and not really flowering plants, so the eucalypts are the tallest flowering plants in the world. Whenever people see a big tree they wonder how old it is. Big size suggests big time. The Grandis Tree is estimated at only 400 or 500 years. Grandis grow fast. They are big weeds. Size always seems to offer a way to see through the obscurity of time: space is obvious and present; time is mostly long gone, its present fleeting, its traces perplexing, its nature mysterious. The dimensions of time may well be traced in those of space, but enigmatically. Compared to the life of a tree, the life of a forest is longer and messier. For want of a main character organizing and therein referring to itself, it is misleading to call it a life. With a miscellany of characters that may live for a 63

millennium or a day, a forest not only defies the format of a life, it defies both the time an observer has to spare and even the comparatively brief duration of the scientific culture whose concepts the observer brings to the theory-laden act of observation. Not only in everyday imagination, but in scientific research, spatially conditioned differences have to substitute for temporally conditioned ones. We have to observe forests at different stages of development by observing different forests in different places, but this is not always a good substitute in the all too historical discipline of ecology. Scientific thought works away incessantly, wheedling its way out of the chronic complication of history’s particularity, trying to rescue whatever is effectively universal. The plot of natural selection may be a very general plot, applicable to all species, but the evolution of any given species is utterly particular. The biography of an individual tallowwood is particular, but by belonging to what is virtually a natural kind of thinga speciestallowwoods share physiological features and, all things being equal, lead similar lives. Tallowwoods are of what is effectively a type, virtually permanent in its characteristics, because the timescale of natural selection is so vast compared to the life of an individual that tallowwoods, generation after generation, are effectively all pretty much the same. Forests, on the other hand, are much less effectively distinguished this way; the general plot of the history of a type of forest is much less likely to match the salient events of the particular plots of particular forests. The story of a forest’s process of assembly is called a succession. To give it a beginning, the simplest plot starts with a clean slatesay the ash bed of a big fire, the mineral soil a land slip, or the mash of a bulldozed clearing. Already plot is being deformed to pander to human intuition. As the poets have long known, narratives have to start somewhere, anywhere, and always in medias res, in the middle of things. You make the best of it, or, like the poets, a virtue of it. The clean slate is as good a starting point as any mainly because human agriculture is so given to cleaning slates. It is also a way of starting with the conceptually simple, or simplified, and proceeding to the more complicated. The trouble is even those three types of clean slates are contaminated by their differences. Rainforests successions are often described as a kind of relay, in which species colonize the forest in a definite order. Some species are said to pioneer the clean slateannual herbs whose seeds are blown in on the wind, or short-lived shrubs and trees. It is another metaphor. The pioneers sound like they prepare the way, as if the succession were organized in stages to reach a designed end, and all species were not just utter opportunists and in it for themselves. At the second stage, birds and wind bring in the seed of slightly more long-lived, fast-growing treestrees that still like high light levels. These species germinate and start to take over. Around here there are seeds like those of blackwood (Acacia melanoxylon), seeds that have lain dormant in the ground from the old ex-forest, and they, if they haven’t already, germinate. Along with blackwood, species like red ash, brown kurrajong and pencil cedar take advantage of the sunny conditions. These pioneer trees grow to form a canopy, and this creates the slightly shadier conditions exploited in turn by the species 64

of a third stage. These species are longer lived, they can germinate and grow amongst other vegetation and litter, grow in partial shade and perhaps, at least as seedlings, may not be able always to endure the harsh sun and the fluctuations in heat and water that effect open country. They arrive by birds and wind, and fruit bats. Some like weeping lilly pillies, blue quandongs, blackbeans and native chestnut arrive by river and line banks. The precise stage to which a species belongs becomes unclear. Those of the so-called third stage are said to create the conditions for the mature phase rainforest species, the long lived trees that germinate in low light, but the whole pioneering idea, the idea of preparing the way, is getting more unclear too. Someseldom those with windblown seedpersist and fruit as denizens of the shady understorey: native gardenia, hairy walnut, white bolly gum. Others like black and white booyongs, rosewoods, Dorrigo plum, red beans, black beans, pepperberries, or yellow carabeens persist and grow at low light and then, years later, when an old tree falls and a gap forms in the canopy, are able to finally push their way up. But they are all different and I don’t like these lumped together lists. They are like conceptual detention centres. From the high canopy, species with windblown seed can now disseminate themselves. Those with succulent fruits rely on birds and bats or rats. Some like the Dorrigo plum, the rusty plum or the hairy walnut have heavy fruits the size of cricket balls. Where once they could rely on bird, marsupial or reptile megafauna, they now depend on rats, floods and primate megafauna for dissemination. These ‘four stages of rainforest succession’ are not set in stone like the Stations of the Cross, although sometimes people talk as if they are and match it with their reverence. People replanting rainforest can discuss the question of a species’ proper stage as if it were a point of theology. Really, this notorious 4-stage doctrine of successionits recent cultural ancestors in northern NSW are Hopkins (1981) and Floyd (1991)is just a way for booting up to the task of plotting the natural history of a rainforest, and that was how the ecologists meant it. The vines to tangle it up, the herbivores to nibble it down, the ferns and orchids to deck its halls, the storms and floods and chainsaws to topple bits of it, the drought to whither it and the fire to burn it have been left out. It is a perfunctory concoction, mostly false and a terrible underestimation. To remedy the artifice of starting with a clean slate there needs to be some account of the process of gap regeneration, whereby the rainforest is said to routinely make ongoing repairs to itself (Another metaphor). When a tree falls in a rainforest, if the gap left in the canopy is big enough and the sun hits enough ground, species that germinate in higher light or heat conditions like giant stinging trees or red cedars or cudgeries colonize. Sometimes the mature phase species that are lurking in the middle layer get their chance, sometimes vines and lianas like the native grapes, often already present, erupt all over the damaged canopy. Gap size and incumbent species determine just what happens. In chronically wind disturbed rainforestscyclone forests they are sometimes calledviny canopy can persist indefinitely. Vines are often left out of the picture, but vines make up 30% of rainforest canopy. As well as being called 65

closed forests because their canopy provides over 70% cover from the sky, rainforests are also called vine forests. Light-loving lianas such as the tendrilled grapes and twining blood vine hang from the high branches having hitched a ride up on growing trees; lawyer palms hook their way up through the shade on long vicious barbs; giant peppers creep slowly up wet trunks along with climbing ferns and pothos and eventually clothe the trunks in a dense shag. The relay plot is applied to rainforest, but there is another kind of plot in which the species that come up under the initial conditions on the clean slate persist indefinitely until the slate is cleared again. On the ash bed of a fire, eucalypts, sclerophyll shrubs, bracken, grasses and sedges may colonize, and, then under a regime of fires that return more or less every year or every few years, the same trees, shrubs and herbs persist because other would-be colonizing species cannot survive the fires. The species that can survive the fires are already present anyway and, in the case of eucalypts, they can create the very fuel and conditions that make regular fire so highly likely. After fire, they re-sprout again or germinate from seed again. Over time, there may be a little shifting in the proportions of the various species. Frequent firing removes species that don’t have time to seed or the ability to keep resprouting between burns, and it favours those that can resprout or re-seed themselves. In a dry sclerophyll forest where eucalypts drop sticks onto an understorey of sclerophyll shrubs, or in a grassy forest or woodland where perennial grasses like Imperata grow up every wet season and dry out into a neat crop of fuel, fire can become as regular as ignition allows it, and the initial composition of fire hardy species is likely to persist. Sometimes, where there are callitris or casuarina or acacia, a relay process might get started. If it is wet enough and the soil rich enough, as it is in much of the Bellinger valley, a faltering relay of eucalypt forest and rainforest may get starteda wet sclerophyll forest. As long as fire and drought stay out of the wet eucalypt forest, the rainforest species gradually colonize it. Birds and bats bring in seed from the drupes and berries of laurels, myrtles and grapes, from the arils of the Sapindaceae, and from hundreds of other succulent fruited trees and vines. Bangalow palms begin to appear as odd seedlings and in 30 years steep moist gullies turn into viny palm groves. Fern spores blow in and the fiery blady grass and bracken give way to tree ferns and gristle and rasp ferns. Drought and fire test the limits of the rainforest. One dry spring a small fire may crackle down through the fallen sticks and branches of the eucalypts on a drier ridge, petering out in the fine, thatched litter of a patch of forest oaks (Allocasuarina torulosa)the local casuarinas beloved of the glossy black cockatoos who can spend all day in one grove munching the winged samaras out of the cones. Or if it is fiercer, the fire might burn beyond them, popping their steamy trunks, and coming to a halt where the spur drops southwards into a brushy gully. Like the acacias, the forest oaks burn dense and hot in a stovethey were the standard fuel of woodfired bakers ovensbut their litter is less encouraging of bushfire than that of eucalypts, and the trees more susceptible to it. They can only shoot again after cool fires. Anything hotter and they rely on seed. Here on the east coast the 66

winter rains of the continent’s south have given way to the humid, rainy summers of the subtropical and tropical north. With the summer rains, burnt white mahoganies or blackbutts will replace their singed leaves, blue gums or tallowwoods may re-leave or they may have to germinate from seed, the blady grass will send up its green spears and fluffy flowers, and a bracken plant that may be 500 years old will curl its succulent fronds up out of the ashes from its network of starchy rhizomes. Otherwise or elsewhere, beyond the incursion of the fire, the wet sclerophyll forest becomes dominated by rainforest species, and gristle and rasp ferns are joined by or give way to shield ferns and prickly tree fern. Sometimes the rainforest can persist in the moister gullies, protected long enough for the windblown seeds of cudgerie and red cedar to colonize gaps; or sassafras and socketwood might make their way in. Even coachwood or booyong might eventually arrive. After centuries, fire-sown eucalypts may tower as ancient monuments over a fully constituted rainforest, the gums eventually rotting, collapsing and leaving only the dense brush. Chances are it wont happennot over centuries when El Niño driven droughts are coming and going in great cycles of rising and falling fire risk, and the great greedy eucalypts, their roots establishing command over every nook of the soil, are pumping the water out of it, robbing the rainforest colonizers until their leaves droop and fall and even the hardiest turn into living or dead fuelbut it can and does. Most of the time these so called gully rainforests are somewhat depauperate. Growing along gullies surrounded by fired eucalypt forest restricts the sources of incoming seed. Growing on poorer, slaty soils rather than basalt or alluvial soils reduces the likelihood of the nutrient loving species with their soft extravagant leaves and favours the thrifty sclerophylls. Growing as rainforests with a short life expectancy reduces the likelihood of species that colonize the more mature phases of rainforests. Fast colonizers, bird-dispersed species, species that coppice after the odd fire, and species of poorer or drier soils predominateoften of uneven age, often multi-stemmed, often of only moderate height: the laurels like jackwood and murrogun; myrtles like scrub turpentine, native guava, lilly pilly and the quasi-eucalypt, brushbox; Sapindaceae like tamarinds, foambarks and guioas; the ubiquitous red ash, blackwood and cheese tree; on the warmer aspects, cudgerie, white beech, red cedar and red bean; on the cooler slopes, caldcluvia, possumwood and sassafras; and everywhere the vinesgrapes, morinda, melodinus, giant raspberry, cockspur, lawyer palm, and prickly sarsaparilla. I often think the bush around here might as well be called grape forest as tallowwood country or ridge country, or wet sclerophyll forest. The two native grapes that own the placeCissus antarctica and the five-leaved Cissus hypoglaucabelong to the same family as the wine grape. They are big fleshy lianas. They look strong enough to swing on and are sometimes called monkey vines. They have been called water vines too. They almost spurt water when you cut them and, it is said, cedar getters and old bushies used to cut them for a drink when they were up in the bush away from streams. With their neatly 67

forked tendrils, the vines climb the shrubs, trees and other vines of rainforest regrowth and eucalypt understorey, tangling their heavy foliage over whatever they can. In winter to avoid the goannas the baldy pigeons rustle and flutter in the tangle, courting and nesting and calling with a short om and a long low oom that haunts the ridges and gullies. When the vines are dropping fruit the wonga pigeons walk beneath them pecking it up. Like their domestic cousins the grapes have bunches of dark blue berries, ripe with a glaucous bloom in late summerplump-seeded, thick-skinned grapes whose tannin can screw your face up when you eat them, and dry your mouth out. They can, nevertheless, be made into a jellya little astringent maybe, but dark and sweet. The berries of C. antarctica are bigger, plumper and juicier than C. hypoglauca, and better for jelly. It is a culinary niche though that has not led to much of a local grape culture. People who like trees, including many a rainforest regenerator and many a eucalypt forester, are circumspect about grapes. There is no doubt they can form a persistent viny scrub and make the development of a tall tree canopy a slow process. Grape growth can only be called rampant, and cutting a bit back from the odd entangled tree is hardly going to endanger the vigour of an individual vine let alone the viability of a population. While we sleep, these locals are busy growing, seeding and spreading themselves around with the assistance of hordes of bowerbirds, catbirds and Lewin’s honeyeaters, and with a virulence that is admirably weed like. It is partly perversity, partly loyalty to a nature that decides its own directions, and mainly just affection for the plants that this country belongs to as much as the eucalypts that makes me let them do their thing and scramble over almost anything they choose. Anyway, policing grape would be a full time job. More than anythingexcept maybe nowadays lantanawhat marks the moist gullies of the local wet sclerophyll forest is the dark green of the viny grape scrub, highlighted by the gold of the shoots, tendrils and flowers. Walking through the tangle can be slow, but at least these vines don’t cut, prickle, burn, abrade, jag or hooktheir ropy loops are as reassuring as low solid swings, their leaves are as comforting as their suede indumentum. Walking with the wongas beneath the vines in late summer, the ground bountiful with blue fruits, the air with fermentation, I daydream about a grape culture or cuisine or industry or fortune, truly of this grape country. Unlike the open fire forest, the rainforest understorey casts a deeper shade and a leafier litter. It is already likely to be thickest on the moistest sites, protected from the harshest sun and the hottest winds, and on soils lower down in the gullies where there has been more enrichment by deposition. Its fallen leaves fertilize the woody litter of the eucalypts, hastening the breakdown by insects, fungi and bacteria. Its more shallow-rooted trees and vines more equitably share the commonwealth of soil moisture. Its fallen wood is usually softer and quickly rotted by the living organisms protected under the shady canopy. Foliage is softer, moister and less volatile, and for want of dry wood and kindling the rainforest resists future fire incursions. While it is getting established a mild fire might not get into it. Even a bigger fire might just singe 68

the dry fronds of palms dotted along its edge it. Otherwise, a long drought, the dry foliage of a wind smashed tree, and a spark from humans or lightning, and firemaybe the first one in 50 or 100 or 500 yearseats back into the wet forest or opens it up, the next time to consume it. Some of the rainforest species may coppice and recover and certain patches may survive, while the phoenix eucalypts rise once more. In the wet sclerophyll, changes staged by the colonizing rainforest are anything but inevitable. They are like the European revolutions of the 19th century, which, according to Karl Marx writing in the 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, ‘interrupt themselves continually in their own course, come back to the apparently accomplished in order to begin afresh, deride with unmerciful thoroughness the inadequacies, weaknesses and paltriness of their first attempts, seem to throw down their adversary only in order that he may draw new strength from the earth and rise again more gigantic before them, recoil ever and anon from the indefinite prodigiousness of their own aims, until the situation has been created which makes all turning back impossible.’ In the pattern of the rainforest and eucalypt forest, as it is laid out over the landscape, the change from one to another can sometimes be abrupt. At other times the two merge into an ecotone, part eucalypt part rainforest. In fact, wet sclerophyll forest is more or less all ecotone. Just why there is more rainforest in one place and more eucalypt forest in another, is partly determinate, partly the result of iterative processes, partly intentional, the rest random. Gullies, southern aspects, good soils and soil moisture are all favourable for the rainforest and causally they are confounded with one another. Once rainforest gets started, it, like the eucalypt forest, is self-perpetuatingbut only weakly. People like to think or hope that if they grow rainforests plants in eucalypt country they will ward off fire, but they need the consistent moisture and aspect as well, and they need a large enough patch so that fire wont eat into it and they need to be spared bad droughts and big fires. There is no sure conversion of just any bit of wet sclerophyll country to rainforest, and the drier it gets, the riskier it gets. In its risky interrupted relay, wet sclerophyll forest recapitulates the great fluctuating dramas of the longer biogeopraphical struggle between rainforest and sclerophyll forest. What makes its present form distinctive in that long history are the dominance of the eucalyptus genus, the ubiquity of human fire and 10,000 years of warm moist conditions. The abrupt changes from rainforest to grassy eucalypt forest, so often described in early colonial accounts, lead many to conclude that wet sclerophyll forest is an artifact of the new colonial fire regimes, a rank eruption occasioned by neglect, by new weedy species like lantana, by ignorance of traditional fire management, and by subsequent reification of that ignorance in new fire practices designed now to reproduce a mistaken image of the pristine. The abrupt changes from grassy eucalypt to rainforest were partly the result of patterns of burning and herbivory, partly determined by certain forest types, and partly by forest age. The Aborigines burnt with no need to worry about wildfires consuming buildings and little need 69

to extinguish a fire once started. Because they burnt according to the different uses and significance of different kinds of countryhusbanding game populations, clearing passage or views through in one place, preserving useful fire sensitive plants in anotherburning intentions were confounded with the determinate fire ecology of the different kinds of vegetation, one reinforced the other, and perceived structural divisions between different vegetation types may have become somewhat emphatic. As modern fire culture reifies its image of nature, albeit imperfectly across the landscape, Aboriginal fire culture also reified its understanding of country. The works of both however could not help but be exceeded by the power and persistence of extrahuman nature and unintended social nature, no matter how much they might be reconfigured in retrospect as intentional. Despite deliberate burning and the historically unprecedented increase in sources of ignition, the rainforest during the last 10,000 years managed to creep back out of the refuges to which it had retreated during the last ice age. What it crept out into though, was a country where eucalypts now reigned. I suspect that in the remote rugged country of the Bellinger valley, rainforests and wet sclerophyll forests were mighty enough forces of nature for them to persist and perpetuate themselves more or less beyond the immediate intentions of most Gumbaynggirr custodianship, as they still do beyond the meddling and management of busy modernity. Wet sclerophyll forests would have exceeded human designs. Deliberate burning would have defined their extent somewhat, but wildfire, whether anthropogenic or from lightening strike, may well have accounted for much of the burningas it does nowburning that would have stencilled the erratic proportions of eucalypt and rainforest across the remoter ridges and gullies. Deliberately designed burning would have most affected the coastal foreststhe areas of higher occupancygrassy woodlands and open forests on the estuary and river flats, and the main ridges used to travel to and from the Dorrigo Plateau. Once a forest of big eucalypts is established with an understorey of perennial grasses, sedges, lomandras, and ferns, rather than an understorey of small rainforest trees and vines, the structure may become somewhat selfmaintaining. To get established the eucalypt seedlings may have come up in droves, or the trees may be of mixed ages, but over 50 or 100 or 200 years they thin out. Hotter fires at odd intervals might disrupt this, encouraging continual regeneration of youngish eucalypt poles from seed and lignotubers. Nowadays, agricultural herbivores like cattle might graze out the sweet grasses and leave eucalypt seedlings and shrubby, viny or weedy growth. Otherwise, under big gums, colonizing trees and shrubs can struggle to germinate. If they do, they might not survive the delectation of wallabies, or the Medusa crowns of sawfly larvae writhing as they eat their way along each leaf blade, or there are droughts, fires, or soil that fluctuates between waterlogged and bone dry. Combine small fires and the proclivity of wallabies and kangaroos for grazing patches of burnt ground and the understorey can become less shrubby and less diverse. Big gums can dominate in the competition for water and nutrients; 70

perennial grasses, sedges, rushes and herbs can ride out the cycles of dry and wet years. Particular species of eucalypt on certain country seem given to forming forest like this. Forest red gum, once common on heavy soils along the coast and coastal floodplainsand therefore on the first kind of country to be selected for farminggets its name because forest was used to specifically designate land, as Governor King said in an 1805 letter to Earl Camden, ‘such as abounds with Grass, and is the only Ground which is fit to graze. According to the local distinction the Grass is the discriminating Character and not the Trees.’ The coastal forestsespecially the forest red gum and kangaroo grass on the heavier soilsand the blackbutt and blady grass on the better drained coastal soils and on the ridges are still grassier than forests in the shady gullies or further up the valley in the shadow of the 1000m escarpment. They are seldom as tall, or as protected from fire as the forests in the deeper gullies, where the tallest eucalypts and densest rainforest grow. A mature red gum forest might have had trees as widely separated as ½ to 2 crown widthswhat would now technically be called a woodland or even an open woodlandwith as few as 30 big trees per hectare. Other grassy forests like blackbutt were probably more closely spacedsay a quarter a crown width and close enough therefore to be called an open forest. Rainforests are closed forests. The crowns touch or overlap. In wet sclerophyll forests the tall eucalypt crowns are less than a quarter of their width apart and the understorey is a more or less closed forest of small trees, shrubs and vines. People argue passionately about how dense the Aboriginal forests and woodlands were. It is part of the argument over the changes between traditional and modern burning, about how country should be managed and about how good or bad fire is. Ecological categories are confounded with historical, political and ethical ones. Questions about what the bush looked like should be answered with questions: Where? When? What kind of bush? At what stage of succession? On what soil? Based on whose report? Whose evidence? Whose speculation? It is too simple to say that modern wet forests are cluttered with poles and shrubby understorey because of failure to burn them or burn them properly. Like all history, like this history, the search for answers is a romance, but reports and descriptions are equivocal and best read as pieces in a satire. As the summer rain clouds roll around the edge of the escarpment, they drop rain up there that the coast misses. The coastal rainforests were found in their distinctive littoral form on well-watered sands behind foredunes, as gallery forests along estuarine creeks, as patches on the flood plain dotted through a mosaic of swamp oak and paperbark swamp forests, sedgelands, and red gum forest, and strung along some of the deeper coastal gullies carved back up into the metasediment ridge country. The coastal eucalypt forests are the only forests on the Bellinger nowadays that are open and grassy enough for eastern grey kangaroos to graze, and I would guess that they were traditionally burnt for hunting not only this, the largest of the local marsupials, but other smaller fauna. On the lower Bellinger flats, on the farming country just down below 71

these ridges where I am writing, and on soil derived from estuarine silts deposited during the last 100,000 years, there were once red gum forestsopen and grassy and typically managed by burning. It was lined and dotted with patches of rainforest, swamp forest, and sedgeland. Now though, hardly any of this survives, having been replaced by feral grasslands lined with drainage channels and dotted with camphor laurels. As a nutritious eucalypt that is fancied by koalas, the forest red gum flats would have been a place for easy hunting of this slow arboreal marsupial. Perhaps too easy. Would they have been hunted down to fairly small populations? Koalas are now confined to feeding on the tallowwood, grey gum and forest oak up here in the wet sclerophyll country on the ridges. They seem quite common. It is a place also of shy swamp wallabies, turkeys, pigeons, tree goannas, carpet snakes, brushtail possums, bandicoots, echidnas, gliders, a number of smaller mammals, many smaller reptiles, and 100 species of birds. Yet whatever is now conspicuous may be a misleading indication of the fauna found and hunted in the past, so great are the changes to the land. Besides, now and in the past, casual reports may be a misleading indication of the status of the fauna, so obscure are the fluctuations of animal populations to reliable observation, let alone explanation. Beyond the grassy coastal and estuarine forests, frequent patch burning might have been most common on travelling routes along the river flats and up to the escarpment. Grassy glades amongst the brushes on the river would have been places for camping and hunting pademelons and wallabies, small browsing macropods who may have assisted in the perpetuation of such glades. On many of the ridges and spurs leading to the plateau there are clusters of shining burrawangs, cycads with big nuts that were eaten after baking, pounding and leaching out the toxins. Cycads fruit well after burning and elsewhere they were burnt in order to induce such fruiting. Up on the plateau there were little grassy plains, fired and frosted into the brush, recorded in early European descriptions, and some still recorded now as traces on the landscape itself. Little Plains at North Dorrigo takes its name from a few grassy acres beside a creek once fringed with teatree and cassinia, now by privet. The town of Dorrigo took advantage of another grassland on the slopes beside the Bielsdown. ‘We suddenly enter one of the little “plains” or meadows,’ wrote the botanist Joseph Maiden (4) in 1894, ‘and are fairly in Dorrigo.’ He saw the plains dominated by flowering kangaroo grass and something else he took for Sorghum plumosum. Although he saw ‘specimen trees dotted about as in a gentleman’s park’ (4), legend has it that no tree ever grew in the grassy little plains, nor ever will. Nor ever should. Cedar cutters and the first selectors found the clearings prepared for them by the Gumbaynggirr and the winter frost, there in the heavy quilt of rosewood rainforest that grew on the wellwatered basalt soil. Otherwise this highland rainforest was broken only by small patches of white gum—and less often, blue gum—that had managed to take advantage of a drought, a landslip, an odd burn or the odd patch of poorer soil. Mostly the eucalypts were ‘on the skirts of it (never penetrating beyond the fringe)’ (4). Further east, off the basalt and on the metasediments, the plains at 72

Killungoondie were fired and kept open by the Gumbaynggirr through otherwise great sombre stretches of hoop pine and coachwood rainforest. Only now are they being colonized by thickets of black oak (Allocasuarina littoralis). I imagine Killungoondie must look like somewhere from the last ice ageafter the onset of human fire and before the consummation of the dominion of eucalypts. Quite a bit of the valley and the plateau was tended by fire, and like now there was a lot of ridge country in the valley foothills covered in an open forest of old eucalypts that made life difficult for the woody and viny understorey of wet sclerophyll to establish itself in the understorey of grass and ferns and herbs, but even so, the earliest written reports of the Bellinger emphasize its dense junglestall, brushy and varied on the river flats, harder and viny under the eucalypts in the gullies or around the estuarine fringe. In the moments that have passed since the European settlement, the ecology of all these forests has been transformed. There are now new kinds of upheaval rivalling and perhaps exceeding those of the Tertiary and the early Quaternary. The ages of axe, cattle, plough, bulldozer, chainsaw, forestry, postGumbaynggirr burning and, most of all, the global cultigens of modern agriculture and horticulture have changed the eucalypt forests again and again and continue to change them. At the hands of farming and forestry we have remade the forests according to our disaffected image of them, reifying their perceived charmlessness in the tracts of weedy undergrowth that we are now left with. Seen from a high vantage they still blanket ridge after ridge, broken only by grassy farms along the rivers. Mountains are waves in the ocean of the gum forest. They loom at the back of every landscape in the Bellinger valley as if they have always been there and always will be there. But we utter parochials in time, we are like mites even when it comes to the brief timescale of the revolutions through which the eucalypt forests have been lurching for just the last 100 years. Except when we refer to them by the dismissive term regrowth we hardly see the passing of time that is so scratched and torn into them, and so graffitied over them that it defies historical disentanglement. We probably don’t want to; we would prefer distance and bogus invocations of timelessness to render them poetic. Most of them were ringbarked and burnt by the time of the First World War. Old photographs from the early 20th century show forests of dead pillars running way up the ridges, often with a shag of ferny regrowth already erupting beneath them where there weren’t enough brushhooks to control it. In Winter’s Afternoon, Bellingen, Elioth Gruner painted a valley of grassy hills rolling beneath the blue silhouette of McGrath’s Hump. This was 1937. There is the odd remnant stag, and the odd gum or scrub tree where now there would be ridges and gullies of regrowth, lantana and camphor laurel. Most of the blue backdrop behind the valley’s cleared farmland was country that had started out as old, over-mature forest with few trees that did not bear the scars of fire, termites and time. By 1912, much of the lower altitude ridge country had become steep farmlandcountry burnt, fenced and brushed for rough grazing. A grass from South America, paspalum (P. dilatatum), promised a way of 73

transforming the lower spurs of the despised hardwood ridges into some kind of pasture. According to the District Forester, Edward Swain, before 1905 only the flats—25,000ha—had been selected and cleared for corn and cattle. By 1912 a further 30,000 ha—nearly all lower ridge country was selected and being cleared. Most of the rest stayed with the Crown and ended up as state forest. It had all been cut over for the best and easiest trees by the First World War, and afterwards it was gone over with axesringbarking the rest of the old, hollow trees. Farmers did this on the freehold in order to burn it and keep it clear. Foresters did it to grow straight, even-age stands. High-grading they called it. Swain (1912) wrote: The original forest, according to the Bellinger pioneers, was almost park-like in its growth, and low lateral branching was thereby permitted…Since the advent of settlement, however, several agencies have operated to clear the forest floor of its dominating carpet of native grasses, and allow the upspringing of hardwood seedlings, many of which are now in the spar stages, and because of greater density are of a much better timber quality than was produced in the primeval forest. Agriculturally, the Bellinger had been one of the last valleys cleared and one of the poorest in the state. Few families grew rich off it. They cropped corn and grew veggies on the small river flats, eked out a living from grazing and dairy, and cut timber from the ridge country. Then, year by year, with the droughts of the Second World War, the big flood of 1950 that washed away the bridges and shut down the little farms up the river past Darkwood, the shrinking of family size, the relentless tightening of the market and regulatory screws on the dairy industry, people had to walk off the land. In the 1960s Australian Paper Mills bought up many of the ridge farms in the lower valley country nearest to the port of Coffs Harbour. They planted thousands of hectares of flooded gum and blackbutta sign that timber was the only industry that the combined environments of markets and ridge country could support. By the 70s and 80s, when most farming had shrunk to small scale beef grazing supplemented by offfarm income, and a metropolitan population had extended itself to the north coastthe land of its childhood beach holidays and its rainforest dreamingregrowth had taken back the ridges again for the eucalypts, the second time round with an understorey of wattle, red ash, lantana, camphor laurel and privet scrub. Large areas thickened up with young forest. The stuff the farmers had been battling, burning, brushing and grazing for half a century, became decorative backdrop to lifestyle. The stock had long ago grazed out the sweetest grasses and encouraged woody shrubs and treesgums, wattles, red ash, and lantana. The new irregular burning, part deracinated tradition, part haphazard, part wildfire, encouraged bracken, blady grass and especially weeds. During nearly a century of clearing and burning, grazing, logging and regrowth, reclearing 74

and regrowing, successive waves of exotic plant species made their appearances, each taking up its distinctive place in the understorey scrub and each affecting the still ruling eucalypts in its own way. Lantana was common by the end of the 19th century. Joseph Maiden saw it lining both sides of the road when he traveled from the river mouth to Bellingen in 1894. There had always been targets for the sardonic contempt these forests evokedstumps, regrowth, ferns, undergrowthand lantana was to out-perform its many indistinguishable native rivals for this role as the dominant species of rubbish. It dominated the understorey of the moist regrowth, poisoned cattle (at least the red flowered variety did), and wrote itself into the popular culture of the landscape. The terms, regrowth, rubbish and undergrowth all became as confused as the tangle of lantana scrub that had come to characterize each of them. They all existed to be cleaned up. The understorey of rubbish dragged down the status of the regrowth wet sclerophyll forest, and while the gums came up as thick or thicker than ever in many places, they had trouble out-competing lantana down in the wettest gullies. Especially when regrowth was establishing in wet years alongside forests that were already full of seeding lantana. When attempts were made to clear or clean up the regrowth, the rubbish or the understorey, it came back more rubbishy. A new exotic invader would appear. Camphor laurels had been planted late in the 19th century as shade trees on the cleared landscape. The shade from old eucalypts was too thin. The old scrub trees were too tall and too weak when left out in the paddock after everything around had been cut down. Camphor laurel was shady, fast growing, Chinoiserie, andyou never knowit could turn out useful in the medicine cabinet or a linen chest. It was an irresistible horticultural curiosity. It was also a survivorideal for planting in public places. Some of the biggest camphors in Bellingen still grow on the main street, planted in front of what was the old school and is now the Shire Council. Trees started to seed, first one generation then the next. Topknot pigeonsinitially decimated by the loss of their local laurels in the alluvial brusheslearned to feed on the oily drupes and spread the seed. Compared to lantana it was a slow succession of long generations, but the camphors gradually staked out the flats and richer gullies as theirs. They came up near houses, in parks, along fence lines, beside rivers and creeks, under ringbarked stags, under the eucalypts in the gully countrywhere ever the rushing flocks of topknot pigeons regurgitated and dropped their seeds. Even by the end of the 20th century though, they had still a long way to go to reach their potential. While the camphors were taking their portion of the wet sclerophyll forest so were the waves of small-leaved privetalso from China. At first the red soil rainforests of Dorrigo had been domesticated by rolling kikuyu pasture portioned between privet hedgerows and windbreaks of Monterey Pine. Later, radiating out from towns and farms where they had once been planted and trimmed as hedges, the privets took over water scoured gullies, neglected fencelines, abandoned hillsides and patches of bush. They did the same down in the valley. Each generation flowered and fruited and moved on to remoter 75

gullies and remoter hillsides, spread by birds and bats. By the end of the 20th century the privets lined creeks and gullies in dense multistemmed droves, yet, like the camphors, they too were only just starting to achieve their potential. After a century and a half of introducing self-perpetuating pasture grasses, the Department of Agriculture fulfilled its sacred bureaucratic destiny and finally hit upon a species of South American paspalum that could out-compete the natives in the new wet sclerophyll forests. Paspalum dilatatum seed had been sown into the ash beds of cleared forest from the end of the 19th century, but it would not grow in shade. Along with the prized kikuyu, stingy carpet grass and stingier whiskey grass, it dominated the perennial summer grasslands of agricultural Bellingen. Now however, broad-leaved paspalum (Paspalum wettsteinii) arrived on the scene from South America to finally offer a shade tolerant pasture, a miraculous understorey grass for a more and more treeconscious grazing industry. In the 1970s, 80s and 90s it was sown under gums and into forest where the understorey had been ‘cleaned up’. Farmers could now clean up the rubbish and grass it down with a Landcare grass. To stop erosion and feed cattle, it was sown on steep banana country, scoured creek banks and cleared gullies. It was sown into State Forest and under eucalypt plantations to encourage a bucolic understorey that would value-add beef and beauty to industrial timber factories. By 2000 it had worked its way into a good proportion of the tall forest remnants at the back of farms, seeding outliers into good forest, hitching rides on wallaby and stock and boots, proliferating into swards at any hint of ground or canopy disturbance, along roads and wallaby tracks, on land slips, riverbanks and water scoured ground. Although it had not managed get through bureaucratic and political filters and work its way onto official lists of the serious weeds of moist forests, it was busy working along with lantana and privet ensuring that native grasses, rushes, sedges and herbs disappeared from landscape and memory. As new weeds arrived one after another to take there places beside and beneath the eucalyptus, so did new technologies, each seeming to be predesigned for the use of one or other of the weeds. As if designed by lantana, bulldozers could clear a gully into a steam pudding seedbed of caterpillartracked clay, hastening the old work of axes, bullocks and fire. Fences and shade trees attracted birds, brilliantly, to drop the seed of camphors and privets. Slashers could brush back native regrowth to a heavy sward of paspalum, and even bring the seed in on their tyres without trying. It was all a beautifully designed, seamlessly functioning ecosystem, a nightmare realization of the wildest dreams of ecosystem managers. What many see now as timeless forest is the regrowth that signified the failure of farming to turn all those ridges of unruly timber into corn or milk or beef. Various ages of plantation and regrowth, each distinctive for its weeds, swallowed up old farms. Still standing here and there in the regrowth forests are the ruins: giant stumps with axe holes above the buttresses where axemen wedged step-planks as platforms for felling, the last ringbarked stagsa century old now; house piers, footings, fence posts and rusting wire; orchard 76

relics China pears, persimmons, guavas, poorman’s oranges, mandarins, mango trees, macadamias and mulberries; and self-propagating bush lemons, passionfruit vines and cape gooseberriesa legacy some might number among the weeds. The eucalypts, the long-lived weeds of fire and catastrophe, have so far seemed to hold their own, even prevailed. Appearances may be deceptive though, because their life cycle is so slow, and the ongoing changes to their regime take a long time to express themselves. The main weeds of the wet sclerophyll are weeds of the rainforest component, of the ground, shrub and small tree layers. They erupt when wet eucalypt forest is logged or cleared, especially in the deep moist nooks of the gullies, and they now grow through most of the forest that is adjacent to farming and forestry country on the Bellinger lowlands. In the tangle of weeds, the rainforest trees struggle, but the eucalypts can struggle too. Many tracts of former eucalypt country have now been reduced to a weedy, viny scrub clamouring over the corpses of collapsed wattles.

John Lewin’s watercolour of Evans Peak (1815) was commissioned by Lachlan Macquarie. The Governor of NSW at the time, he wanted paintings to record his first official crossing of the Blue Mountains. Lewin saw the continent disappearing into the distance, the thick smoky sky, the hazy washout of light over the hard leaves, the eucalypt crowns asymmetrical, sympodial and silhouetted on the ridges, the dollopy forest texture on the spurs and peaks, the scrubby gully between the grassy woodland slopes. Best of all is the portrait of that awkward stingy-leaved stringy bark. Lewin did not get it to decorously frame a vista. It insisted on standing too far over on the right. Bark, dead sticks and leaves hang from the odd branch and they are shed thin and messy on the ground. The colonial coroner and scientific draughtsman, painter of fish, birds, plants and insects had the sensualist, empiricists eye for things that venerable generations of painters, distracted by oil, grand designs, or the burden of national and picturesque intentions, could not allow into their works. Received art history has it that the landscape set an historic task for the imaginative appropriation of the country, and that the eucalypt was the central icon of that landscape. In order to become Australia—to mature as a nation— the nation had to see the eucalypt truly and take its image to heart. Peter Conrad and Philip Adams only recently agreed on ABC Radio National that Fred Williams was the Australian to finally nail this holy grail of national aesthetic maturity. Yet this true image of the eucalypt has been discovered, lost and rediscovered by the various non-utilitarian departments of spiritartistic, botanical, nationalist and environmentalistmany times. The iconography’s history, has not been a gradual progression to a culminating realization, but a series of fits and starts, slips and recoveries, the same epiphanies experienced, forgotten and reiterated generation by generation. Received histories of a national aesthetic sensibility maturing in a long struggle against old fashioned 77

distaste for the bush seem more like commentator’s personal aesthetic development writ large. Either that or they are simply equating the aesthetic progress of modern art (and its new ways of seeing) with maturing national landscape sensibility. Well after Lewin, the task for John Glover, not long off the boat from England, is still supposed to have been that of getting the look of the place by getting the shapes and hues of the eucalypt crowns. He sort of did, so we are told, in paintings like Paterdale Landscape (1835) although he could not quite resist giving a picturesque swirl to branches that, according to official modern iconography, should have been more sticky. Even an untidy fallen branch would be said to suffer from its intention to frame a vignette of the painter’s cattle. In other paintings, Glover brought sentiment to the gum tree landscape, elaborating it with small groups of Aboriginal people in the receding middleground, in part heedless of their impending exit from it, yet in part a valediction. 50 years after Lewin, Louis Buvelot’s contemporaries declared that he was the first to make eucalypts properly aesthetic. He sort of was. Again. Yet being feted as the first to capture the poetry in them is another way of saying that he bent the eucalypts to a preformed aesthetic sensibility. In popular national consciousness, it was the Heidelberg painters, at the end of the 19th century, who seemed at last to get it right, complete with a bit of Australian Impressionist light to show off the bush, and, in the laboured major works, lost children or battling selectors to give that mere bushnow devoid of Aboriginal societya bit of human interest and aesthetic weight. Afterwards, the likes of Hans Heysen and Albert Namatjirra, and endless imitators, instituted the iconic Gum Tree Picture: a smooth-barked guma time-scarred river red gum or a sinewy ghost gumframing a distant range, a road or gully wandering away into the wide middle ground. That pretty much describes my own first work in oil, painted as an eight year old Impressionist with a set of colours my sister had given me. In later years Fred Williams was to develop a vocabulary of eucalypt ideograms, importing a bit of abstraction and hard edge from New York for the big gallery works. He showed how the gums wrote their signatures across different stretches of country, country that could now be imagined as a canvas itself. In Lynn Onus the gum tree bush ended up as indigenous postmodern, decked sardonically with roadside consumer culturestuff chucked out of Andy Warhol’s car I’d sayand fenced off, by a cyclone wire installation, like property where trespassers will be prosecuted. Throughout this colonial and post-colonial history, it has never been the case that the newest immigrants, as opposed to the native born ‘gumsuckers’, could not appreciate the gums. While Buvelot, fresh from Switzerland in the 1860s, was being feted in the 1870s and 80s, native-born bushmen, who could skite they’d learned a thing or two about the bush, were hard at it ringbarking the forests and woodlands and marking out their new tenure in waves of dead eucalypt spars. So matter of fact. Ferdinand von Mueller, another European immigrant, was forced to watch the eucalypts he’d planted in the Melbourne botanic gardens, grubbed out by the good citizens, who hankered for a greener, 78

grassier look. Dubbed Baron Blue Gum, he was sacked from the gardens’ directorship and the resources he needed to complete his ambitious Eucalyptographia were withdrawn. Whether in images or elsewhere, the culture of eucalyptus has been more like an intermittent, evolving system of social antagonisms than a progressionanalogous, in a way, to the interrupted course of eucalypt evolution or the natural history of a wet eucalypt forest. This says something about the cultural nature of the sublime impulsethat distinctively if not exclusively modern drive to appreciate what defies aesthetic sensibility, whether one’s own or that of the society. The ugly, the awkward, the wild, the foreign, the forbidden or the new are redeemed, renovating sensibility in the process. In the modern encounter with the Australian continent this impulse has been used to construct a national iconography and make an alien country into a homeland. For native born and immigrant, it is a typical experience to learn to love eucalypts and the bush, a supposedly subjective matter of aesthetics which has been put to common national use. Yet although the subjective experience of gum tree sentiment has been a powerful influence on national history, the progressive aesthetic appreciation of eucalyptus and the bush has been enacted in individuals’ experience in a way that reflects its ambiguity in social history. In turn, the sublime response has been put to the task of savouring that ambiguity. Social evolution is a very different thing from individual development, and antagonistic pressures steer the streams of modern culture in sometimes opposed, sometimes entwined currents. On the one hand, there have been and remain the usual, and often locally urgent pressures, for doing away with eucalypts and their culture: securing your rights to land by clearing it; ensuring where your next meal or dollar is coming from; doing what you have done before and know how to do; and in the end carrying on these practices for their own sake, or as custom, or right or as the deliberate declaration of a right. On the other hand, there are recurring, non-aesthetic pressures for a eucalypt culture. There is the appreciation of their utility in forestrya pressure that often seemed inherently contradictory to 20th century environmentalists. There is the all too remote, sometimes mythologized utility of gum trees in the ecological management of salinity, water tables, climate and biodiversity, a utility appreciated, at least implicitly during the 19th century, and emphatically in the late 20th. All of these combine and curdle with a nationalist affectation about the bush that can be affectionate, ironic and deprecatory. In such a social environment, the evolution of eucalypt poetics is as complex as the evolution of the eucalypts themselves amidst the historical struggles of drought and rain, and fire and rainforest. Despite the status of the eucalypts as a national symbol, only someone steeped in Aboriginal custom would break off a branch to decorate a body or a place, or to celebrate circumstance or occasion. No one decks the halls with boughs of blackbutt or picks a vase of bloodwood flowers. For the rest of us, the spiritual labours, like all labours, have been divided, the special task has been definedagain and again it seemsas that of capturing that ‘look’, and this spiritual duty has been conferred upon painters and 79

photographers, professional and amateur. Non Aboriginal Australia, during our recreational momentsif we are not busy painting or taking our own gumtree picturescan relax and check out the achievement of the image culture in the nation’s books, galleries, tourist shops, living rooms and, of course, national parks. Compared to the gum tree vista, the lush rainforests, the open grassy woodland, the sunny beaches, the cool streams, and the sublime views, compared to all these, the tall wet eucalypt forests can shun human passion, interest, comfort, affection, perception, and conceptualization. Especially the regrowth. Apart from distanced prospects blue with haze, the relief of tree fern glades, or the spectacle of primeval giants, people have seldom painted or photographed the tall wet sclerophyll forest. A likely contender is the tapestry in Parliament House. Arthur Boyd designed it, but I’d say it might be dry not wet sclerophyllquite a different look and quite a touch of the Heidelberg to it. Fred Williams is a better example. He has sort of done it, with a fair bit of abstraction. When you are in a position to see these big wet forests, you are inside them and then everything is too close and crowded to get a fitting vista, the depth only casually beginning all round, at a little distanceand there is too much greenery and it’s too drab and, more often than not, weedy at that. Cutting down the foreground was part of an artist’s job in the 19th century (Bonyhady, 193-209), and contemporary gum-tree pictures of the Bellinger still make the most of the pastoral prospects bequeathed by the ringbarkers. The seemingly practical problem of getting a look insinuates itself into individual psyche as uninterest, and into aesthetic society as a void. Few artists have discovered a vocabulary of ideograms adequate to these particular forests, a vocabulary adequate to the crowded experience of being in them. There are for me painters of the tallowwood country, who live in this ridge and gully country, not who have found solutions to these problems but opportunities in them. They are not opportunities though that have yielded logos for the art market. Dedication to the immense particularity of this crowded kind of nature is not an easy road to recognizable, retail style. Among many things, Ted Hillyer has turned to the forms cut into the forest by the light and spaces of coast, escarpment and culture. Joseph Conroy has looked at the meeting of clouds and canopy or turned to the nature morte at his feet, and painted still lives of the same intricate eucalypt litter that was eventually to kindle, fire up and consume many of his works, and that then, as a flame in the night, become a new subject against the blackened background. Otherwise the crowded tall wet forests remain largely uncaptured, unobjectifiable objects of distracted, uncomfortable apprehension, framed occasionally as noisy compositions in the glossies of bureaucracies and NGOs promoting the natural environment. No wonder burners think they are untended modern wildernesses of crowded spars and impenetrable undergrowth. Aesthetic sensibility demands a good burn. Most landscape painters have, like the farmers, moved further and further into the open country and especially, when it comes to national art, into the spiritual comfort of the pre-mythologized 80

interior, consigning the unframeable tedium of tall hardwood regrowth to scenic blue backdrops or a cultural unconscious of forestry and environmentalism. Wet sclerophyll is not the official light, look or landscape. It is a failure to confront the continent; it is cringing on the coast. Apart from strong timber, most of which can only be nailed green or drilled, they yield too little to have inspired more care, affection or passion than that which comes with the rough pragmatics of hardwood forestry, or the worthy but selective sentiments of green primevalism, or the ceaselessly restaged antagonism between the two. Beyond this antagonism over custody, few would think of this eternal backdrop to Australia, this backdrop supplied by utterly extra-human nature, as something whose poetic role would ever be more than that of the iconic one, that of an object for national imagesmostly in the background. The forests are just brute, physical facts. You either cut them down or you save them. Yet in this age of images when all things become images of themselves, eucalypts can be no exception. So to work on the image of eucalypts you have to work on the eucalypts. It is the same with most of nature now. I painted the eucalypt forest for a while, and then found I could not help working on the thing itself. Of all things in the bush though, eucalypts seem the most intractable, the most unyielding to anyone who would actually like to work on them. The bush has always signified the most recalcitrant streak in nature and hence nature in its most refractory otherness. And eucalypts are the epitome of this bush. So it turns out that even bush regeneratorsespecially bush regenerators like meseem to be dwarfed by eucalypts, in space by the physical presence, and in time both by their endurance and by the bustle of all that goes on inside them. As Baudelaire said of the city, the eucalypt forest changes faster than the human heart. And slower. Here in the Bellinger, we just walk under them most of the time like they are the great givens of nature, timeless pillars busy holding up the still or windy sky over our little world—and this is only the regrowth. We just employ ourselves weeding the understorey and letting the rainforest species colonize. In the backs of our minds we rely on the mighty eucalypts to just look after themselves in the long termcome fire or ferals. Or perhaps we try to not think too much about it. That’s easy. We can only do what we cannot help doing. Those who try burning in order to regenerate them encourage other sclerophyll plants, and weeds, but unless they burn the fire that particular eucalypt species wantand they all want different kindsthey too just manage the understorey, the lignotubers and the epicormic regrowth. Foresters in the wet forests have lost the will, the means, the skill, the inclination, the historical ecological conditions, the management structures and the market environment to regenerate all but a few species. Theirs has been and remains a practice with limited functions and one scarcely ever conceived as poetic, let alone undertaken as such. Few people get to see eucalypts come up at their instigationon the forest edge or somewhere else where deliberate and designed disturbance has been undertaken. Mostly they come up despite our intentions after a wildfire, or along the edge of a new road on bare subsoil that 81

only a callous engineer, busy at some task in another department of economic life, would dare cut into the living earth. Or they come up as cheap life in flood deposits in risky droves of seedlings, and someone who gets down on their knees and notices them and fences them off from stock can at least say that they have assisted them, like the humblest of servants of even more humble beings. All we can do is not let the opportunities pass, which they mostly do, rare and unseen. Of course, you can plant them. That’s what most do. They give reasons like forestry, firewood, integrated land management or carbon credits. I am talking about the big local forest trees. They stick them in clapped out pasture or eroded gullies or where it’s too harsh to get anything else to grow. They might have a windbreak, a wildlife corridor or koala habitat in mind. It is a green thing or a natural resource management thing. Beauty, like the flowers, is seldom mentioned. Gardeners are warned against them. Only the odd one slips into a backyardthe sign of a horticultural novice or philistine, a hopeless bush romantic; or else someone has a big yard. Personally, I hate planting trees. I don’t like all the botherdigging all those holes, getting the seedlings to the holes, putting them in, watering them, mulching them, putting guards around them, collecting the empty pots. I hate working bees plantings even more. Afterwards, some force of nature like a swamp wallaby or a vandal comes along anyway. One snacks on the seedlingsalways only the planted seedlingsas if they are sweets served up on a plate; the other labours blissfully and purposefullyalways only on the planted seedlings too. Or there is frost or drought or insects or fungus or god knows what, each working to restore the natural design. Worse than the planting, I never know what to plant or where. It keeps me awake at night. As soon as I plant a tree I see how wrong I have been to do it. Everything I plant is in the wrong place and I think everyone else plants the wrong things in the wrong places too. People often say that they don’t like seeing trees planted in rows because it looks regimented and unnatural. I think every planted tree looks like thiseucalypt plantings especially, because nearly anything looks regimented compared to native forests that have been laid out across the landscape as ecological noise. And when you think about the nuances of a site and the disgustingly profligate culling of natural seedlings it is no wonder that so many eucalyptus plantations look sad or odd. How can planting at a cutthroat thousand trees or dollars per hectare rival the idiotic abundance and magnificent waste of nature. It’s all so disheartening. Sometimes only the wallabies and vandals cheer me up. I have seldom met anyone who has actually forgotten about forestry or carbon credits or riparian rehabilitation or growth rates or establishment success and everything else, and set out to restore or imitate from scratch what might be thought of as a natural eucalypt foresta wet sclerophyll forest say. Not anyone who advertised it anyway. I am not sure whether people are only willing to admit to humbler intentions than emulating the nature of eucalyptus, or whether they are not willing to admit to such a humble intention. I suspect 82

people’s diffidence about this hides their equivocationand the eucalypt’s. Perhaps, of all plants, eucalypts and the bush they create are the most problematically natural and unnatural at the same time. For 40,000 years they have been fashionedfrom their landscape deployment right down to their genesby human fire, making them unnatural. But 40,000 years of human burning can only have affected eucalypt ecology in a way that exceeded human intentions, making them natural. But they have been regularly burnt several times within an individual’s life and burnt according to traditional cultural intentions, making them unnatural. But they live so much beyond a single human life and their evolution stretches out beyond the persistence of any culture, making them natural. And when people now make eucalypt forests they plant themin rows mind youmaking them unnatural. Yet if people did not plant them, there would just be degraded pasture and no amount of just waiting for them to regenerate or burning to encourage them would bring them back; and when the right species are planted in the right place and they get away, they can start to look like a forest monoculture of even-age self-sown juveniles powering away monopodially after a fire, and so unnaturally natural. They defy easy understanding. I have had a go at describing their rag-tag history, not their essence. They haven’t got one of those.

83

84

4 Lantana Portrait of a weed and what it does to the bush infested with it.

The floras all call it a shrub but it isn’t really. It is a scrambling climber or a shrubby scrambler. In the absence of anything to climb over, it scrambles back and forth over itself, criss-crossing canes that harden into a perplexing shrublike lattice with light green leaves and multicoloured flowers. The light canes are square in cross section with rows of sharp little recurved hooks along the four edges. The rough, toothed, ovate leaves grow in neat pairs on opposite sides of the canes. Given the support of shrubs or trees, it drapes its canes over them, holding on at first with the little hooks and climbing eventually up to a height of 10 or more metres. As the stems thicken and loose their hooks they hang off the trees like smooth, pale lianas. Under the tallowwood and blue gum forest on the main ridges, the understorey is a tangle of lantana, 2 or 3 metres high. It is thick and lush during warm wet whether and becomes thin and twiggy when it is dry. Higher up on the driest ridges under blackbutts, grey gums and forest oak, it is nearly always a bit thinner and twiggier. Where it is lush, it grows up over the understorey treesthe cheese trees, the red ash, the blackwood, the guoia, the scentless rosewood, the foambark, the malletwood, the sandpaper figbending them over and breaking them off. It is too thick to walk through. Its sticks poke you, the little hooks on the branches scratch you, and the rough leaves when brushed past give off a volatile aroma of musty sage and old moth balls. Well clothed and shod, you can make your way slowly, pushing through it, trampling over it or crawling under it, finding a line of least resistance, but seldom being able to go just where you want toto the base of that tree, along that gully, under those giant raspberriesand never getting an opportunity to trace the contours of the landthe little gullies, rises and depressions, the shapes of shrubs, ferns or herbs, or fallen logs or termite mounds. Said to be descended from native plants in the Caribbean and South Americaand probably native itself to the greenhouses of 18th century EuropeLantana camara now grows all around the world as a weed of the humid tropics and sub-tropics. It is one of the most famous weeds in Australiaalmost the generic weeda prominence recognized in its status as an honorary, if feral, native. A member of the Verbena family, the classification

85

of lantana is complicated by the horticultural selection that went into its breeding. This selection was done using specimens of uncertain origin whose offspring have in turn had extensive dissemination. Legend has it that Linnaeus himself managed to name it twiceLantana aculeata as well as Lantana camara. Lantana comes from a Latin name for the European wayfaring tree Viburnum lantanathe two species have similar looking flowers and leaves. Kamara is Greek for an arcade or covered carriage or anything with an arched cover. I’m not sure if that is where the camara comes from but it makes me think about tunnelling under arching canes of a lantana thicket and leaving little arched spaces that serve as children’s hideaways. For taxonomic convenience and in the absence of extensive DNA testing, the several recognized varieties are grouped as one species. Varieties differ in their chemical constitution, susceptibility to herbivores and parasites, flower colour, leaves and stem morphology. Popular culture distinguishes two varieties growing wild on the North Coast according to the dominant flower colour: the red and the pink. Get a bit more technical or look a bit closer and you will see five varieties—pink, white, pink-edged red, red, and orange—each with its distinct combination of cream, yellow, lilac, red, pinkish, reddish and orange buds and tubular flowers bunched together in its flowering heads near the ends of the canes. Each flower is a thin phial of nectar. They are fancied by the local eastern spinebill honeyeaters, as apparently the native lantanas of South America are by hummingbirds. To complicate things, most of the individual flowers are twotoned. What we used to call pink and red around here are strictly white and pink-edged red. The red lantanas are supposed to be poisonous to stock, causing liver damage and pathological sensitivity to sunlight. Swamp wallabies graze on (at least) the local white lantana all winter in the local gullies, trampling over it, thoroughly defoliating it and doing more damage than any other herbivore, mammalian or insectivorous. Of course, it all grows back thicker than ever in the summer. As a plant that epitomizes weeds, lantana has long been a favourite subject of trials and speculation about biological control. In 1902 one of the earliest reported attempts at biological control tried 15 insect species to control lantana in Hawaii (Thomas & Ellison). Similar trials in Australia have met with a consistency of failure that must be said to epitomize weed responses to biological control in general. Lantana holds the Australian records for the earliest introduction of a biological control agent (1914) and the most introduced agents (at least 24) (Adair, 191). The difference in lantana strains, particularly in their toxicity, is often cited as contributing to the difficulty of finding control agentsroutinely assumed to be pests that eat or blight the thing back in its natural home. Nothing controls every strainor any strain, for that matterbut then what would have fed on it back in those European hot houses lantana calls home? When a friend had the gorm (or gall) to suggest at a conference that swamp wallabies were a biological control the gormless laughter verged on derisive. The fact that no one thinks of marauding swamp wallabies browsing a gully full of lantana back to bare trampled canes as 86

biological control, says something about the heedlessness of searches for biological control. So they press on between the carrot of the miracle and the stick of the unmiraculous, always busily looking forward to the next possibility that might just appear out of somewhere in South America; always excusing the latest unmiraculous results with the wise counsel that any introduced insect or fungus was never going to be a single fatal blow but only one tool of ‘multipronged’ control; always using that weedy-word ‘control’. It grows anywhere, means anything. The searchor rather the foreshadowed, recommended, hoped for, believed in, or eschatological searchfor the philosophers stone of biological control is a seductive ecological custom perfectly adapted to the cultural rationale of ‘environmental weeds’: ecological controls must exist somewhere otherwise lantana would be out of control everywhere, which would be an affront to the balance of nature. Control must therefore come down to a question of how many components of those balanced, faraway ecosystems we have to introduce here, in order to balance our own. ‘Balance’ is a weedy word too. In the natural history of weed control culture the value of searching is balanced against the unlikelihood of finding. Perhaps if swamp wallabies were insects from South America, they would have been granted the prestige of ‘possible agents’ and given a role in ‘integrated weed management’. The pretty flowers and the ability of this climber to climb back over itself and form thick bright green hedges and bowers are the features that attracted the interest of gardeners. Specimens probably arrived in Australia some time before 1840 from stock that had been earlier introduced to South Africa. Lantana was already on the North Coast by 1848. While staying with the Innes family at Port Macquarie, Anabella Boswell recorded in her journal for 31st March: ‘We have been busy tidying up Lantana Bower, but so many young plants have sprung up they quite spoil the place, and are likely to become a nuisance.’ She also remarks that the plant had been brought to Colonel Innes’s garden from Alexander Macleay’s extensive botanical collection in his garden at Elizabeth Bay in Sydney. The fruits are little blue-black drupes, sweet and sort of edible when ripe, and said to contain poisonous triterpenes when green. Native birds such as Lewin’s honeyeaters, currawongs and bowerbirds eat them and spread the seeds around. In comparatively little time, and with a little assistance from gardeners looking for pretty, acclimatized plants, and loggers and land-clearers disturbing soil and understorey and canopy, the birds eventually managed to spread lantana right through the moist forests of the east coast of Australia. It has its uses. The leaves are just about hard and rough enough to sand very soft smooth wood for a very short time. The canes have been cut and chewed a bit on the end and used to ‘brush’ teethsomewhere where they don’t have toothbrushes. Camping on a coastal inlet, some friends once wove a fish trap from the canes and caught a feckless Wobbegong in it. Best of all, the particoloured flowers can be pulled off in handfuls to make splendid confetti for weddings, parties, and impromptu decorating. And there are always the little 87

blue-black fruitssomething sweetish to taste, at least they are not as poisonous as when they are still green, and besides it would be hard to eat enough of them. Down off the tops of the ridges and spurs where the forest gets moisterand still under the tallowwoods, blue gums and flooded gumsthe lantana gets thicker and it climbs higher in the trees and over the shrubs. It gets laced occasionally with giant raspberry, prickly sarsaparilla, cockspur, lawyer palm, native grape and morinda vines, so when you are pushing or crawling through you are likely to be torn, stabbed, hooked, tripped of strangled by one or other of these. Occasionally there are patches where a rainforest understorey of jackwood, murrogun, possumwood, sandpaper fig, palms and tree ferns manages to push the lantana and the vines up enough to make crawling under it easier. Where trees fall and sunny gaps form, the lantana grows thicker. Walking through gaps is not an option. In the bottom of the gullies it is all gap and therefore full of impassable lantana. The narrow rainforest gullies were cleared for grazing, but with too much competition and shade for grasses and a decline in grazing numbers, and the lantana invaded with a vengeance. Here the mass is 3 metres high, in a thick snarl. Stems shoot over one another and over the ground, rooting and re-rooting. Few other plants grow apart from giant raspberry and native grape vines or sometimes just a little twiner maybe, like the forest glycine. Any trees struggle under the combination of lantana and the native vines. Eventually they die.

Throughout its modern history, the bush has regularly (though by no means universally) been imagined as an uninviting place. To many eyesmost famously Darwin’s when he travelled form Sydney up to the Blue Mountains during his Beagle voyagemuch of it has been a drab and melancholy place of shadeless hard leaved trees, tuneless birds, and sun-bleached ground littered with strips of bark, sticks and leaves. It was seen as melancholy and fallen right from the first encounter, never blessed with a pristine beauty, but only ever old and worn out. At best it could be graced by distanceas picturesque background to rural life or the hazy blue backdrop of sublime vistas. When people drive now along the highways of the east coast, there is a relentless sense of its dull damaged form strung out endlessly along the road. The monotony is broken only by the bleak scare tissue of hot service station towns and half-hearted holdings hacked out of the bush. It all brings on a familiar weariness and an impatience to reach destinations. Even the tall moist eucalypt forest around here was seen this way. It never quite achieves the lush charms of the rainforest, let alone the comforts of flower-strewn temperate woods. From the nineteenth century it was seen as being good for hardwood forestryalthough in need of good silvicultural discipline to get more trees of decent form. Otherwise it was a problem for agriculture, full of tough, greedy, hard-leaved trees, difficult to clear, quick to grow back, and messy and unpalatable when it did, slow going on foot, horse or 88

vehicle, and full of discomforts and unseen dangers like snakes, ticks, spiders, and lacerating vines, and those desperate, terrified screams at nightnot, in short, a place to venture into unwarily. ‘Only strangers, the very poor and the dead walk in it,’ wrote Les Murray (1997, 57). ‘Of the living, no-one who belongs to the bush walks any further in it than they can help.’ Stories and pictures of lost children are customary in Australian arteven in Aboriginal traditionand in contemporary news. According to Meaghan Morris (2001), the experience of non-specific panic in the bush is a well-known cultural symptom, a “narcissistically ‘bounced’, accusatory historical gaze.” Wariness of it and boredom with it are each instilled in the young for their own and their parents’ comfort, and carried as habits into adult life. This is one version of a process that might be called the infantilization of culture. It operates, for good and ill, in the evolution of a wide range of social formswhether in the acquisition of languages and literacies or in the market dominance of fluffy white bread or bad Hollywood movies. Childish habits become traditional forms of adult society. When the alien, unentered eucalypt forest of the east coast was cleared or logged or grazed or burnt and thereafter developed a dense, impenetrable lantana understorey, it regrew in an exaggerated image of the bush’s already alien character. This reified forest was even more impenetrable and therefore further alienated. Few people see a bit of bush and just walk straight into it. What for? It’s not our culture. It is just not done. And especially not if lantana is blocking the way. You can’t get into it. As for the rainforest gullies, they just became solid lantana with no overstorey of trees to at least give the consolation of a forest structure. We might like to put this down to neglect or abandonment, but if so, it is neglect and abandonment as self-replicating forms of culture. Weeds are despised but, for most people, weeding is even more despised. It is drudgery, and, if it comes to it, expensive drudgery. So the vast lantana scrubs rarely attract any remedial work apart from the easy exercise of waiting for biological control. Under the pall of anticipated drudgery, and with the widespread sense of the impossibility of successful control, social forms that either deny any long-term problem, or even value lantana take on a lease of life. As a lush understorey, lantana has a nice green look to some eyes, a look that relieves the drabness of the native vegetation. Lantana quickly covers exposed sites so it has long been credited with preserving soil and habitat. Soil erosion and habitat loss are almost universally claimed to be undesirable and so lantana has taken on a certain conservation value. ‘Without lantana the whole valley would have been washed out to sea.’ ‘It was the salvation of a lot of this country.’ These are phrases from lantana culture, a culture that rescues whatever virtue it can from a necessity made real by its own declaration. ‘It’s inevitable.’ Tim Low, maintaining his pitch in The New Nature (2002, 91-3) and The Feral Future (1999, 240-1) has given us a recent version of this culture. Native animals are said to depend on lantanabees live in its stems, birds feed on its flowers and fruits. When a patch was weeded in Vaucluse in Sydney in the 89

1960s, the last mainland population of the eastern quoll lost its cover and died out. Not only are these things true, they are legends. In The Sydney Morning Herald (17/8/2) Low was quoted saying ‘there does not seem to be anything that can replace it.’ The environmental consultant, Mike Olsen was quoted saying that ‘it’s filling an ecological niche.’ There is always something tautological in the way an adapted species is supposed to fit its niche like a glove. Try defining a niche in terms of the particular environmental conditions and role that species are able to occupy, and try doing it exhaustively and exclusively so that you distinguish the precise conditions and precise role of a particular niche, and pretty soon you start defining the niche by its occupant. ‘Very few native plants furnish food and shelter for so many,’ says Low (2002, 92) ‘…it has become a keystone species for wildlife. No other weed so ingratiates itself with animals. If lantana disappeared overnight most whipbirds would be homeless and many wallabies would die from dog attacks.’ The Herald article says whipbirds and scrubwrens ‘disappear’ when you weed lantana out. A little grammatical tinkering to change the past tense ‘disappeared’ to the universal present and what researchers saw once under particular conditions in Queensland becomes a universal truth. Happily the whipbirds and scrubwrens around here have ignored thisbut then here, the disappearing lantana didn’t do it overnight. That only happens in the land of outlandish hypotheses. If its not lantana's function for wildlife, it is its function in forest regeneration: ‘When rainforest is cleared it’s the first plant to clothe the bare earth, before the rainforest returns’ (2002, 93). Trivially, pretty soon there can be nothing that can replace lantana, insofar as it is lantana doing whatever it is lantana does, in precisely the way lantana does itunless it is lantana itself. In this though, lantana is pretty much like everything from thistles to wild blackberries to Tasmanian tigers to unicorns. Lantana, like the one hundred and sixty odd plant species that have colonized the country around here where it has been weeded out, ‘is integrated into the environment.’ There are twenty native species that are new to this place since the lantana has disappeared. The lantana must have effectively displaced or even replaced them for half a century, yet now it seems nothing is supposed to be able replace it. Once people start declaring tautologies and pleonasms as world historical conclusions, all sorts of empty notions start to look like surprising ecological findings, or else just plain undeniable common sense. Lantana becomes a refuge for the slippery rhetoric of a book’s sales pitch. Niches for non-sequiturs open up in the argument landscape of environmental culture. An environmental consultant can say ‘It has become such an intimate part of the whole process that we are not going to be able to change it,’ as if intimacy implies inevitability. The intimacy of ‘intimacy’ and the holier-thanthou holism of ‘whole’ join emotive forces with the technicality of ‘process’ in a claim that is even better adapted to the disturbed landscape of environmental culture than the lantana is to the disturbed landscape of the forest. ‘It is not worth controlling anymore.’ The point is though, it is quite a good thing to 90

weed lantana out, if you are interested in just seeing something that is beautiful and intricate. You can readily get rid of it and then watch the native species do that ‘clothe the bare earth’ thing. Finally the folk culture of lantana promises an eventual homecoming anyway: it is believed lantana eventually just dies out anyway and the native bush takes overall is redeemed by time and succession and good old nature itselfa dubious or at the very best a specific observation that has conveniently been universalized into a consoling prophecy of a happily drudge and weed free future. For an authoritative and thus reproductively successful ancestor in the genealogy of this idea there are remarks in a paper on rainforest regeneration by Alex Floyd. (1991, 25), and also in Low (2002). For a grain or two of salt though, there are studies that describe just how persistent lantana scrub remains (Gentle and Duggin, 1997; and Fensham et al, 1994). I look to my own experience, waiting for the stuff to just die out of the local gullies. I have been waiting for years now and there is not much dying outexcept of native trees that have struggled on and on and ended up succumbing to the stuff. Even if it is hard to like, Australians have spent a lot of time learning to like the harsher realities of nature. Forms of acquired taste seem to be the opposite of the infantilization of culturebut I am not sure that they are not almost the same thing sometimes. The transcendent aesthetic efforts of sublime apprehensioncombined with its penchant for ignoring detailthe grudging fondness that comes with time and memory, and humorous resignation attributed to experience have all been enlisted in the development of lantana culture. By naming and getting a cameo in Ray Lawrence’s film, it put another seal on its status as a rich cultural symbollantana, those three evocative syllables, with a lilt to rival the labials of Nabokov’s Lolita or the lush modulations Lana Turner. The present situation is that, informed ecology, conservationist values and the biogeographical history of lantana notwithstanding, a particular attitude to the bush, a particular image of the bush, a particular evaluation of lantana and a particular theory about lantana populations have all become self perpetuating in the popular culture of eastern Australian environmental management. This is reflected in the documents we produceand not simply in the spoken and written ones but in the living ones as well. It is reflected in that particular, lantana-infested version of material culture we on the North Coast call the bush. ~ One of us at least, had been weeding out lantana for agesthe one who had been foolish enough to suggest wallabies as biological control. Picking up her long-handled loppers in the afternoon, walking down into the bush, cutting plants at their base, pulling up the stems and attached roots, sometimes resting on a stump and having a look around and watching a yellow robin homing in to make inquiries about the newly exposed ground. After rain, seedlings of red ash or blackwood might appear. Or clematis, grape, raspberry, tamarind, cudgerie, 91

red cedar, white beech, or brown kurrajong. Occasional fronds of gristle, ground or rasp fern would start to multiply. Sandpaper figs, scentless rosewoods, cheese trees, brush capers and guioas that had been bent over under the lantana would straighten and expand their crowns. She was careful to leave all the native vineseven the vicious flesh tearers, jaggers, stabbers and stranglersand although they still had a go at us, without the lantana they did not seem to trouble the trees anywhere near as much. As the dead lantana sticks dried out and fell to the ground, the lie of the land was revealed. The whole of a forking spur and the gully in between the forksThe Blue Gum Forest and the South East Cornerwas rediscovered. It was like finding a new country or a lost country brought back. Eventually I started helping, instead of just walking through the new land in a gratified daze. One day, at a place that came to be called The Conversion Site, I saw some shield ferns, and it entered my head that the bit of lantana in the little gap under the tall red ashes could just be weeded out. Just like that. And it stayed in my head. Everyday I found just another little bit that took my fancy. We walked and worked and weeded in places we never walked before, uncovered dried up waterfalls, unknown plants, secret places. Instead of looking uniformly dark and musty, the deeper gullies became lively with shapes and hues and spaces that had all been censored. Where there had been just vegetative noise, an elaborate harmony developed. Instead of smelling of stale sage and naphthalene we could smell sassafras and soil and water and clear air. Besides the ferns and seedlings, panic and basket grasses began to run over the floor of the forest, blue lobelias and pastel flowers appeared like new constellations. Clumps of forest sedge, fine-flowered finger grass, wild raspberry, native lemon grass and ginger grew. We had never thought of the forest as a place of grass and flowering herbs, but that was what it really was and wanted to be. We saw orchids that looked like nothing we had ever encountered: potato orchids, grub orchids, beard orchids, midge orchids. We had to invent names for them. On valley floors we found sedges coming up that had never grown there before, and pollia, aneilema and nettles, and the big bright green cunjevois with summer flowers like fleshy aerials transmitting a sweet electric scent through the still shadows and sunlight. Because we went over every inch of land as we weeded, we saw everywhere, and every plantsingle specimens of unanticipated species like helicia, hairy rosewood, maiden’s blush, black apple, Oliver’s sassafras, cabbage palm, the blue-leaved grey walnut, giant blood vine, and furry milk vine. We found a lot of specimens of the rare clear-sapped milk vine that had to be untwined from lantana as we weeded it. We had to hide it in the foliage of other plants otherwise the wallabies or possums would it eat it back to the ground as soon as they found it exposed. And there were plants that we had never encountered anywhere else before, that just seemed to come up under the new dispensationthe rare Senna acclinis whose hard seeds must have rested for god knows how long in the ground, the small-leaved bleeding heart, and the bell-fruit tree. It was like the sleeping beauty, as if for half a century the whole 92

place had been drugged by lantana balm and now we were clearing the air and scratching the earth’s back and it was stretching and turning over and waking up to memories almost forgotten. And every animal. When it was wet, leeches were alive on the ground, undeviating in wild blood-lust, or we found them later gorged and slobbering around our waists and ankles. We found shellback ticks behind our ears, under our arms, in our groins, crawling on our hairthe only wild animal that I have never actually seen in the bush, but only on humans or domestic animals. In the humid summers it would be mosquitoes and midges, and in late summer the tiny grass ticksbaby shellbacksmigrating by the thousand up legs, seeking a sweaty sanctuary to embed themselves in the skin. From itchy experience you learn to notice them in time to wash and scrub them off. You learn about the paper wasps to. They are exacting teachers. Bitten once by a paper wasp you leave that patch unweeded until winter. There were jumping ants decorating their mounds with tallowwood calyptras, red ash capsules or the fringed leaflets of blue-skin wattles, jumping at anyone who blundered upon them or who dared to weed a seedling from their front porch, or dropping from branches onto necks or arms, biting the unwary with venomous resolve. Crawling through a viny gully on a warm summer evening you might come face to face with a little angle-headed dragon edging its way around the trunk of a sandpaper fig. Or if you were sitting, resting, it might signal its presence by running over the dry leaves. A goanna would eye you from the bloodwood you had forced it up. A fat land mullet would slip its sleek, black body under the edge of a fallen log, a kilo or two of solid skink. A marsh snake might slip away under your feet, or bird alarms might go up around a carpet python trying to idle along a liana. Swamp wallabies would lurk in cissus, browsing on any old leaf, until they could no longer help but make a jump. A little one padded around me one day thinking I was a tree fern or something. When I whistled like a bird it twitched its ears with curiosity, and finally thought it wiser to lope away up a gully. Wongas would fly up off the forest floor as you approached, their wings whistling with the effort of lifting those fat pigeon breasts. Brush turkeys patrolled the forest, raking up litter, whipbirds called to one another across your path, Log-runners tried diverting your attention with their cry of ‘quick quick quick’. One little brown bandicoot would turn over the soil and leaf litter under an entire patch of weeded flooded gums, digging holes a foot deep into the subsoil, cone-shaped to fit its nose or to sprain your ankle. Male koalas would start grunting or females start screaming back up the gully where you had just been walking, as if they had waited for you to move through before they gave themselves away. Or you might see one taking advantage of the clear passage to walk where the lantana had been weeded. It was easier going for everyone. Noisy pittas appeared one summer and stayed, as if to take advantage at last of the clear run across the forest floor. ‘Walk to work,’ they said, or ‘Squawk the squawk,’ every evening. And suddenly we started finding the empty shells of giant snails left by the pittas along the gully floors. There was a dead pitta on 93

the track one evening, so small and frail under its feathers, a little bit of clear sky blue against its dark olive back, the deep fading gold of its breast, and the red and the black. But there were still pittas. And then there was always the next evening, the next patch, cutting around that new fig near the fallen flooded gum, following our noses, wandering apart and whistling to one another like Lewin’s honeyeaters to keep track, getting back to somewhere to see what we had missed before it all grew back too much, pulling up stems that had layered under the leaves, or new lantana seedlings, watching and wondering about whatever little thing came up, seeing what wallabies would graze back to twigs or the ground, and always pushing a little further up the gully, finding a new place, even just reaching an arm a stretch further through the vines to get that stem at the limit, or just finishing off those last few up there before it got too dark. The same and new every day. Other things came up too, things we did not want. Lantana was not the only weed, and weeding it out created an opportunity for newer, more treacherous intruders like broad-leaved paspalum, crofton weed and even a catsclaw creeper. They weren’t as much fun but we just weeded them out too. On winter evenings squawk the squawk at sunset said time to go home, and the yellow robins would chirp to one another down among the tree trunks and pipe our easy walk back along the wallaby tracks, dreaming or whistling.

94

5 The Fan The restoration of a bit of bush.

The Fan is just one place, a triangle of land at the bottom of a gully. We weeded everywhere and everywhere we found a name. A gentle pubic mound between two joining branches of the gully, its full name is The Frangipani Fan, from the tall native frangipani tree clinging on the edge where the western branch suddenly cuts deep. From the road around the back of the gully, we used to catch sight of this tree when it flowered, way down below us, through the viny scrub, surrounded by lantana. It was the place there was no way to. The closest we got in thirteen years was once when we pushed our way through to a tower of vines on the eastern side of The Fan, gathering the fruits of Rubus nebulosa, the giant native raspberry vine. Over the years we weeded our way down through the tallowwood forest and then the vine forest on the eastern side of the gully. We reached The Big Red Bean in the eastern branch of the gully, and at last discovered what we now call The Lost Rainforest on the steep slope overlooking the northern side of The Fana tangle of cissus, prickly rubus, vicious calamus, and (back then) lantana thrown over a canopy of caldcluvia, possumwood, sassafras and white beech. As you cross these gullies, slope, aspect, soil, moisture, and seasonal sunshine all change constantly, and the vegetation changes with them. Everywhere is what ecologists sometimes call ecotone—a zone of transition between two ecosystems, between rainforest and eucalypt forest. Viny gully rainforest takes over from the open eucalypt forest where moisture is more persistent. Of course, ever since the turn of the centurywhen this country was first ring-barked, burnt and fencedaxes, chainsaws, brush hooks, bulldozers, cattle, weeds and ferals have toned up those ecotones even more. Only real estate agents seem to be confident giving this weedy, gully scrub the name rainforest. It doesn’t really get an official label in Alex Floyd’s (1990) classification of rainforests, because tallowwoods, flooded gums and other eucalypts are often a part of the picture, or more often, there’s a stump to remind you that they once wereand may well be again. Floyd’s classification applies to relatively mature and persistent rainforest communities, those that seem to havein the past at leaststood the test of time, their integrity uncomplicated by eucalypts with their dry, fiery, catastrophic histories. In order

95

to describe the kind of closed forest that grows in these gullies now, let’s just call it a Red Ash-Jackwood alliance with a Cudgerie-Red Bean-Red CedarWhite Beech suballiance on the warmer sites and a Sassafras-CaldcluviaPossumwood suballiance on the cooler, damper southerly sites. It’s a bit misleading though, that these vegetation alliances are conventionally named using dominant canopy trees, otherwise the cissus vines would get their names in there too. So would the lantana. The Fan was pure lantana scrub, two or three meters deep and thick. We started on The Fan itself by weeding a path straight through the scrambled mass of lantana, just so we could cross from The Big Red Bean and stand at last under the falling frangipani flowers. By weeding, I mean cutting the lantana stems with loppers, reaching down and pulling the stems out by the roots, and so gradually wrestling our way through the prickly tangle. Really, it was easy bush regeneration. No deadlines, no management plans, no community liaison, no grant applications, no herbicide, no planting, no plastic tree guards, no vandals, no horror weed species. It was pure lantanaso dark and thick and layered and abnormally mulchy at the bottom that almost nothing else grew there. Apart from one common native speciesthe slender forest glycine that managed to twine its way through the matrix of the lantanawe found a small sassafras, an unexpected little patch of bracken, and the odd struggling frangipani seedling. We had no trouble persisting with the task. It was a pleasure. It was like wrestling. We even worried that we might eventually finish. Two of us weeded in the late afternoons, and not always at The Fan. It was one site along a front, so we didn’t do it all at once. We took three summers to cross the fifty metres of Fan, and as we pushed into the wall of tana the regenerating vegetation came up in waves behind us. So here we were on The Fan, having weeded down to bare ground and litter, and under the open sky. Now we would be able to compare The Fan’s succession, starting from scratch, with the usual models. Rainforest regenerators seem to await the four stages of succession like the second coming. It is not always clear though whether a particular model is being used as a prediction or a norm. Whatever. The trouble is that vines, herbs and fauna get scant mention in most versions of the models, yet they insinuate themselves into the actual works with a vengeance. Fauna, especially the swamp wallabies and us, have been major players on The Fan, greatly affecting the flora. And when Time comes on stage it is extravagant, rehearsing more structural and floristic combinations than models dare dream of, running whole generations of seedlings, only to cut them down for the sake of some herbivore and start again. If you classify plant species by their typical stages, or stages by their typical species, everything was a bit of a jumble. On the other hand, if you just call what happens in the first five years Stage 1, then Stage 1 consisted of many stages. Like Russian Dolls it was stages all the way down. So far, things have gone like this:

96

The lantana that we had missed during the primary weeding resproutednever from roots, only from stems. Lots of seedlings of Phytolacca octandra and P. americanum appeared. So did broad-leaved paspalumthe accursed, shade-tolerant pasture grasscarried in (I think) on wallaby fur. And there was wild tobacco, white passionflower, whiskey grass, crofton weed, spear thistle, thick head, Indian strawberry and Mullumbimby couch. All exotics. But, along with the forest glycines that had survived the shock of the primary weeding, there were seedlings of prickly nightshade (Solanum prinophyllum), kangaroo apple, native frangipani, brown kurrajong, red ash, sandpaper fig, blackwood, trema, pencil cedar, and the odd white cedarpresumably the offspring of a parent growing halfway up the eastern ridge. I think most of thesethe trees at leastwould be called Stage 3, but they had not read the stage instructions and came on well before cue. As we followed up pulling out the exotics, the swamp wallabies cleaned up all the woody native seedlings, except for the white cedars, pencil cedars, frangipanis, and the prickly nightshadethe low, prickly annual whose constellations of blue flowers would eventually mark the completion of the first year’s regeneration. By then, pittosporum beetles were defoliating all the frangipanis and borers were finishing off all but one of the pencil cedars. When the exhausted nightshades mulched before our eyesleaving only their fruits, like purple eggs in nests of pricklesthe sedge, Cyperus tetraphyllus, and the umbrella fern, Pteris tremula, revealed themselves, showing us that at least nothing was eating them. Where we weeded paspalum, the sedge in particular got the chance nowadays denied it by the grass. After two years, the umbrella ferns lost vigour, and rough ground fern (Hypolepis muelleri), having apparently colonized by spore, took off with the sedges all over the parts of The Fan that had been weeded early on. The patch of bracken asserted itself too for a while, and forest lobelia, wild raspberry, ginger, forest pennywort, centella, dianella, native bryony, muehlenbeckia, morinda, pollia, two kinds of aneilema, and two kinds of cissus were all there. In the winters, the wallabies trampled and burrowed through the ferns, browsed on the trees and shrubs (except for white cedars), and generally lurked, as swamp wallabies do. When you walk onto The Fan, you hear them thump as they jump away, and it smells of wallaby. In nearby gullies they spend the winter eating and trampling their way through fields of lantana. Now, in the fifth summer, the downy ground fern (Hypolepis glandulifera) has also apparently colonized by spore, and along with wild raspberry it’s all through the first areas we weeded. So too are many seedlings of many more species. Weeds now so dominate moist, sunny sites that this kind of native herbaceous community is a rarity on the North Coast lowlands. It is also a rarity because of the way we restore rainforests. Rainforest regenerators seem to like to go for the quickest establishment of tree canopy possible, ‘skipping stages’, ‘speeding up succession’, sacrificing unnecessary vines and herbsand their attendant fauna. Canopy is a defining feature of rainforests, and, of course, canopy makes maintenance easier, reducing the resilience or increasing the 97

generation time of most weedsa handy mix of essence and efficiency. And it seems that not only is canopy our tool for our intentions, it’s the rainforest’s tool as wellits ‘own’ functional adaptation for its ‘own’ self-perpetuation. This suspiciously neat coincidence of human and ecosystem teleology is so irresistible, no wonder canopy becomes the be all and end all. Meanwhile the passing pleasures are forgotten as just thatmerely passing. The pleasure of The Fan has not been that of reaching targets, achieving outcomes or satisfying performance indicators. We haven’t restored a predesignated and persistent natural community, whose credentials are now there to be contemplated once and for all. Instead, we’ve had the pleasure of following the peculiar detailsmany of them inconsequentialof a long slow, convoluted narrative, with us as players. Because of the accidents of natural history, each stage following each treatment has been slightly different from the corresponding stages set in motion by earlier treatments. And as we have worked our way across The Fan, various stages of ‘Stage 1’ have all been arrayed behind us in a kind of tableau of that history. After five years there were still no trees except for the few white cedars, the one original little sassafras, a stunted pencil cedar, and some struggling frangipanis. It seemed like a grove of widely spaced white cedars might be developing as the tree canopy. Something I have never seen. Is this natural or unnatural history? Shouldn’t we be busy trying to get a real rainforest with a real canopy up on real trunks? In nearby gullies, red ashes, cudgeries, red beans, red cedars, sandpaper figs, brown kurrajongs or pencil cedars readily take off. More often than not they carry a heavy blanket of cissus and rubus up with them too, to form the canopy. Here it’s different. Everywhere’s different. Every time’s different. Here at The Fan we like our Swamp Wallaby-White Cedar-Ground Fern suballiance. And, anyway, it won’t last. No end of restoration is ever the end.

98

6 Belonging and Naming One person’s relation to a bit of bush.

…to adventure for a change in one place. —Jack McLaren, My Crowded Solitude

Who belongs to what, or what belongs to whom? I walk up the spur behind the Red Cedars, the Cedars Spur it’s called. My hands and eyes have been all over this country. Even so it is always changing and always new. Immediately behind the deep shade that the cedars cast I draw my hand along the strong familiar blades and culm of a gymnostachys up to the blue fruits. A little further on, I put my nose up in the air and try to trace the source of the fleeting odour of bolwarra, sweet like the vanilla and olive oil in an old Greek milkbar. It reminds a friend of her aunt’s kitchen in Friesland. I slip under a cockspur without getting caught and address it as my friend, brush by the sweet, musky foliage of wild raspberry, climb over an even mat of litter under a grove of forest oaks and sit looking back down through the trees over the Red Cedars, over the forested spurs that run away to the south and the east. There is a whiff of wallaby in the air, sweet as urine and fur. One has been resting here. Grey Thrush is singing like an angel above menot an angel in reverence or awe of god, but an angel delighting to explore and play the range of its voice. Grey Fantail comes to chatter to me between titbits taken on the wing. I sit and wait as long as I like and visitors keep coming: a varied triller just above, trilling to another down the spur; king parrots chiming way up in a tallowwood before screeching and belting off; a turkey scratching its way up the slope until, coming out of a scrub turpentine thicket, until it notices me and goes about on its black rudder of a tail and paces back into cover. In the distance I can see the blue-grey eye of the Pacific on the left and the perfect cone of Nunguu Mirral on the rightalso known as Valla Mountain and Pickett’s Hillbut from here there is no sign of the farms in the Bellinger valley or of the river and roads that pass along the valley between me and Valla. It could all be bush. It could all be 1000 years ago. Can I say that I belong to this country? Belonging is like belief. I don’t think it matters to me. ‘Most of all, I feel connected’ says Peter Timms in the final sentence of Making Nature. What is

99

this longing for connection? Connection to what? Perhaps I am just modern and my condition is what Georg Lukacs called transcendental homelessness. If that is what I am, then it is something that I am not unhappy to be. I am particularly pleased to think that for some reason this is supposed to be a cause for regret. All the same, if I am to be transcendentally homeless, then I would prefer to be that here and happily in this forest, where every tree and vine and herb is familiar and surprising and a delight, where every little place has a name and a story. I would prefer simply not to be concerned about whether or not I belong to this place, right here where I call nearly all the birds that call by their first name and where even the shy forest wallabies relax their wariness and watch us come and go. Blissfully, they pursue their purposes among our belongings, properly beyond belonging. I don’t have to sit up under the forest oaks and assure myself that I feel connected. I don’t know what it would feel like to feel connected, but it sounds like being caught in someone else’s category, a category that I don’t belong to. Places name themselves here, or the names just happen. We are their mouthpieces. We find ourselves uttering them as we emerge from the trance of close attention, of going over every square metre of them with our hands and our eyes. The Red Cedars grow in a patch of rainforest on a little level stage of land about 40 metres above see level. I am on the Cedars Spur above the Red Cedars. The gap in the forest canopy on the western side of the Cedars Spur is the Top Gap and below it the steep shady slope of caldcluvias and possumwoods that we call The Original Rainforest because that was the little patch of rainforest we saw when we first walked around the back of The Glow Worm Gully following the 40m contour. Below the Red Cedars to the east there is the steep vicious tangle of prickly giant rubus vinesThe Slippery Slopewhere we had to weed the lantana, stalk by stalk, from the matrix of rubus. To the west there is another slope of caldcluvias and possumwoods and cissus. For a long time we did not know it was there, so years later when we discovered it, we also discovered its nameThe Lost Rainforest. To the west again there is The Shelf a place of ground ferns, saw sedge, lawyer palm and pink hibiscus; and below The Shelf, The Ledge of bangalow palms, tree ferns and vines above the gully called The Glow Worm Gully. Going down the gully there are places named The Fan, The Big Red Bean off on a side gully, The Confluence where the Glow Worm, Gate and Big Red Bean Gullies meet, and at the end of The Confluence, The Boat with its flooded gums and pollia and The Big White Mahogany on its bow. Up on the eastern slope are The White Beeches, and further along, the little patches of sassafras between the gumsThe Sass Pockets. Down past The Boat, past The Sandpaper Figs towards the little dam, the gully changes name to The Dam Gully. The western side of the gully is The West Bank. From north to south The West Bank is divided into The Lone Sassafras, The Laurels where the two big murroguns grow, The North West Bankan open gap, The Lone Tamarind, Gate Spur and Gate Gully. The western side south of Gate Gully is called The Western Slope. Along here, below The Turkey Track that follows the top of the ridge, there are 100

The Blackbutt Spur with The Big Blackbuttits ancient top knocked out and its northern side hollowed out by termites and fire, The Wreckwhere someone dumped the dead Holden back in the 60s, The Wreck Contour and The Wreck Gully, and The Entrance Track, the way we crawled and scrambled onto this place the very first day came here, and The Entrance itself framed by the looping stems of palm lilies. Below the dam on the east is Woman’s Worlda moist, tangled viny place where men are loathe to venture. But on the west there is still no known name. No one has seen it yet or heard it. No one has spent enough time there. Across on the other side of the main ridge where it branches out of the Cedars Spur below the Red Cedars are the Traffic Lights, and the Snig Tracka spur up which a friend and I winched a big tallowwood log. We tried at first to roll it up with crowbars, only to have it roll back down just as we reached the top. And there is The Snig Track Edgenow called Cudgerie Edge because of all the cudgeries that grew up there after we weeded out the lantana. The seed was blown in on the nor’easter from the big cudgerie at Cudgerie Corner. Further down the spur you pass The Pointstwo fingers of vinecovered trees that point out into an open gap that is being colonized now by pencil cedars. Beyond The Points are the Big Dead Tree and the land to its east, the Dead Tree Extension. South of the Big Dead Tree where a jackwood and red ash forest grows on the bottom of the spur as it spreads out between two joining gullies is The Groin. Just to the west of The Groin in a gap next to some shield ferns and orange lomandras there is The Conversion Site, the little place where I first started weeding out some lantana with the inkling that I would not be able to help coming back the next day, and the next. And the next. It was as good as a vision of the future can get. The Groin itself opens out into a gravelly sluice where privets and paspalum used to grow, and it runs down to The Big Dam. Now its ground ferns and red beans and all sorts of other things. On the northwest, at the bottom of Symplocus Ridge, is a stand of straight flooded gums, 30 metres tall, surrounding a couple of their older spreading forebearsThe Flooded Gums. On the south, on the right looking down the gully is The Wedge and, further up the hill, The Triangle. Below The Big Dam, on the south is The North East Corner. I am glad we know these names. I can say that I am going to the Big Red Bean and it’s as good as a grid reference. Better. Topography of course gets lost in a tangled string of language when it comes to naming these places one after another. I could draw them on a map, but really they are places spoken of and reached on foot. Walking through the forest one day, a friend who lives in wheat and sheep country said ‘You can own this?’ Where he lives its acres, paddocks, pasture, stock and crop that you own. Or a ute or a house in town. These things just feel like commodities, possessions. And you can see them. Everywhere is a vantage point, almost as good as the mapmaker’s. Here what comes with the acres is forest, a daunting abundance of it, busy producing itself and full of birds, wallabies, koalas, possums, snakes, lizards, the lot. All singing their own song, screeching their screech, owning only themselves. You and they can’t inventory 101

it or them. From anywhere you can see almost nowhere else. Everyone and thing is too busy. Ownership: it’s a word for life coaches, counselors, lawyers and real estate agents. Goethe said ‘what you really own you can’t throw away.’ I like Walter Benjamin’s shocking definition: ownership is the most intimate relation we can have with things. Yet if ownership were a right, it would be like any right, problematicin law, in the execution of power and in the nature of the things owned. As a relation it is tenuous and impermanent. I sit on the Cedars Spur under white mahoganies, blackbutts and Maiden’s wattles. Through the tree trunks and shrubs I can see a little bit of the road 50m below me. A vehicle could pass and I could just watch it go by without being seen. Without dogs, no one would find me here. I imagine if they came for us in the night we could slip into the forest. They would run into it, collide with it, and we’d be safely up some gully. I notice a noise like a distant train or a plane. Up here sounds reverberate against the ridge and sound unfamiliar and directionless. Gradually I realize that a helicopter is throbbing over the next ridge, busy keeping the cold eye of the state on its subjects, entertaining those inside it with that sublime view of all beneath. Suddenly, loud and dark, it rises over the Turkey Track—the dirt road that follows the main spur from the ridge down to the river—and it patrols along the spurs 200m to the south. It turns and flies northeast surveying the main ridge and the gully that runs down to The Big Dam. I lose sight of it until, unexpectedly, it starts roaring above me and behind me, chopping back along the primary ridge. I see it for a moment back up through the thinner foliage of the grey gums and forest oaks up along the spur. The thin canopy blows out even thinner under the rotor. It is as loud as an angel and so close I can count the rivets and I wonder if there is any chance that they might not be seeing me. Hardly, but it must just be casual entertainment for them up there, just work, just looking. Like an animal I sit still and press myself up against the southeastern side of a white mahogany, while leaves and broken branches spit and whip in the downdraft. Looking cool under this thing must look very uncool from up there. It passes slowly over the forest then tilts and rides away, hovers for a moment above the Turkey Track, then it throbs out of sight westward, searching elsewhere, the grid references of its big cold picture ticking over on its G.P.S. All it has left behind is a shower of leaves and the smell of fuel, like steel pheromones. Exhilarated by disdain I walk back down the spur, under the Cedars, quickly cross the track near the Traffic Lights, make my way down the Snig Track Edge, past Cudegerie Corner, The Points, The Big Dead Tree, The Conversion Site, and The Rusty Plum, keeping to the wallaby all the way.

102

7 Ecology The ecology of a house in the bush

It is not worth the while to go round the world to count the cats in Zanzibar. —Henry David Thoreau, Walden Ecology, oeco – 1873. [  G. ökologie (Haekel), f. Gr. ’ôιĸος house (used for ‘habitat’): see – LOGY.] The science of the economies of animals and plants; that branch of biology that deals with the relations of living organisms to their surroundings, their habits and modes of life, etc. Hence Ecological a. Ecologist. —Shorter Oxford Dictionary

In etymology and my experience ecology begins at home. The leaf-tailed gecko steps out at night from behind a painting or a cupboard. It is like the moon stepping out from behind the horizon. At some stage you just look up and notice it looking back at you. You wonder when it got there, and by what practised and inscrutable movement. Sometimes it stalks on the verandah, devouring funnel webs, brown trapdoors or grey rattlers in its cool light. Sometimes you notice it during the day. Day or night, mostly you see it waiting somewhere while the world goes through its changes. Waiting is one of its talents. So is likeness. Indeed waiting is a kind of likeness. A lot of the world does not move much, and the gecko imitates all that motionlessness. Still, like the moon, it gets around. Our house is a place for things to step out into and be noticed. The abstraction of architecture makes a clearing in the visual noise of the forest. It removes the dapples and the darknesses of leaves and bark and shadows that rustle around the gecko. The gecko can imitate the changing moods of its forest surroundings and disappear into them. However, having fixed itself like an ornament to the wall, the gecko can’t help but look artful to us. It’s on exhibition like the paintings it hides behind by day. Patrick Cook once called it

103

art gecko. We call Gecko by name and talk to it, but it replies with its own studied disregard, bordering on disdain. Even with its bulging eyes it can manage a kind of scowl. Motionless and in muted umbers, it is busy fooling potential passing spiders, and doesn’t like to be disturbed during the longueurs. It is said by us that the gecko is so seldom seen moving because it moves with an alacrity that dodges perception, displacing itself almost instantaneously. When actually caught moving it slows to a prissy gait, part mince, part slink. The fastest observed speed is a grudging scurry at just the right pace to suggest neither discomposure nor willingness. Like all the creatures we see in and around the house, Gecko demands to be addressed or described only in a way that honours it in, and leaves it to, its ordinary particularity. That is what is extraordinary about it—and the other creatures too. To paraphrase Judith Wright, the gecko is perfect in the gecko, as perfect as the five fingers of the little gloves that it sheds along with its gossamer jump-suit. It leaves these things discarded behind jars and under bookcases. It leaves little turds too, dark and crunchy with the exoskeletons of insects and capped by a neat, white calcareous tip. It has been a custom of philosophers to hold that nothing is distinguished in its particularity without drawing on the resources of the universal. That may be why, like the Moon, the proper name of a leaf-tail gecko is the same regardless of which common-noun leaf-tail gecko is being addressed. A proper name denotes an individual. Leaf-tail Gecko is every leaf-tail gecko’s name—or at least one of its names. They have nicknames too, mostly for private occasions. It’s the same with all the animals around here. A description of something in particular calls forth the universal because, as the poet Richard Wilbur said, a thing is most itself when likened—like the gecko, which is most like itself when likening itself to something else, like forest litter. Or like the gecko’s tail, which is most like itself when likened either to a leaf or to the gecko’s own head. It’s a decoy for the head and good enough to fool a predator who has not noticed how much it looks like the self-similar graph of a Mandelbrot set. Shed when attacked, this artifice writhes in overacted agony as the gecko, with a cool head and low dudgeon, slouches offstage. Then it grows a new tail like a new leaf. Diver’s facemasks or glass bottom boats nullify the visual noise at the rough surface of the water. We live in a device like this. Our house is a device for looking into the forest. When frogs hunt on the windows we have an intimate view of their underparts. Birds and wallabies come close up to the windows. But it is more than this. In removing the distractions of the forest the house makes its own habitat. It is not just a window on the forest, it is a little ecosystem laid within the forest. It is kind of lure. Any observation is more or less invasive, more or less governed by its own uncertainty principle. Changing the circumstances in which the thing is observed changes the nature of the thing observed. Are we seeing the leaf-tail gecko being a proper leaf-tail gecko or are we seeing a creature beguiled by this artificial habitat into being an artifact? Perhaps in this respect our house is as innocent or as guilty as the big dead tree that we watch from our verandah. 104

Without that tree things would be different, but we wouldn’t know half of what was going on. Birds land on this tree, some of whom we seldom see elsewhere. Likewise, lizards land in our house, lizards we seldom see elsewhere. Like the gecko they stay and rent rooms. It’s habitat. Roof skinks, also known as tree skinks, lounge in the ceiling and come out on hot days. Murray’s skinks hang around the sink and windowsills day and night like kids at a mall. Weasel skinks, land mullet, blue-tongue and common or garden skink all visit here or live here. We know them all by their first names. Weasel, Roofie and Murray we seldom see elsewhere. This is lizardland. It is like an island of reptiles, like New Caledonia. Any time wildlife officers visited our house they could charge us for keeping native animals. To sell the house would be illegal trade in native species. I don’t know what a leaf-tailed gecko fetches these days. We could be sitting on a fortune. Can a house be an ecosystem? The term sounds technical and the system part makes it sound like something that’s unified by its own organizational integrity. The trouble is that most of the ecosystem-type things that nature has on offer, things like wetlands, forests or rivers, are pretty vague, as vague or vaguer than a house. So to me, our house seems like a good or even an instructive candidate for a smallish ecosystem. It depends how vague you want to be but I would like to think of the Dead Tree as part of our household ecosystem too. It’s as good as a sculpture in the garden. The Tree is just far enough away to miss the house when it falls. It is the last left of the forest ringbarked a hundred years ago when they cleared and fenced this ridge country. A slender tallowwood, not quite the giant that many werethe many that collapsed under their own slowly rotting weight in the closing decades of the 20th century. It still stands above the regrowth. For how much longer? An osprey has landed in it to eat a silver bream brought up from the estuary in its talons. On summer evenings, dollar birds launch themselves from it to pluck insects out of the glowing sky. Then sit in it and contemplate: ek, ek, ek. A goanna climbs it, warming itself up in the last sun for a final rush on a baby dollar bird that just manages to fly off just in time. The parent harasses the goanna until it slinks into a hollow for the night. After a wet week, sacred ibisessick of waterperch there over several nights. On April mornings butcherbirds rehearse canons announcing the coming of a new and brighter kind of blue in the sky. Sugar gliders emerge from its hollows and launch themselves down into the darkening blue gum forest. A koala sleeps in the forest oak that brushes the dead tree’s trunk. The bowerbird club meets up therea couple of dazzling black and gold males and a dappled committee of perch shufflers. Or its fig birds instead. Or blue-eyed satin bower birds do the bower bird plunge down into the forest below. Spangled drongoes shuffle and cackle and flick their tails around in it. On hot spring mornings a sacred kingfisher utters an interminable ki ki ki… ki ki ki ki ki… ki ki ki k… Three glossy black cockatoos, talking quietly to themselves, waft over into it from the forest oaks where they have been crunching cones all day. They fan their red tails as they land. Three big yellow tailed black cockatoos lope over the treetops 105

and land on it, the juvenile squawking non-stop. A tiny scarlet honeyeater sings about having the tip at the top to itself, so does a tiny mistletoe bird. A crested hawk pecks at a frog, a grey goshawk pauses and watches, one year a brown falcon uses it as base, one morning three honking sea eagles overwhelm it, shaking its wood as they land. A green tree snake climbs it, finding a purchase up vertical timber with nothing but a bare abdomen on rippling grain. Green Tree Snake also hunts around the frames of our doors and windows making its curves rectangular. Is it artificial to square a serpent? It snaffles a Tyler’s tree frog asleep in a hat on a rack on the verandah, and as it gapes around its prey it flashes the aniline blue scales of its throat. One day after lunch I was on the phone and I could hear someone in the kitchen washing dishesthat lovely light ringing and clattering of cutlery and crockery. It means someone else is doing the washing-up. Just as I hung up I heard a loud crash. Oops, I thought, and called out. Is everything OK? No answer, just more clattering, but not so comforting anymore. Still calling out, I walked across the breezeway and into the kitchen. No one had done any dishes —certainly not the goanna who was stretched out on the bench feeling and tasting its way through the clutter with its forked tongue. A metre and a half behind the tongue, its tail was making mild havoc among plates, glasses and assorted items of food. When they feel threatened, goannas scurry up trees for protection. The particular species here in this forested country is the tree goanna or lace monitor. It is a typical site to see them holding onto a tree trunk, dark grey and filigreed with bands of pale ochre like a fine dot painting. Don’t run up the wall I thought as we made eye contact. Goannas make a precise and reliably consistent assessment of adult humansthey retreat. Thank God. Not always so with children. A knowing goanna will threaten a child, at least to get them to drop food. And babies? Well I am glad no one had left a baby alone in the kitchen. Come to think of it, a big goanna with food in its jaws or its sites will stand its ground and huff and puff at an angry adult human. Its teeth and claws are sharp. They make you think twice. I have watched them steal a fat nestling pigeon, a friendly tree skink, and a trapped black rat (trap and all), powerless to do anything about it. I have friends who have grabbed big ones by the tail to get them out of a chook house. But a metre and a half of muscular carnivore is a bit close when held at arms length. Thankfully, this day, this goanna bailed outoff the bench, onto the floor and out the back door like a naughty dog. Thankfully there was not too much wild scurry. A quick check revealed a smashed bowl on the floor, a derangement of our lunchtime dishes, and a missing wedge of cheese, wrapping and all. We got off lightly. Lucky it was an average goanna and not one we call Komodo. That’s the opportunistic visitor category. When it comes to the preferred habitat category, the goanna habitat is roof. Goannas like to spend the night and the winter in hollows in trees. If there is an entrance under eaves into the ceiling cavity, that will serve the same purpose nicely. If there is no entrance, but one can be made by pulling back a bit of poorly fixed timber, that’s fine. Goannas can do that. We had various goannas in our roof for years. On summer 106

mornings as the corrugated steel started to stretch and creak with the heat, the resident goanna would stick its head out under the top ridge, pretty as a prow maiden surveying the ocean of forest, ready to start the daily patrol. The goanna would stay over-winter too, occasionally getting restless in its torpor and rolling over and shuffling loudly above our heads. When the weather warmed up again in August the daylight patrols could start again. When all the roof’s weak points were closed, the goanna, evicted and disgruntled, mooched around and probed under the eaves to no avail. That is ecology too: habitat competition. Relegated once more to the status of opportunistic visitors, Goanna and Komodo walk around the house and through the breezeway eyeing us with scorn but scooting up a tree if we get a bit menacing. With the goanna out of the roof, it is even safer for the roof skinks (Egernia mcpheeii). Here is a dark, fat 30cm of skink that likes hot weather by day and a ceiling space by night. It pokes around the edges of the house, hiding under furniture and clutter, and scuttles when approached. It ventures out into the vegetation to snack on the fallen berries of rose myrtle and blue dianella, and into our house to glean fallen crumbs. At one stage we could not work out what was hollowing out bananas on a bunch in the corner of the kitchen. Just when we were jumping to the dismal conclusion Ratty (unwanted interloper, another story), Roofie climbed into the basket and stole the show. Roof Skink fancies a bit of fruit. It is tempting to put a bit on the ground to see Roofie eat it. As long as you keep still Roofie will approach. You can even feed some Roofies by hand. In return for feeding Roofie a bit of banana, we get a kind of pleasure. There is a food-for-pleasure symbiotic exchange that meets the needs of both species, and the requirements of ecological terminologyunless you think this feeding thing is not to Roofie’s benefit in the long run, or unless you think our mere pleasure is not properly ecological in a good businesslike food or mating or competition kind of way. Roofie will climb onto your hand and eat, and try biting your finger on the way. It is a friendly questioning kind of try. And it will do the same to your toe if that is the first bit of you it comes to. With Hunter it is worse. The following is a confession extracted from the other human in the house: I first saw Hunter in the screened space between the beam on top of the north wall and the rafters. It was small and looked like a garden skink but it was a strange place for a garden skink to be. They like to scuttle around in the sunny spots on the veranda. A closer look showed it to be shinier than a garden skink, and as time passed it grew bigger than any garden skink I’ve seen. When we found our lizard lapping splashed water near the kitchen tap we decided it was a water skink. After this we left a little bowl of water for it near the tap. At first our little friend was called Lizzie. Its favourite place was still on the screened area where I first saw it. It liked this place because here,

107

the screen designed to keep insects out was keeping them in for lizard. Lizzie had a new nameHunter. Hunter wasn’t always a good hunter. It would spot its prey, wag its tail like a cat, and pounce. But too late. When the weather was hot and dryusually in Octoberthe inappropriately named March Flies would appear in large numbers. I took to swatting them and putting them somewhere near Hunter as an easy target. Hunter liked this innovation. Eventually it would run up before I put a fly down and snatch it from my fingers. Fingers without flies also became attractive. I worried that Hunter was losing its hunting skills, and when insects were scarce and Hunter was in the wrong place, I would lure it with my fingers onto the palanquina vegetable scrubber that it rather liked to climb onand take it to the insects to do some real hunting. At some point we realized that Hunter was bigger or smaller or shier than the last time we had seen it, and we realized that Hunter was not just one lizard. Word had got around. I don’t really believe in feeding wild animals but I had become corrupted. And so had Hunter. The pleasure of having a lizard eat out of my hand and show me no fear had seduced me. When the weather was cool and there were no insects around I would feed Hunter some rice or wet bread. Hunterone, two and threewere all looking fat and sleek, and they didn’t wag their tails much any more. I had gone too far. It is winter now and Hunter has gone into hiding. When it warms up and Hunter comes back I’ll be strong and let it hunt for itself. We did eventually find out Hunter’s real name. My cousin, who knows about these things, said Hunter was a Eulamprus murrayi or Murray’s skink. Should we change Hunter’s name to Murray? I don’t think so. But if I don’t change my ways maybe I should. Murray sounds more like a lounge lizard. Needless to say, the Other Human wasn’t strong. Years later, Hunter still hangs around the sink and windows. Tiddlesyoung Hunterscome, catch midges, wave their tails, and grow or go. There is Kitchen Hunter and Bedroom Hunter. One Hunter, Hunter the first, lost a tail and became Oblong. Oblong and Hunter II had what looked like a contest. Courtship, mating and aggression can all be a bit confusing with skinks. Hunter gnawed at Oblong’s stump, drew blood and Oblong disappeared for months. When Oblong came back, tail largely regrown, Hunter and Oblong had a rematch. Oblong looked very strong, but after a long day of jousting, it was Oblong who came and visited us down where we were sitting drinking tea at the end of the bench, made what we later understood was a farewell, and then dropped down off the bench, walked across the floor, out the door, across the verandah and off into the gathering dusk. We were never sure whether it had been vanquished or whether it had proved its 108

point and had left for new adventures. Another reason for all Hunters being called Hunter or for all Geckos being called Geckles is that it softens blows to the heart. The Hunter you meet this evening at the tap can be the same Hunter that took its swag and walked out into that dusk so long ago. And another reason is because, as in Louis’s case, Louis is a character played by many actors. And Louis is a character. The generic Louis. Always busy and a busy-body and bossy and a dog in the manger and a sticky beaka kind of comic rogue. Louis is a would-be boss of the forest but too small to push anyone around other than other Louiss, and any of the small birds at the birdbaththe red browed finches, grey or rufous fantail, thornbills brown or striated, fairy wrens or scrub wrens. The birdbath is another one of those devices for observing the creatures of the forest. Louis will try and boss bigger birds, and is cheeky enough to have some success if it catches them in an unwary, flighty or can’t-be-bothered-resisting kind of mood. Yellow Robin is about Louis’s size or a bit smaller. Yellow Robin is solid though, with a formidable little insectivore’s bill, and a composed nature. Louis can move a young yellow robin but adult Yellow Robin stays put. Louis’s antics are an irritation for Yellow Robin, occasionally to be rebuked. The little birds can drink and bathe happily if Yellow Robin is guarding the pool and in a good mood. Louis has finished off the last of the little blue berries on the dianella lily outside the window. They had been dangling off the ends of their stalks, glowing the way blue snooker balls glow. Louis would sneak in and take them. Roofy had been trying to reach them but could not stretch out far enough from the sculpture next to them, and the dianella culm could not take Roofy’s (also known as Fatso’s) weight. The palm lily berries are finished now too, and Louis is in the geebung above the bathroom getting its tongue into the nectar of the small yellow flowers. The rose myrtles are dry this year and Louis seems to be leaving thosetheir time will comebut the elderberry panax fruits are turning mauve and Louis is already picking them, one by one. We watch through the window while we eat breakfast. Most of the time, Louis can find some little black trema fruits to pick, and when snake vine fruits turn from green to yellow to red, Louis is ready for them, one by one. A bit of this and a bit of thata little bit of a lot of things, as long as it is a fruit with a bit of soft flesh somewhere, or a flower with some nectar. Louis has even landed on my knee, too intent upon examining a bunch of bananas next to me to see me. And especially when nestlings are being fed, Louis picks insects from the spiders’ webs in the corners of the windows or huntsmen spiders from the verandah posts. At dusk Louis might just fly into a shrub near the eaves or a hanger under the eaves, tuck its head under a wing, fluff its feathers and sleep the night oblivious to our comings and goings. Just for the record, Louis’s dad refers to John Lewin, the early Australian colonial painter. Lewin was one of the first Europeans to paint the look of the bush. Louis is one of the looks of the bush around here, and the look of the bush is Louis’s. Louis tends it, watches it, eats it, sows the seeds in it, and there 109

is always a Louis calling from somewhere, loud and fast, announcing how fine it all is. Our garden is Louis’s garden. Who says of the birds that neither do they reap or sow? Louis’s Garden consists of all the infill species, the usually unnoticed things, the little lilies and climbers, the small trees and inconspicuous shrubs. Louis’s Garden is a tribute to all the plants that are, as the gardening books say, of no horticultural value. I am worried that this house-as-ecosystem conceit sounds cute, confiding and contrived. Perhaps writing about this ecology this way has everything not going for it. Firstly, it’s too anthropomorphic. Or is anthropomorphism just a dirty word? To understand an animal you have to think like an animal, but to think like an animal you can’t help but think like a human thinking like an animal. I often think people bending over backwards to sound scientific and only allowing themselves to indulge in prescribed terms like mating, territory and competition sound awfully anthropomorphic. It is just that they are anthropomorphic in a rather dismal way. Science is not inhuman so if I want to understand animal behaviour I will anthropomorphize like an amused scientific human. The bans on anthropomorphism are a bit like the old behaviourist bans on using intentional idioms in psychology. Louis acts like an artful character out of comedia del arte or like Bugs Bunny, and that is a good start to understanding. Our anthropomorphized descriptions might not get all the causes and motives and functions right when it comes to describing Louis’s actions, but if you don’t treat Louis as one of us animals, if you don’t factor in intentions, you won’t get far. More science will polish the description up, and gives a pretty good basis for predicting just how Louis will act. One of Louis’s charms by the way is to be so predictable just when he thinks he is being so clever and unpredictable. Secondly, apart from confusing the concept of an ecosystem, isn’t this household ecology a bit unethical? It’s not only feeding lizards that is shameful. Building a house in the bush is irresponsible. People editorialize against this kind of thing. They do it after bushfires; they do it when criticizing urban encroachment. We worry about it too. Some visitors are not quite at home. There is the echidna who sniffs around the footings and through the breezeway at night, its quills tinkling against the bricks and paving. I like to get up and see it. When you meet an echidna it rolls up and sinks into the ground. Literally. It has the uncanny ability to borrow straight down underneath itself and present only a defensive array of spines sticking out from the ground to any would be predator. When you go outside at night to see what is sniffing and snuffling around the breezeway, it is always a delight to meet Echidna nosing about and licking the termites (unwanted interlopers, another story) into line. What is not a delight is that the pavers don’t yield to Echidna’s earthy, downward inclinations. Echidna only has the role up option and the huddle against the equally unyielding wall option. For Echidna, pavers are wrong. For us, snakes are wrong. This is lizardland. Green Tree Snake and even 2m of lurking carpet python are welcome, outside at least. But we draw the line at 110

venomous. Occasionally on warm summer nights a small-eyed snake will slither under your feet on the verandah. Our snake book, Graeme Gow (1989), says prevalent in rocky areas. That seems to explain why Small-eye likes the paved verandah and why it likes to spend daytime and wintertime coiled up in a nook in the brickwork steps. If you are inside with the doors open on a summer night, Small-eye is inclined to sneak in through an opened door to join you. Small, skittish and black, small-eyes don’t herd well, and they make me skittish too. They don’t go for cover, they go for panic and display of aggression, but if you have a good snake herder (e.g. the Other Human) and if you notice the snake before it is too far in, it can be ushered back out. Small-eye has a small mouth that would hardly get around a finger but Grahame Gow says: has been associated with an adult fatality. The Funnel Web spiders that like to walk in on warm rainy nights have been associated with an adult fatality or two too. They are famous for it. They are a worry. Their look alikes, the Brown Trapdoors, have us worried too. They make us wary of our spider identification skills. Gecko likes them though. It must be the balance of nature. One night I was woken from sleep by a bite on the neck. It drew blood. My first thought: where to wrap the pressure bandage for a neck bite. It’s a rhetorical question. There is no answer. It was only when I found an angry longicorn beetle buzzing on my pillow that I realized I did not need an answer. The ecosystem of the house starts and finishes in different places for different creatures. For Small-eye the paved area out the front and through the breezeway is its habitat. For the Swamp Wallaby it isn’t. Wallaby will browse its salad of almost every local herb right up to the window as long as there are no pavers in front off the window. They must like to leave the V-shaped indent of their passage in the feel of the forest earth. For most of the birds their habitat ends where the breezeway starts. Only a few will fly through it or land in it: Louis, Yellow Robin. But the non-bird habitat really starts seriously at the doors and windows. You understand this when birds blunder in through a window, or worse, into a window. The pane that is. The former look so forlorn. Yellow Robin, confident and confiding outside, is reduced to a panicky captive cornered on a sill or up under the ceiling. Likewise suave Grey Thrush, the musician. Outside its clear powerful call dispels all cares. Inside it is reduced to complete anxiety and stunned pathos. Outside, Grey Fantail twitters and gossips and parades and fans and wags its tail, announcing its every arrival and filling the air with its fly catching flits and turns. Inside it is glum and quiet and tiny. You can open all the windows and doors and these masters of space still cower up in some corner stupefied by the uncanny topology. Eventually you have to take them in your hands, firm enough to catch and hold them, gentle enough to save their delicate bodies. Nothing is as touching and tiny as a warm bird under its feathers cradled in your hands. Their panicky shit is warm on your palm. When you open your hands outside they sometimes pause for a moment, taking in their deliverance. Then you can see the beauty and power rush back into them from the bush all around, and they’re gone. 111

Maybe the only thing more touching than a bird in the hand is a bird on the hand. Brown Thornbill used to come and take hair to build its nest. It began by taking hair that had been untangled from a brush and dropped on a potplant. The Other Human taught it to take hair held in the hand. Standing on its little stick-legs it looked you in the eye and tugged the hair from your fingers. When I tried to photograph it standing on a hand and taking hair it landed on my head and tried to tug the hair from there. Tiny and beautiful it tried to pull hair from a friend’s arm, a big man’s arm. We knew when it was coming. For such a little bird it has a big, rich warble. It can still come, in name at least, to the birdbath or to gather hair for a nest. The window pane hitters hit with a painful thud. At best it is a glancing blow and a rest on a branch is enough to recover. At worst it is a fatal head on at high velocity, as when a dove is commuting through the columns of the forest and mistakes the pane for just another rectangle of open air. One year we had to use clay to paint pictures of predators on the glass. Otherwise we don’t wash the windows. Or there are the frogs that hunt happily on the windowpane—outside. If they are unfortunate enough to come inside their propensity for seeking out nooks and crannies is fatal. They are magnets for dust and fluff and hairs. Occasionally we see pathetic little balls of tangled fluff limping in dusty corners. I am not a great rescuer of wildlife but a bleating tree frog or a dwarf green tree frog bound in hair and dusted into an advanced state of desiccation is my specialty. I put it in a bowl of water and using tweezers and a magnifying glass I disentangle it limb by limb, digit by digit. From the trauma of entanglement and the microsurgery of disentanglement they recover under a stone on a stump with plenty of hiding holes. It seems to work. Or there are the fireflies that blunder in on September evenings and waste there blinking until they flicker out. Normally, after their bright silent jangling, they would settle back down under the leaf litter from which they rise again the next evening. We have to close the doors and windows and watch from the verandah. Insects are a whole study in them. Some are completely at home. Black ichneumon wasps with curly orange antennae leave paralyzed spiders in neat little tunnels of clay masonry. Curly lays its eggs in the tunnel with the spiders and the larvae hatch and consume live spiders preserved by the paralysis. Mudwasps build mud nests on walls and ceilings, paper wasps build paper nests on beams, masonry bees burrow into walls, carpenter bees colonize holes in timber posts, gormless sugar ants intoxicate themselves in sweet traps of jam, sugar and wine, golden silk taffeta ants clinch one another on the beams and rafters, little black ants make their inscrutable migrations in and out. Others —March flies, assassin flies, beetles, bugs, cockroaches, moths, crickets— blunder up against screens and glass and might not seem at home. But looks deceive. They are an ecosystem service, live prey for Hunter. The odd jumping ant or bulldog ant ambles in then tries to prey on us. On warm summer evenings when storms start to break, everywhere becomes a muggy atmosphere of flying termites. Louis picks them out of the air. Yellow Robin picks them off 112

the posts and pavers. They don’t so much come into the house. The house finds itself in the termisphere. They circle around lights, plummet into food, drop their wings, crawl into crevices, under clothing, into bedding. Enough have found their way into my mouth for me to know they taste woody and oily. What good is a house in the bush? What good is this imposition? It depends what you do with it. As well as using it to see into the bush, you can use it to listen. On spring mornings everything begins with a click in the dark. And then another, and then: Click click. Click click. Click click. In the dark as dawn begins and only in spring. It keeps going. It is the first bird. Others start the same way, measuring the end of the night. One down in the blue gum forest going: Click click. Click click. Another down in the tallowwoods, another back along the ridge. Click click. Click click. Not together in one rhythm, but together in many rhythms. What can they be? How can I say they are the yellow robins? How can these confiding little birds that gently chick chick chick to one another in the evening forest and pipe a clear repeated note amongst the blue and brown columns be so loud. How can they crack that predawn air like that. You would think they were whipbirds, or at least like whipbirds waking and warming up. You have to go down and see them doing it before you can know. Yellow robins, the first birds. Still dark and in the distance, kookaburras, in big trees down on the edge of the forest and the open country, doing kookookookookookookookook. The second birds. Down there it would be an explosion. Up here they are just that distant familiar sound. Everyone knows this sound. Today a bar shouldered dove starts next. Cookawook cookawook. Pause. Cookawook cookawook. Or cawooca cawooca, depending on how you hear the stress. My mind dreams off and when it comes back I hear more birds now. They have all been starting up: a Lewin’s honeyeater staccato, a high scarlet honeyeater, a grey fantail excited by morning, a whipbird too now with its long low note drawn to a cracking loud close, then another whipbird in the vines whistling a little automatic reply, a fantail cuckoo doing its downward trill, the click click still going click click, golden whistlers going wild back and forth to one another, a grey thrush doing almost the same call but in a richer, fluty voice, a distant butcher bird trying out its perfect notes, a bright little wren fanfare, and a multitude of warbles, trills, chirps, and chatter from all those small brown birdswarblers, gerygones, thornbills, scrubwrens. Everyone is going loud and bright nowgod its loudas the dawn light has started to pick out colour from the black and white of the click, click. Click click. Click click. Holding it all together, so many different voices singing so many ways in one piece of dawnsong. So loud. Each season with its composition. On an autumn day you can walk outside and have topknot pigeons take to the air. The rush of a thousand birds makes the sound of air. A kind of big feathery hush. They shuffle themselves around in the crown of a tallowwood showering regurgitated laurel seeds down through the foliage. When you get too close they flock off along the timbered ridge, then wheel around in the light over the sunless morning gully. 113

This morning was a true summer morning, or at least, of a certain kind of summer day. We have already had those dark overcast days of high summer with heavy cloud and warm drizzle holding off the sun and just the murmur of cicadasthe summer of hot nights and steamy days. First thing this morning, lying awake, I could hear the cicadas, not whingeing, singing. Non-stop, full voice, washing over the morning. The zinging air and distance muffled a wonga pigeon way away in the northern forest pumping its wot wot wot wot wot wot … non-stop, and another somewhere answering with the same eternal question, sounding the depth and distance of the timbered ridges. I got up and stood outside in the forest, pissing and facing east, the soft offshore air pressing against my back, still cool and new out of the receded western night. The forest was so dark because the sky was so light and its blue so deep and clear. Everything was advertising a hot day, one of those days when cicada noise can hurt the ears and end up driving people crazy, just like music. Besides listening and looking, a house in the bush is the best base for working on the bush. You walk out your door and you can look after things without having to form a Landcare group, draft a management plan, apply for funding, drive to working bees, and overcome or tolerate the thousand disincentives to doing good things. And outdoors still sort of feels like indoors. It is possible that if the whole valley were subdivided into bush blocks, the bush would be kept in much better condition. Possible but unlikely. People would mostly just clear house sitesi.e. get rid of the bushand not look after it anyway. As happens with many a tool though, a house’s most adroit function often goes unappreciated until it dawns on you that you have been using it that way for quite some time. The house is like the gecko. It waits. That is its real talent. As the gecko demonstrates, there are few better ways to observe nature than to let it come to you. Just take a seat on a log in the bush, sit still and keep quiet. A house is like a log you sit on in the bush. For a very long time. The house does the waiting for you while you get on with other business until something comes by. To whatever has the power of waiting, the secular approximation to the power of everlasting presence, eventually something comes. It might not be the Messiah. It might not be someone heralded by the gossip of the grey fantail chatting at the birdbath in the evening. But it will be someone. Just Grey Fantail is someone enough. Even just Louis is. At five to eight one evening a someone knocked on the back door. No one ever comes to the back door, and not at night, and we had not heard anyone drive up. When the Other Human opened the door, a koala pushed past and walked straight in, uninvited. It paused and looked around and blinked. A baby on the back was looking over its mother’s head, like a jockey. I blocked the entry to the kitchen and ushered our visitors through the other way. The koala walked through to where the TV was on and sat on a rug on the floor. Kerry O’Brien was doing an interview. We flitted around opening doors and windows while we made small talk to our guests. We said things in sing-sing voices, while the koala, blinking, watched Kerry, and the jockey peered at the screen 114

between the mother’s ears. The last thing we wanted was for them to feel uneasyand start climbing. For one uncomfortable moment our adult guest did decide to climb onto a chair, but for an arboreal marsupial it did not climb very well, or it was half-hearted. A koala’s skill base is limited to meeting a narrow range of needseating leaves, climbing and sitting in gum trees, ornamenting the view from our verandah, sleeping, grunting (males), screaming (females), sex sometimes I suppose (I have seen a grunting male whip a long penis about as a female screamed off in the distance) and just walking througha list that does not seem to include climbing onto chairs. The mother blinked, slipped, and settled its pointy bum back on the floor. I suspect that if koalas had selfesteem it might be low, but they don’t seem to need it. When Kerry wrapped up the 7:30 Report, Koala and child saw an open door, toddled out to the breezeway, and headed off. ‘Bye,’ we said, and watched the mother amble up the front path into the dark, the rider high on its mount, looking into the night.

115

116

8 The Dream; Or Unconscious Nature. How society fashions its nature and its image of nature, unaware of itself; and how nature comes back to haunt it.

The phantasmagoria of that wild dreamland termed the bush, interprets itself. —Marcus Clarke, 1876, Preface to Adam Lindsay Gordon’s Sea Spray

Nature is like the dreamwork of society, sometimes coming to us as transcendent vision, sometimes delusion, sometimes delightful fulfillment, sometimes nightmare come back to haunt us, an unreal part of the real world. What we call nature around here in the Bellinger Valley and in most of Australia, these leftovers and selections of a society strangely unconscious of the secret purposes and ministry of its works, cannot be entirely repressed; nor can we so successfully delude ourselves that it does not sometimes declare itself, strangely interrupting our experience, invading the logic of the everyday, supplanting common expectation, substituting images, juxtaposing and transferring objects of desire and loathing. As a dream is supposed to be to the dreamer, so nature is baffling evidence of a kind of social unconscious, the existence of which is seldom acknowledged, a social unconscious that is like a force of nature. Sure, the living nature we still have is the outcome of the natural selection and evolution of species, but the nature now scattered here and there as bush is also the result of social selection and the evolution of culture. Nature is a cultureeven in wilderness, where it is used to represent what is utterly natural. And what we take to be utterly natural is 2nd nature nownot only in the common sense of something we take for granted as it is (in this case we take it for granted that it is natural, untouched nature) but in the philosophers’ sense of a new nature which is the product of human works. Some of it is replicated and selected in the deliberate genres of nature reserves and national parks, in the management of the rainforest or wetland or grassy woodland, in the threatened species recovery program, or in the construction of the lookout or

117

the walking track or the tourist centreeven if we are not quite conscious of these things as genres. Or it is in the genres of agriculture, silviculture, gardening, landscape architecture or restored bushif we would call these things nature. A lot of it though is selected unconsciously, because, whether or not we reproduce nature’s genres deliberately, we are hardly aware of the existence of social selection processes that often defy expressed intentions and exceed personal time scales, other than in the sense that we might be wearied by certain processes that strikes us as arbitrary, and seem to be estranged from our control, processes for example like what the ecologist Eugene Odum called the ‘tyranny of small decisions’ or what others, with a worldweariness or hardheadedness that encourages resignation, refer to as ‘just progress’what you can’t stop. Common sense is not accustomed to describing the world in terms of such processesother than vaguelybecause social selection processes, even though they may be the result of many individual human actions, are primarily selections of functions that work for the things being selected and not necessarily for us. In its conscious or unconscious cultural forms, nature has been socially selected for its adaptations to human use, abuse and neglect. Because of this, the nature we have is selected by a natural social process that can be as wild and as alien to us humans as a wilderness or a wildfire. Wilder. Think of nature’s untold case history. Formerly the heaths, the grassy woodlands, the dry and wet eucalypt forests, and the rainforests were placed about the country according to 40,000 years of Aboriginal culture, especially fire culture. This, like all multigenerational culture, wildly exceeded consciousness by exceeding individuals’ intentions and their lives' timescales; and like a lot of fire it exceeded the intentions of people too. The great time taken to fashion a cultural biota ensured a social unconscious, but then the invading European culture was utterly unconscious of the culture of others and thought the land it ran wild over and the culture it trampled over was all just some pure state of naturealbeit a nature of the bastard or fallen kind. Now, 200 years later, there are all those bits in national parksabandoned they were, locked up they say. These bits were left over after the agricultural land-grab. They were adapted to modern society simply by the negative virtues of their steep topography, poor soil, remote location and lack of commodity. It is strange to think of lack of commodity as a function, but it has been functional for the survival of these bits. Afterwards, the same features turned out to work in quite a different way. This time they enabled survival in a society that wanted to set up a museum of pristine nature or a fantasia of virgin nature, and behold out there beyond the bitumen there were genres of this very nature already waiting to be folded into the care of society. Yet again in history, cultural forms may have been variable, but their social functions were even more so. These places found that they could survive in a society where it had been decided that what was called its natural environment was the most important tool it had at its disposal for engineering water quality, maintaining agricultural productivity, earning the tourist dollar, healing the sick at heart and saving the planet from 118

ecological catastrophe. It was to be slotted in as a supplier of ecosystem services, just one other part of society’s fully functionalized landscape. Some of this preserved nature is unreal vision. Such is the picturesque backdrop of the Bellinger escarpment, the blue hardwood forests, the succession of fading ridges that line up between the plateau, the Nambucca Valley, the Pacific and the sky. It works by its feature of sheer appearancea camouflage that fools any animal so fascinated by the sensuousness of looking, not to mention the modern sensibility of sublime contemplation so carefully cultivated since the 18th century. Initially, this form of aesthetic culture had itself been socially selected in order to preserve the dream image of mighty and glorious nature once the real thing had started to look a little too beholden to an alien and arbitrary power monstrously born from the matrix of human intentions. Close up, a lot of this nature is a delight. Some dreams are sweet. The bright streams full of green bass, fat eels, blue yabbies and sleek platypus, the lapis lazuli of quandongs, the garnet of wisteria seeds, jewels in the rocky pools, water dragons sunning on a snag, the wind combing chords through the harp of casuarina, the remote wild forest blinking with firefliesthese indices and images of the past, places where it is so hard to banish any notion that this is not all absolutely untouched and remote from the havoc of modernity, so successful are the illusory or delusory devices of the social unconscious. Then there is the other kind of river, the lowland river running through agricultural or urban landa kind of recurring nightmare in which we go over and over the traumatic events of clearing, and weed growth, erosion and shoaling, over fishing and feral fish, eutrophication, and salinationthings that resist assimilation into the self image of a society that wants its nature abundant, obedient, beautiful and enduring—all at once. In such repetition, unconscious society erupts as ugly nature. It pricks itself again and again with this cruel irritation, tormenting itself for gratification and indulging images prurient with desire for misery and ugliness. Then there are those bits of bush beside the road, the bush slashed by the bitumen, the road-world oozing into the raw wound. Take that unsettling dream landscape along the Dorrigo mountain road, of black booyongs, purple cherries, pothos and stinging trees. It is not so unsettling though until you stop the car, climb the safety rail and step into it and feel the dreamlike estrangement occasioned by that simple transposition. Into this new world the unconscious has discarded Coke bottles, Mac packs, dirty nappies, car tyres, the whole catalogue of consumer cultureall its rotting flowers used, all disposedlittered with booyong petals among the images of an unused rainforest that is too useful for accommodating the spent designs of the packaging industry not to exceed, in its uses, merely good intentions. All this stuff arranges itself according to some curious super-human sorting processessomething like the kind that arranges sand precisely between the Pacific Ocean and the east of the continent, or dust in corners. Litter, like sand is not deposited at random. It has its appointed places in the unconscious nature 119

of society and the unconscious society of nature, placed by dreamwork deliberation along the littoral of trunk roads and highways. In the kind of critique idly entertained while driving past, that road might be construed as an abrupt violation of the rainforest, an emblem of a hasty, unreconciled society. Yet in this functioning modern landscape there is flawless integration of the one upon the other. The rainforest as National Park is still there and visited by virtue of the road system. Viewed from the car, the forest works perfectly, concealing the debris of consumption and beautifying the drive. The road frames it like a picture. Even these thoughts, occurring to the daydreaming, drive-by flaneur in the rainforest city, arise from the scene of passing beauty, the luxury of it so conducive to them. Beyond the safety rail is only a bad dream if you step into it. Down in the Bellinger valley much advertised for its beauty, again there is the sudden juxtaposition of road slicing now through the tallowwoods and blue gums. It is so banal and familiar this roadway through eucalypts, but only because it has the familiarity of a recurring dream. It is a dream that almost fulfills the desire for a locomotion that undoes time and space, and yet it is one in which our intentions become estranged from us and in unruly eruptions make arbitrary reprisals, whether in rank growth of pasture grasses that have adapted human pastoral intentions to their own roadside interests, or in the raw open flesh of the clay cutting now populated by privets regurgitated from addicted pigeons and mangled into hedges by quick and dirty bank slashers. This roadside nature is the landscape of suspicion, shallow graves, paranoia and roadkill, a place for a serial killer to hail you down, or where you would not want to break down at night. You find yourself walking along it, on a different planet from the passing cars. By day a wallaby carcass lies in dust just beyond the gutter, leaking odour and flesh into the buzzing sunlight. By night the moon spills onto the gum tree branches, a little seeping down into a gully clogged with trunks, and cars come by lighting up the place under their surveillance, hurling girders of light and dark around the nightscape, and passing like asteroids huge and fast into the depths of space. Especially on the North Coast of NSW, the nation would see itself as a coastal culture, even entertaining itself with holiday criticism of its ignorance of a geographic heart, reading from the colour supplements as it lies on the beach. Yet it lives far away from both. Apart perhaps from lowland rivers, nowhere is so cruelly a dystopia as the culturescape of coastal bush, the land of the holiday. Few forms of nature are so poignantly displaced by social selection from the powerful and persistent human yearning that exists for them. A repeated and persistent custom, vernacular towns of skillion fibro have been thrown up in the lee of headlands and foredunes, edged by dead lawns, and sporadic eruption of rattling progress palms and desultory hibiscus. Even if you didn’t have to clear it to get the truck in and the frame up and a bit of sandy garden, you can’t keep the pyrophytic flora of the heath and open woodland running gloriously right up to the door, so you destroy the beauty that you might have wished to steal. You mow your rectangle of dry couch into the galaxy of flannel flowers. The 120

towns are on sheltered rises, slightly above the sandy, often-swampy soils and behind the beaches that run north of each headland to the next head and the next town. In the slapdash antagonism of townscape and bush the former humbles the latter with its easy, careless triumph and lets its detritus leak into it: dead cars, plastic bags, weeds. This repeated form is the outcome and image of a social antagonism. On the one side there is an insouciant make-do holiday society and a calculating make-money society that exploits it and calls itself development. On the other, there is the society that has walked into shadeless wallum and seen its thousand beauties: bristling and curling sedges, lilies, orchids and rushes, peas and banksias, stingy xeromorphs luxuriant with posies, and wallum rocket frogs thick as grasshoppers and fattened on nothing but lean white sand. As an antagonism of societies spawned by all four of monetary calculation, aesthetic thrill, holiday indolence, and fond reminiscence of the fibro weekender, it can abide or sleep within individuals regardless of whether they take the green or the other side when it comes to politics. The form of nature it generates has been selected as at once the most beautiful and ignored of bush. Infinitely subtle sandy heath, woodland and wallum, the floral orchestration of fire history and minuscule altitude changes and drainage patterns, have been hacked back into a rectilinear disorder by the cadastre of weekender yards, sandmining, lousy poor grazing, faddish teatree oil plantations, golf courses, expanding residential and resort real estate and landscaping. Even now the national parks mostly cater for visitors at the remaining grassy headlands, sheltered beaches, weedy littoral rainforests and the sandy beach dunes, bright green with bitou or brown with sprayed bitou, leaving the glary heath to firefighters and service tracks, to the technicians and to the lovers of nature, and to the nor’easter blowing off the surf in the afternoon. They are places whose tattered spirit has been selected by and for the holiday, adapted to its yearning for beauty and pleasure and summer and the sea, and also to its indolence, perfect in their design for all this. Or there is the great ocean, all sea surface full of clouds, painted by a thousand winds and torn not only by dolphins, whales, and gannets, and the tailor running along the coast, but by long lines and drift nets and rusting hulls and Sargassos of plastic and oil, disguising the absences beneath with its bewitching surface. Then there are those bits that we would work on and restore. The culture of ecological restoration is like a dream in which our intentions are repeatedly frustrated. The dreamworks of society transfer desire for restoration to works of planning, access, signage, fencing, fund raising, monitoring and tree planting. The Landcare viewing platform raises us above the bizarre circus of bitou and gloriosa, so we can watch the 4WDs gunning down the beach. With the logic of the fetish, each of these cultural forms thrives and reproduces itself in a society where restoration and weeding epitomizes drudgery, where what we need is more information, a whole of landscape approach, and current best practices, where erecting signs and building fences is quick and unambiguous work, where what you need is planning, promotion and education, where you can do 121

anything if you have funding, and where the tree is the symbol of nature and the tree planting ritual raises awareness, gets the public involved, gives the kiddies ownership. Restoration society is brilliantly adapted to this kind of environment. In our dreams, most of what the dreamwork delivers us is offices, meetings, forms, acronyms, regulations, plans, promotions and people to work on them, ambitious beginnings without the persistence for ends, and for brief moments we encounter a genre of nature persisting as planned, inventoried fragmentsbehind fences, advertised by signs, tattered by the tread of distant bureaucrats, weedy with management plans, funding applications, uncompleted intentions, flagging resolutions, fructifying with a fantasia weeds and planted trees, like the furniture of dreams, an arbitrary array, in various conditions of health and various stages of growth. In some places another genre of nature is evolvingone that has transcended the nostalgic aesthetic of native vegetation and wildlife and the functionalist, environmentalist cult of biodiversity. We can see cultural evolution at work. It is like watching generations of bacteria being selected for antibiotic resistance. A new beauty is born adapted to our capacity for superceding our older aesthetic sensibilities or for just growing used to things or for putting up with them, or to our indolence, our cold hearts, our ignorance, our willingness to praise any green or wildish thing, our capacity not to notice incremental degradation or to assimilate it as a necessary cost of progress, or our squeamishness about keeping on taking up green arms against weeds and ferals in the ruthless war that Les Murray calls ‘merciless rearrangement of the whole earth…passionate with altruism as ever inquisition was’to all or any of the above. An aesthetics of nature evolves in which we make a virtue of overwhelming contingency and our own idlenessin which, for example, camphor laurel and lantana thrive, where deer browse, horses range, trout are stocked, wild pigs snuffle and foxes stalk. It is not simply that they are such resilient species; rather, as such resilient species, they themselves become multiplying symbols of vigorous, majestic and abundant nature. If plants, they are valued for providing habitat, stopping erosion, conditioning soil, looking so lush and green, flowering profusely, and screening off roads. If animals, they delight as wild and free, as warm and cuddly, as instant heritage, as sport. And although these features might not seem like adaptations for the restoration culturea culture that overtly functionalizes native species and secretly, guiltily aestheticizes themthey are nevertheless adapted to restoration culture simply by virtue of the fact that, as so ecologically resilient and invasive, they thrive on restoration culture’s immense capacity for prevarication and neglect, its capacity for merely planning, its capacity for self-diversion, its capacity for delay, and its incapacity to manage any more than fragments in a landscape. In this dream we frame our drives with avenues of camphor and privet, deck our riverbanks with willows, blossoms of catsclaw and curtains of balloon vine, gaze across an untouched wilderness of lantana where no foot may tread, park behind coastal fore dunes in the flowering glades of bitou and gloriosa lily, witness the inauguration of bamboo and queen palm groves along the coasts 122

and rivers, celebrate and preserve the proud tradition of barreling down long beaches in four wheel drives, and fight to preserve the pristine ‘new nature’ where feral pigs, donkeys, camels, cats, horses and wild deer wander ‘here and there,’ as Blake would have it, ‘to keep the human heart from care’. Not the ‘old fashioned’ nature of nostalgia, natives, the national parks services and environmentalism, this traditional postmodern new nature, the consummation of the Quaternary, is a kind of advertising landscape replete with images from the iconography of globalized, infantilized desire, the place to sell a new car before a mob of brumbies, or a holiday in palmy erotica exotica. If you don’t like it, tough. While you’re grieving or whingeing, social evolution is making this, for most, the stuff of fond memory and experience, and biological evolution is getting on with it, working away developing a new range of pests and predators to devour this delicious over-supply of new naturebalancing it all out in the end if you like, or lurching to over correct itand this wild ride is no more or less wild or a dream than the precious, authentic pristine it is relentlessly superseding. Meanwhile, in some places the nostalgia is indulged and fragments are restored as dream images of the past. Some of this is so close to us though that it is still hard to know whether we are dreaming or not. But we well know the experience of waking up from the past andif we have not just forgotten about it in the dazzling new lightseeing our dreamwork defamiliarized as we recall and retell the dreamlike events of the past, busily unconscious of our secondary elaborations. We have seen the best intentions and the best works revealed as well meaning folly: those riverbank restorations of the hardly distant past that pulled out the snags and planted willows and privets; all those curious tree plantings where achieving canopy, farm forestry, remnant connectivity and provision of wildlife habitat were believed to be nature’s own multifunctional road back to a pristine future. Unwaking, we dream on, assuming that this all happened only in the past, before ecological enlightenment, when those wellmeaners who came before us did not understand. But we would do well to expect that we too participate in the eternal recurrence of stupidity, and to see the signs of the same kind of things happening now: in the current best practice ecosystem function rehabilitation; in the cost effective programs; in the sound of rainforest canopies going clunk as they close over the swish-swish of the sprayers underneath; in the acres of wood-chipped plantings; in tree, canopy, koala, and getting-the-kiddies-involved cults; in our dear natives coming back to haunt us like Hitchcock’s Birdskiller currawongs and kookaburras, noisy miners, swarming lorikeets, koala plagues on Kangaroo Island, pittosporums worse than privets; in the shuffling of troublesome vines, nasty thorns and mere herbs off into some lurking oblivion; in the selected hierarchies of environmental weeds; in the antagonistic mystifications of fire culture lurching between the good burn and universal exclusion; in the time-bound cultures of agricultural and engineering technologies like herbicides or earth movers or ‘integrated pest management’; in the deformations of nature and aesthetics by markets, efficiency, managerialism, funding cycles, and publicity. And in all the 123

other unnamed and as yet undiscovered places where we are all proven wrong. And then there is the society subdivided into functional subcultures where, with one hand we desperately restore a pathetic little bit of nature over here according to our time bound understanding, while with the other we damage all that over thereat an almost effortless stroke. So society fashions its nature and its image of nature, mainly in the unconscious selections of a kind of daytime torpor: seldom aware of its intentions, for all its busy planning; seldom aware of its work, either in apprehension of the task at hand, or of the deed in the doing, or in understanding the result; only to be granted indications of its meaning in images as cryptic and forgettable as dreams. Like the TV, nature is just over there in the corner somewhere and just on. The very fact that nature epitomizes self-generation and that its plethora of self-serving organisms and physical recalcitrants is ultimately uncontrolled by human intentions, now seems consistent with its character as unconscious society. For the term social unconscious designates those processes that exceed society’s would-be description of its would-be self-controlled self. On the one hand, the malignant self-generation of brutalized naturethe eruption of weeds and pest animals, the ugly and cruel consequences of air and water pollution, and all the anti-products of so called production and progress constitute the nightmarish eruption of this unconsciousa nightmare visited on us by the abuses of social history. On the other hand, the wild forest and river of the Upper Bellinger, Rosewood or Never Never overwhelms like an awesome, beautiful, haunting dream. It blesses us like a long, deep, dreamy rest. All this might sound like a dream itself, a delirium, yet it is scarcely an exaggeration to say that it is cautious description, prosaic, barely metaphorical. It follows from careful scrutiny and scrupulous description of the historical genesis of the social phenomenon that we call nature. What follows is how I think nature could get to be this way.

124

9 The Natural History of Culture. A theory of cultural evolution outlined as the basis for understanding the current state of our culture of nature.

The objectivity of historic life is that of natural history —Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics

Warning: Nature Is Not Natural. The physical world, the essence or nature of a thing, that which is not culture, that which is self-generating, all that beautiful stuff out there in national parks, etc, etc. The word nature is famous for having too many meanings, for being too ambiguous or too hard to define. No one can list all the meanings. They’ve tried. Anything that has a history, said Nietzsche, cannot be defined. And no doubt, this concept nature has got a history. Whatever a word might mean though, its uses are another matter. And like the thing nature, the concept nature has appeared again and again in societies, or in conversation or thought, because people have always had one or another kind of use for it. Ambiguity itself makes it very useful. People can think they are talking about the same thing when they aren’t. Or different things when they aren’t. It helps them to agree or disagree—whichever they prefer. Cunningly, the word can refashion its meaning mid-sentence, letting a sentence look as though it has more meaning than it deserves. Surreptitiously, one of nature’s meanings can easily become a fetish for another, making things so mysterious. Just take this as a caveat. Personally, I like to use nature instead of environment or natural environment. When Tim Low says he cringes at the word nature, he speaks for the times. But even though it sounds a bit dated and precious, I don’t mind. It lacks the cheap technical prestige of natural environment. I prefer nature’s cheap poetic prestige. And I prefer an old anachronism like nature to a new one like the natural environment. And I like to have something nice and material to point to when people start extolling the virtues of spirituality. I like to be able

125

to use nature to refer to the objects of the physical world, which, as far as I am concerned include the objects of the biological, psychological and social worlds. Bodies, minds and societies are among the most wonderful and peculiar bits of nature. The recurring inclination to define the concept nature is probably a symptom that, as with the thing, people are seldom fully conscious of just what they are doing with it or to it. Even less are they aware of what it is doing with them. It is an all too useful miasma of connotations. While they are busy not really thinking what they are doing with it, it is using them to keep itself alive as an evolving concept on the tip of everyone’s tongue. One of the things the ambiguous old concept does is hide society from itself. And the thing nature is used to do this too. We find it so easy to hide ourselves and society behind its vast and dazzling presence that we are reluctant to accept that we and society are lurking in it and haunting it everywhere. It is a kind of sleight of hand—an illusion that society uses to fool us. Even ecologists are apt to comply by seldom writing humans into the inventories of the species in the bits of nature they study. They are quite scrupulous about this. Homo sapiens is one of the most important speciesperhaps what some ecologists used to call a keystone speciesin all the earth’s biological communities. Everything on earth is somehow at our mercy, if only at the mercy of our capacity for destruction. For this reason alone, society must be understood as a major player in the ecological processes of those peculiar objects that make up what we like to call the natural environment. No wonder it is we humans then that so often come back in the form of nature to haunt ourselves. Ecology that ignores society can scarcely claim to be ecological. Yet it is not only our capacity for destruction that matters. Although custom conceives nature as the antithesis of culture, this custom itself belongs to our peculiar culture of nature. Nature is culture—high culture and pop culture—and it’s big. The provider of natural resources and ecosystem services, the object of scientific and aesthetic experience, nature is not only used and abused, exploited and wasted, it is sold, imagined, promoted, admired, explained, depicted, defended, conserved, managed and restored. Even so, when contemplating a sublime landscape painted in the 19th century, Robert Hughes scoffed at the idea that nature is a cultural construct. And he was right enough. This is just a platitude that does neither nature nor culture justice. For although nature is a culture, it is more instructive to assert that culture is a natural construct. Cultural theorists, especially when teaching, insist upon emphasizing that something or other is a cultural construct. They are at pains to do this precisely because culture is like nature. It carries on the construction of its cultural forms in a natural and unnoticed manner, as if it were natural. Cultural construction is just culture’s nature. In a meditation on wildlife, the American naturalist Aldo Leopold wondered whether ‘human populations have behaviour patterns of which we are unaware, but which we help to execute (186)?’ Are there social processes which, rather than being collective acts of individual volition are somehow supra-individual 126

processes. He suspected that there were and that our knowledge of them is ‘largely ex post facto.’ It seems that there is a kind of human or social nature that is wild in its own way, wild enough to exceed human intentions and, at least until after the fact, human awareness. Going on over the heads of individuals, a bit like Adam Smith’s guiding hand, society has its own history, the objectivity of which is that of natural history. Nature has its own cultural history and culture has its own natural history. How best to describe this natural history of society is what concerns me here. For nature not only has its natural history as nature, it has its own natural history as a cultural form. Without a good description, the natural history of culture may be barely registered except in a certain arbitrary defiance of our intentions and then only subliminally as something uncomfortable or alien. When this happens in social or political life we are likely to attribute it to the human agency of others, or to that supraindividual bogey that we like to designate with the anonymous pronoun they, or to that bad old deep down human nature. We hold dear the notion that all social phenomena have their origins and persistence in individual will, whether we delight in freedom or shrug things off to some unchangeable, miserable human essence. However what most interests me is when a circumstance that strikes us as beyond our control seems to have its origin in the natural environment, as it does for example in the features of a national park. In cases like this we might just be making the mistake of accepting such a circumstance as a given of natural nature when in fact it is a social phenomenon.

The Natural History Of Culture Even though ecology can ill afford to ignore society, social science can ill afford to ignore biological thought. By this though, I don’t simply mean the environmentalist commonplace that economics should take the ecology of resources into account. What I mean is that a kind of processone that is very well known to biological thoughtcan be used to describe and explain many familiar but otherwise mystifying features of society, features that exhibit their own self-perpetuation and determination. The process is a selection process, and a theory of social (as opposed to natural) selection can be used to describe the nature of many social phenomena. Such a description then provides novel explanations and surprising predictions about the social phenomena so described. The best-known selection process is what Darwin famously described as evolution by natural selection. In natural selection, genes are copied, often with slight variation, and then they are selected according to whether the functions of the features that organisms have because of these genes have led, on average, to better survival and reproduction of the organisms. This is a particularly brief and inadequate description of a process of which there have been all too many brief and inadequate descriptions. Most people think they know enough about 127

natural selection to think that they know what evolution is all about anyway. However, for an idea that is part of the educated common sense of modernity it is notoriously misunderstood. This is mainly because selection, as an algorithmic process, is apt to generate mind-boggling results from the remorseless repetition of quite simple steps. For such a brilliantly simple idea, natural selection is not simple. In social evolution by social selection the things that get copied, also often with variation, are cultural forms. When stories are told and retold, when something or someone is imitated, when documents are copied, when something is learned and taught, when clichés are uttered and re-uttered, when anything is communicated or when any formality, manner, genre, custom, tradition or institution is reproduced, cultural forms are getting copied. The sociologist Niklas Luhmann (1984) contended that society is best conceived as a collection of communications. Such a description of society, he claimed, is more useful than the notion that society is a collection of people. The stuff of society is this galaxy of reproducing cultural forms. In social evolution they are copied, often with slight variation, and then they are selected according to whether the their physical, symbolic or semantic features have functioned, on average, for the good of their survival and repeated copying. Thus cultural forms evolve according to the strictures of a selection process that is Darwinian in its algorithmic form but social and communicative rather than biological and genetic in terms of the content or stuff it works on. I admit that this is as brief and inadequate a description of social selection as the description of genetic selection above. Many have provided more exhaustive accounts from David Hull (1988) to Daniel Dennett (1995) to the Journal of Memetics. This theory of social selection is a contested science. Is it a real science or not? It will just have to prove itself by its adequacy to descriptive and explanatory demands. Like any science. Any validation, like that of any science, would be stronger for being supplemented by the convergence of the theory with other scientific disciplines, just as natural selection has been convergent with knowledge in genetics, ecology and geology. For my purposes here it need only be virtually or effectively scientific. Like any science. The science of social selection has been called memetics. One of the problems people have with accepting such descriptions of society is that the replicable units in the selection processthe forms of cultureare sometimes called memes. The term sounds like a label for selling a fangled thingo of dubious ontological status. Whatever memes are supposed to be, people are disinclined to countenance their existence. The term was coined (as an analogy with gene) by the evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins, almost as a throwaway, in his pop science book pitched with a marketable anti-humanist title: The Selfish Gene. With that pedigree, meme sounds like the jargon of catchy sociobiology, and for that matter, a concept that seems destined quickly to go the way of humours or spirits or phlogiston or some dizzy household detergent additive. Whatever its fate, the term denotes phenomena that belong

128

to cultural theory, social history, and social science, rather than biology or even sociobiology. Society is a universe of replicable cultural forms or memes. Just what is one of these replicable forms of culture? Surely if they had to be labeled memes they can’t just be these things we have been making and copying for yearswords, clichés, stories, films, jokes, songs, genres, tools, gardens, forests, national parks, images, financial transactions, moral actions, acts of war, rites, rituals, traditions, procedures, protocols, methods, forms and formalitiesotherwise we would have noticed them. Are they mental things in brains or are they in the physical copies or are they gestures or actions? These are ontological questions, questions of existence. It is worth recalling that genes had a skeptical ontological reception when they were first mooted. Indeed, despite their undoubted material character, just what a gene is is still by no means a simple question. Just how a gene is defined depends upon what kinds of operations are being described, and this depends upon the branch of biology in which the operation is relevant. Population genetics, evolutionary biology, taxonomy and biochemistry all prefer to conceive genes slightly differently. Also recall that Darwin himself had managed to describe a selection process pretty well without describing just what was getting copied. He had to speak about inheritance between generations without having a clue about the mechanism. He was a natural historian, not a geneticist. No one was then. As I have said, I just want to use the explanatory power of a selection process. My concerns are epistemological, or ‘how and why’ questions, rather than ontological or ‘what’ questions. In this I am only following the inclinations of modern science. Ontology otherwise is too much like metaphysics. In accordance with empirical science, and like the anthropologist Dan Sperber (1996), I insist that the explanations of culture only commit to an ontology of quite material things: representations in the mental sphere, that is neurological events in brains, and representations in the public sphere, that is physical objects and actions. Whether the replicable forms are in the brains or in the public sphere or both, or whether you want to think, by analogy with genetics, that the mental phenomena correspond say to the genotype and the public forms to the phenotype, or, as I am inclined to, vice versa, I agree with Sperber that the causal chain of mental object - public object - mental object public object - and so on is what is crucial. What matters is whether these objects are empirical enough, stable enough, and causal enough to be observed or inferred as copied objects in a selection process that runs through social history. For my purposes here (if not for a full explanation) these forms might as well be the physical, observable copiesthe observable forms of cultureas long as they (like genes in natural selection) satisfy the conditions needed to make them operational objects in their own kind of selection process. In fact this is why no one noticed them before. Although people noticed the replication of words, stories, jokes, garden design, institutional procedures, traditional practices, etc, and although it is our quite normal recognition, labeling and reproduction of these things that constitutes their operationally distinct character, no one actually noticed these things as operational objects in 129

selection processes. They are probably even less likely to notice it in the case of what we are apt to think of as nature or the natural environment. National park design, the biodiversity we value, the kinds of places reserved, the tracks, look outs, facilities and interpretative centres, ecotourism practices, picnicking and bushwalking cultures, environmental laws, bushfire management practices, environmental management and restoration techniques and aims—all these things are also cultural forms undergoing replication with variation and selection. If they are to operate as the things copied (sometimes with variation) in a selection process, then the following conditions must apply. They must at least embody a discrete amount of information. As with genes, what gets transmitted from one generation of cultural forms to the next is, in abstract, information. (I should say though, that there is no such thing as information abstracted from a context in which there is something or someone to interpret it. In the case of genes that would be the cellular environment; in the case of cultural forms that would be human minds.) They must be members of a lineage of copieseven if sometimes with variation between copiesand the tendency of the copies to change through the lineage from copy to copy should not exceed the pressure of the selection process to favour the survival and subsequent copying of certain forms over other forms. (Williams 1966, 25; Wilkins 1998). If a cultural form were to change in a way that exceeded the social selection pressures, then it could not be seen as adapted to those social selection pressures. However society is well supplied with cultural forms that satisfy this proviso. The selection pressures are exerted by the physical environment of the copies, in particular by the physical media and environments in which the copies are embodied, by the mental or psychic environment that interprets the copies as well as storing the information and initiating its replication, and by the social environment of other copies. Thus a cultural form like the safely fenced lookout platform is copied over and over again and persists because it meets persistent social and psychic pressures to look at views from a safe vantage. The cultural nature of humans evolves faster than the genetically conditioned biophysical nature. In turn however, the biophysical nature of humans is an especially persistent selection pressure in the evolution of culture and to that extent accounts for relatively persistent features of culture. On the other hand, cultural forms that are free from such persistent pressures (such as say the colour of the safety rails) may be copied for reasons of fashion, but due to there being much less pressure to eliminate variant copies (as there is in the case of look-outs without safety fences at all) the features of such forms tend to undergo a certain amount of random drift. Even so, compared to the clothing that people wear at the lookouts, the colour of the rails is probably less prone to random drift. For reasons having to do with a relatively persistent cult of naturalness, wood-grain, brown and green seem to have persisted pretty well as railing colours in local national parks. Of course, the national parks themselves make up a lineage of copies of what is the most common kind of modern nature

130

reserve. They are institutions sharing inherited features that are adapted to the specific legal, national, scientific and recreational environment of the times. As part of the educated common sense of modernity, it is often assumed that the power of the theory of natural selection lies in its enabling us to cobble together genealogies of species, to discover missing links and branches of families, and to reveal the origins of species. No doubt human nous is fascinated by stories, gratified by the plausible historicist explanations they offer and charmed by myths of origin. However such a use squanders the explanatory power that description as a selection process supplies. As the evolutionary biologist George Williams (1966) emphasized, it is the fact of a genealogical process of selection that enables evolutionary theory to be used in turn as a theory of the functional adaptation and biological design of organisms. The same goes for social selection. It is a theory of the design and adaptation of cultural formsdesign for and adaptation to the psychic, social and physical environment of society. Piecing together genealogies is most useful as a stage in the explanation and prediction of function and design, and in many cases these defy the expectations of historicist plausibility. Given the branching tree of cultural genealogy, most searches for single origins of cultural forms are futile, most myths of origin invalid. One origin of these ideas on the history of ideas lies in that most original and ironically titled work of natural history, On The Origin of Species. Another lies in Darwin’s critic, Friedrich Nietzsche—although the author of Genealogy of Morals is more a critic of Darwin’s English temperament than of his genealogical cast of mind. In accounting for evolution by selection, the features of organisms are not traced back to origins, but are accounted for as having been inherited from their ancestors because they did the job for those ancestors; and they had better do something nowany which awayif they are going to get passed on again. And in the course of history, the function of an inherited feature may well change; where natural history provides design, survival and selection may well find new uses. Some bones in a reptiles jaw turn out to be useful in mammals’ ears. Skin flaps for cooling are found to be useful as skin flaps for gliding. Likewise in social nature, a memetic feature such as punishment is adapted, as Nietzsche showed (213), to satisfy many ends: such as quarantine, retribution, vengeance, rehabilitation, memorial, or triumphant indulgence of malice. As Nietzsche puts it, ‘the actual cause of a thing’s origin and its eventual uses, the manner of its incorporation into a system of purposes, are worlds apart.’ ‘While forms are fluid, their meaning is even more so.’ In the postcolonial culture of nature the bush has been adapted to many social ends. Initially a by-product or leftover of the agricultural and urban landgrab of colonialism it works now as recreational parkland, travelling stock route, undispensed common land, forestry, conservation of flora and fauna, protection of water supply catchments, scenic backdrop, restitution for indigenous dispossession, and wilderness to name only a few of its functions. Thinking about the history of social phenomena as a genealogy of the replication and selection of cultural forms is very useful as a way of describing 131

certain more or less persistent features of society, and discovering their functions as socially selected cultural phenomena. Given the variety of functions to which a single form may be put and the selection of forms based on their functioning for the perpetuation of the form itselfand not necessarily for the individual humans who deliberately or inadvertently replicate itmost speculation about authentic or original function is vain, and myths of authentic function are wrong-headed. Instead, the theory of social selection enables predictions about the function of a particular cultural feature and about the particular environmental pressurespsychic, or social or physicalthat a feature is designed to deal with. By describing and discovering the kinds of social and psychological selection pressures operating in the environment of the particular cultural phenomenon, it is possible to discover functions that might otherwise not have been recognized at all. One of the insights that such a theory gives is that many features of society have functions for themselves that are quite surprising or unexpected. Society can be both counterintuitive and operating against our interests. This is because cultural forms, like genes, are selected for features whose function is their survival and reproduction, and not necessarily ours. What they do for themselves is not necessarily what we might think they do for us or what we think we are doing with them. These ideas are the key to sober understanding of what might otherwise have seemed like a delirious description of nature. They demystify a culture of nature, much of which is a kind of unconscious culture. How then may this theory about the natural history of culture be applied to those bits of culture that we think of as natural heritage in order to see how they have a natural history as culture as well as a natural history as ecosystems? The cultural forms by which we know nature are replicated by our own and nature’s devices and selected by the pressures that we, deliberately and inadvertently bring to bear. I don’t simply mean the landscape art, photography, ecological science, management plans, environmentalist literature and all the other images and documents of our culture of nature. More on these later. They belong to the image of nature. They are all commentary, translation and annotation to the primary forms of the culture of nature, namely those that are embodied in physical nature itself: things like national parks, nature reserves, marine reserves, and various bits of bush, coast, ocean, rivers, public or private land and all the plants, creatures and geophysical feature that they comprise. Consider one local genre: the lowland, floodplain rainforest remnant. Besides the few hectares of bat ridden brush at Bellingen Island there are similar remnants on the North Coast at Wingham Brush on the Manning, at Coramba on the Orara, at Susan Island and Maclean on the Clarence River, at several places on the red volcanic soil that once supported the Big Scrub, at Stott’s Island in the Tweed River, and at many more smaller, less public patches dotted along streams or about paddocks. Persistent pressures of social selection have led to similarities in their form, similarities that might otherwise be thought of as just plain naturally natural. These shared features are maintained by the persistence of pressures selecting successful features through 132

time. In some cases, certain features may have performed different functions at different periods of the remnants evolution. Indeed such features have persisted because they have performed different functions when needed. At first it might seem that these remnants are not a lineage of cultural forms, but rather at best, the similar results of similar selection processes operating as a kind of parallel evolution on unrelated natural objects in different areas. However it is because of their shared culture of management—whether it be the past unconscious management of which they seem like the accidental leftovers, or the modern culture of conservation and restoration of which they are an articulate expression—that they are a lineage. Each of these forms of culture is a lineage and so therefore are its products or expressions in which one may observe features that have been replicated from remnant to remnant. For instance, these thoroughly cultural forms are always remnants, small patches from a few hectares down to a few trees. Small size was an adaptation to ancestral selection pressures: large patches were cleared for agricultural exploitation of the alluvium; small patches survived as nooks or crannies on flood prone land or steep banks, and as public recreation or natural heritage areas. High flood risk, steep riverbanks, proximity to towns in need of public land for common utilitarian, recreational or natural heritage purposes have all been adaptations. Even though small size was often a concomitant feature of these, it did of itself act as a disincentive to clearing, so it was selected as an adaptation itself. Yet although functional in the past, small size might seem no longer to be an optimal adaptation. It doesn’t to conservation ecology. For conservation ecology, small size means fewer species. Small size catches up on remnants in the form of ecological invasions and subsequent structural and biotic degradation. In an environment of chronic flooding, cattle grazing or recreational traffic, small size makes for rainforest remnants that are weedy or weed prone. However many or most of these small remnants are now intensively worked upon in order to maintain there weed free forms. In the context of social selection small size and proximity to towns, rather than operating simply as potentially lethal ecological features can be selected as advantageous features. In defiance of ecological theories of fragmentation, small size can become useful. It is an adaptation to the limited management capacity of restoration culture and to the modern circumstances of tenure and demographic distribution. And what may have once been a cause of lethal variation to a remnant—that is a cause of its degradation—can now be a cause of beneficial variation that increases the remnants’ chance of survival as management changes and as biological forms like species composition and structure change with it. Three of the remnants are next to towns, near the heads of riverine navigation and permanent freshwater, and they are long-term flying fox camps. Flying fox camps are unconscious cultural forms in themselves, strangely natural and unnatural. Social preferences for the location and structure of towns and remnants—the selection pressures to which the remnants are adapted— match the preferences that flying foxes exhibit in the selection of their camps: 133

the remnants are last relics of natural heritage, they are adjacent to streams, they are an optimal solution to the problem of available freshwater and proximity to the coast. Like litter along the highway littoral, flying fox camps are not positioned at random. Flying foxes make their own urban centres where we make ours. They can see the generic features of these remnants, and add themselves to the production and replication of the generic mix. And now the ecological management of remnants for flying foxes reproduces itself up and down the North Coast. Tree canopy is a feature of these restored remnants. Indeed it is an aesthetic, technical and (given the bats’ adverse effect on it) political problematic. It is not simply a fact of or a defining feature of any rainforest and therefore of these remnant rainforests. Canopy is a norm of rainforest restoration culture, replicated and selected for the convergence of its functional role for efficient weed management and its defining status in popular rainforest ecology. Vegetation made up of tree canopy species is socially more successful than viny canopy or gap vegetation. Up and down the North Coast it is replicated and selected as the reified form of lowland rainforest. That is, it is made into the real form. These municipal micro-wildernesses may seem too small and too much the product of human actions to be properly called nature except in the philosophers’ sense of 2nd nature. The national park is the authentic cultural form of natural nature. The rainforest patches are all remnants evolved from the little bits that were once gratuitously cut from the cloth of the pristine lowland rainforests; and though they are now somewhat stylized images, or even to some extent arbitrary symbols, of those pristine forests, I cite them precisely because they epitomize the status of all nature here and now on the North Coast: the rainforest remnants, the coastal bush, the escarpment national park, the state forest or ex-state forest, the bush on steep land at the back of the farmat the scale of private ownership a kind of functional analogue of the escarpment national park which is located at the back of the agricultural lowland landscape. Each of these genres reproduces its forms and each form persists in an evolving lineage because it was formerly adapted to specific social selection pressures and it is now adapted not only to such modern uses as biodiversity conservation, public recreation, natural heritage, tourism, and the aesthetics of nature, but to many less well recognized and less well intentioned uses. In each we may discern the eerie repetitions and the social maintenance of persistent cultural forms of nature. Our relations to nature are social relations, relations of humans to one another. For nature is a sign through which we speak. Yet it is, like language, a system of signs that exceed our intentions, and as they say of language so we may say of nature: it speaks us. This is the nature of the nature we love. It escapes our intentions both as wild beautiful nature and as a cultural form.

134

II The Image of Nature

135

136

10 Shallow Ecology, The Philosophy Of A Science The science of ecology, its concerns and its limitations.

We have no sound notions either in logic or physics; substance, quality, action, passion, and existence are not clear notions; much less, weight, levity, density, tenuity, moisture, dryness, generation, corruption, attraction, repulsion, element, matter, form, and the like. They are all fantastical and ill defined. —Francis Bacon, Novum Organum, §15

The Philosophy Of Science Meets Ecology Philosophy, science and the philosophy of science may have been born together of the same inquiring impulse, but they have been defining themselves and separating into their own departments ever since. In the 14th century William of Ockham’s via moderna plainly differentiated itself from the old metaphysics, seeing no need to encumber nature—already bewildering enough —with a clutter of unwanted objects and contrived explanations. The rule of cutting back on metaphysical clutter still goes by the name of Ockham’s Razor. In the 17th century both Bacon and Descartes again declared independence from the past while philosophizing about modernity’s prodigy: science. Works like Bacon’s Novum Organum (the greatest work of English prose not written in English) and Descartes’ Discourse on Method are seen as seminal in the department of learning now called the philosophy of science. They seem to stand at the threshold of modernity like prophetic manifestos declaring the philosophical intentions and protocols science was thereafter to fulfill. Yet while philosophy was being philosophical, science was too busy becoming science to take a lot of notice. Regardless of philosophy, science just does the philosophy it needs to do in order to do its science. As a philosopher, if not as a mathematician, Descartes turned out to be of little relevance to the physical sciences. His rules in Discourse on Method (§2) about dividing big problems up into parts and directing one’s thoughts to the simplest building blocks of understanding amounted to a renovated version of

137

Ockham’s Razor. As for the search he conducted in the Meditations for foundational, indubitable truths—that was a very big distraction. It was founded on little more than a kind of architectural faith that the value of knowledge, including scientific knowledge, depended upon the certainty of its foundations. Aristotle had written about such foundational principles, or first philosophy as he called it, in the Metaphysics. So Descartes was not so detached from hand-me-down tradition as he declared. What he did was first philosophy, the second time round. It is unfortunate that he did not apply his methodological doubt to the received notion that the certainty of first principles was somehow so important. Combining faith in certainty with abstract scepticism has been a bad philosophical habit ever since, and very hard to shake off. Descartes was inspired by a modern belief in individuality, by its authenticity when compared to doing philosophy by committee, and by its achievement when compared to rehashing inherited doctrine that ‘several hands have sought to adapt’. Perhaps it was due to these sentiments that, apart from finding certainty in Godthat least empirical and least certain thing of allDescartes claimed to find it in, of all places, the most obscurely subjective sphere: the hidden inner place where the ego describes itself to itself for itself with that all too ingenious argument cogito ergo sum—I think therefore I am. It may be fun for philosophy students to get their minds around, but the cogito line was only half clever. Once philosophers started to question what was doing what and therefore what, the argument started to come apart. Whatever our manner of speech may suggest, the ego, thinking and existence are not as simple as we might fool ourselves into thinking. Meanwhile, not much at all is certain, and nearly everything is susceptible to abstract skepticism. The problem for knowledge was how it could get anywhere given that uncertainty was everywhere. But science forgot this problem and just got on with the business of getting to know about thingsas adequately as it could for its purposes. This is what an organism does—or a subject, as the philosophers used to say. That is, science itself followed Bacon’s, and the organism’s, pragmatic approach. It was cunning, sensualist, and empirical, and it was so busy at it that even Bacon’s philosophy of science was of little explicit relevance to it. The chemist and cofounder of The Royal Society, Robert Boyle, is said to have remarked that Bacon wrote natural philosophy like a Lord Chancellor. He was after all Lord Chancellor and just laying down the law. What empowered physical science was not certaintyand certainly not certainty certified by obscure inner life and an old con artist called the ego doing some trick with mirrors. Science’s strength lay in its relative validity. Although some of its propagandists might like to think so, science is not about absolute truth. Use the word relative though and you risk being accused of the dreaded relativism. Someone reaches for their gun. When I say relative validity I mean that some knowledge is better than others for the purposes at handwhich is certainly not the relativism of any knowledge is as good as any 138

other. Some things are much less uncertain than others. For validity read something half-hearted like adequacy, pragmatic like usefulness, or arrogant like power. There is no way you can observe something without having an observer, and therefore the observer’s subjectivity to deal with. That is just the nature of observation. Empirical science dealt with the difficulties of such unavoidable subjectivity by multiplying them. Among other things, it hit upon a very useful social selection pressure for the validation of its knowledge: empirical observations were to be open to scrutiny by a second observer. Such was the social and normative nature of empirical observation: less than certain, it was a subjective observation of an object, but one that was to be itself, as an observation, openly observable by others. Think of the demand that experiments be repeatable, or more trivially that a technology works for all to see. Partly as a result of having to achieve relative validity, there developed not one unified science but many sciences, each one concerned with the particular problems of explaining its own subject matter as best it could typically using whatever mathematical tools it had on hand. Science is not, as some of its devotees like to think, a single system of knowledge, nor, as its weaker critics parody it, just one system of knowledge among many knowledges. It is many branches of knowledge rooted in a shared system of strong propositions about certain fundamental physical processes. Although the sciences more or less share certain norms about empirical observation, publication, mathematical rigour, theoretical reduction and internal consistency, and although they also share ideals about consistency with one another and translation between one another, they are not all perfectly reconciled, and they do not all speak the same language. Although they are very closely related disciplines describing almost the same set of phenomena, even classical Mendelian genetics cannot be perfectly reduced to molecular biology (Hull, Rosenburg, Sterelny & Griffiths). The biological sciences are also given to explanations that use functional descriptions—say of the hows and whys of the workings of an organism— rather than descriptions in terms of physics or chemistry. The functional properties and relations of organisms can be realized by many different physical mechanisms and the same physical mechanisms can operate in many different functional contexts. Reduction from functional to physical descriptions is not necessarily useful nor, when one functional description must be reduced to several physical descriptions and vice versa, even feasible. This problem seems even more glaring when, in a case internal to ecology, there is a problem of translating between population zoology and botany on the one hand and community ecology on the other, and reducing the latter to the former. The sciences are divided by the differences between their objects, by their particular instrumental imperatives, by the kinds of descriptions they find useful or feasible, and therefore by what Imré Lakatos (1970) called their research programs. A research program is characterized by core ideas whose validity is maintained almost as a methodological principle. If empirical data appear to 139

provide evidence that falsifies one of the core ideas, it is assumed that some other proposition must be reformulated, not a core principle. The adaptationist view of evolutionary biology is one such research program. As its critics like Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin have complained, adaptationism quarantines its core principles from empirical falsification. However it all depends how metaphysical you want to get about your core principles (i.e. how much you deem them to be indisputable principles) and how much you want to insist upon their ontological foundations (i.e. how much you believe in the kinds of objects those principles deem to exist). As the philosophers Kim Sterelny and Paul Griffiths (1999) point out, there are degrees of adaptationism, depending upon which core ideas are held most firmly. One might hold that natural selection shapes most of the significant features of organisms, and that all of these features are adaptations. One might take the less theological view that only natural selection can explain complex adaptations. Or one might simply hold that the concepts of design, adaptation and selection provide good methodological principles to organize theoretical and empirical evolutionary biology. Sciences cluster as research programs around core ideas because in doing so they satisfy not only some Cartesian principle about the division of larger problems into smaller ones, but, more urgently, pragmatic imperatives. Leaping to a universal science—although it might seem to offer more efficient explanations by reducing two sciences to a single common set of core ideas—is easier said than done. While intellectual labour divided its tasks between the sciences, the arts and the humanities, philosophy persisted as something of a secular habitat for universalist aspirations. A lot of philosophical thought about the sciences was given to positing a unitary science and therefore to taking one science, typically physics, as the single norm of a proper science. In its less reflective forms it probably still does. The presumption was that until, say, ecology or sociology could do science like physics—or indeed as physics—they would not be real sciences. Until a science could be reduced to the language of physics it could not be regarded as fully scientific. As it has turned out though, since there are many sciences, it is difficult to formulate any universal theory of the sciences. In the event, different sciences have inspired or demanded different philosophical reflections. Sometimes the reflections have been epistemology— the theory of what knowledge is and how science can or should discover it; sometimes they have been a complaint about the epistemological predicament of a particularly dismal science; sometimes they have been a sociology of how scientific societies have functioned or function; sometimes they have been a philosophy of the history of science. Sometimes even ontological concerns are raised about whether or not the objects that a science deals with are real and exist independently of our concepts. Take the philosophy of biology. Among other things, it has been a discipline concerned with the epistemological status of biology compared with the other sciences. For other sciences tradition still demands that we read physics or chemistry. It has also been concerned with the implications of such things as 140

genetics and evolutionary theory. A great deal of philosophical effort has been devoted to questions about how these biological theories can best conceive of their objects: What are genes? How do we relate genes to microbiology? This stuff has been grist to the mill of philosophy of science: in the problem of reducing genetics to microbiology, biology has supplied an exemplar of the disunity of the sciences. Just how does evolution work? What is an adaptation? What is a species? As attempts to clarify biological thought, these questions are not only philosophy of science, they are also a kind of metabiology: the philosophy biologists have to do in order to do biology. But does biology have implications beyond its discipline, perhaps even beyond the curricula of philosophy of science—implications for so-called philosophy itself. Wittgenstein thought that ‘the Darwinian theory has no more to do with philosophy than has any other hypothesis of natural science' (4.1122). Bertrand Russell thought much the same. However, evolutionary theory has led to evolutionary epistemology, wherein the theory of knowledge becomes the theory of how an organismany organismcan know something, what kind of action that ‘knowing’ can be, and how organisms got to be able to do this thing called ‘knowing’. As a result of this kind of reflection, the philosophy of biology has foreseen its own end, and that of philosophy itself, in something we might as well call the biology of philosophy. This, by the way, is the kind of premonition of self-annihilation that is quite common in such a self-reflective discipline as philosophy. It has all the trappings of philosophy itself. Such a biology of philosophy would be the culmination of the project that the Harvard philosopher Willard Van Ormand Quine (1969) long ago dubbed epistemology naturalized. This is the kind of thing that really puts paid to the old Cartesian I think. The biology of philosophy would understand the nature of knowledge by recognizing that what we can know and how we can know it is something given to us by nature. Knowing, thinking, believing, desiring, feeling, emotion, consciousness, and self-consciousness, are all illuminated by such a project. So is the philosophy of language. So are society and science. In the case of humans I would say that all this depends on the nature of society as well as the biological nature of brainy human bodies; and to support such a claim I would simply cite the significance of scientific culture itself. So epistemology naturalized demands a sociology as well as a biology of philosophy. Even so, in order to think about how nature could construct knowing organisms and societies, one cannot avoid thinking about the problems of what knowledge would be given any possible knowing subject, and any possible nature. These are eminently philosophical problems. They still look like problems for philosophy itself, but they are informed by biology and not only by mathematics and logic (philosophy’s traditional stable mates). What then of the philosophy of ecology? Is there such a beast? What is its relation to the philosophy of biology? And would it have anything at all to contribute to philosophy? Many would probably think it is just another term for environmental philosophya term for speculative thought, political programmatics or personal opinion about environmental ethics under the 141

gathering clouds of ecological catastrophe. Yet we also have a philosophy of the science of ecology. At the very least such a discipline can be the selfdescription of ecology itself, sometimes worried, sometimes self critical, sometimes prescriptivethe philosophy ecologists do in order to do ecology. Even so, if it plays either the methodological handmaid of ecology, or the legislator of ecological theory, it may well be ignored by ecological practice that is too busy just getting on with doing ecology. Philosophy of ecology can also be a reflection on the culture of ecology. Or maybe it might just try to advise ecology that ecology itself is a hopeless task. Either way the philosophy of ecology can inquire into how and why the social phenomenon called ecology is whatever it is. Ecology is a dismal sciencemore or less as dismal as economicsbut, like economics, it is only as dismal as its expectations are ambitious and its questions overweening. This is because what started as a discipline concerned with the relation of an organism to its environment became a discipline concerned with the everything else of environmenta big vague subject, but a fascinating one. All too fascinating. In his Critique for Ecology (1991, 6-14), the ecologist Robert Peters expressed misgivings that ecology is not as competitive, high pressure or interactive as other sciences. Ecological papers have a longer half-life than those in other disciplinesbecause new developments in ecology are not rapidly overtaking one another. They also have a higher rejection ratebecause the reviewers’ expectations about just what constitutes proper ecological research is more a matter of taste than in other disciplines. Ecology is not always quite sure what it is about. Ecology is also a parasite of other sciences, tending to cite papers in non-ecological journals more frequently than ecological papers are cited in them. It is a consumer rather than a producer of knowledgea kind of interdisciplinary affair in an age otherwise marked by specialization. This is one indication that ecology is less likely to contribute to philosophy than vice versa. If philosophy is to be handmaid to ecology it is a case of the master humbled by the servant: ecology is struggling to look after itself; it hasn’t the wherewithal to help others. Several features prejudice ecology’s scientific status: its ideological connection with environmental politics; its widely being taught and practiced in applied form as environmental management; and the false popular notion that it is not as mathematically demanding as other sciences. Last in his list of ecology’s symptomsand in Peter’s opinion its most telling deficiencyis that the practical environmental problems that ecology should solve are not being solved. All of these things go with ecology’s reputation for being a soft science. The problem for the soft sciences however, is that they are, because of the nature of their objects, the hardest. If ecology is in some senses a social scienceinsofar as humans and society are things that ecology can ill afford to ignorethen that makes it even softer and therefore even harder. The term ecology was coined by Ernst Haeckel, and it was inspired by Darwin’s evolutionary theory. Since the relations of organisms to their environments were of such evolutionary significance, a term that referred to the 142

systematic study of such relations was a ready cultural adaptation to post Darwinian scientific society. It may well be said that the term ecology was coined after the fact of the discipline itself, and that the first great achievement of ecology was, indeed, the theory of natural selectiona theory that could be said to mark the differentiation of ecology and evolutionary theory from one another and from their cultural ancestor, natural history. Some might also say it was ecology’s last great achievement. Darwin himself treated environment as a kind of black box. Knowing just exactly what was going on out there around a particular lineage of organisms was not as important as assuming that a lot was going on no matter what it was. It was terribly complicated and it had mostly been in the past. It was much easier to observe the features of the organisms instead of all that environment. For all his experience of the diversity of natural history and the examples it supplied him in the sustained argument of Origin of The Species, Darwin could not hope thoroughly to analyze the complex and obscure detail of an organism’s historical environment. Instead he concentrated on the organism and on the way its physiology was an index of the selection pressures that had been exerted by its evolutionary environments. The process of inheritance with variation went on, as it were, within the lineage of organisms. Beyond that, all of that environmental complexity fell under the abstract term selection. By this schematic conception, Darwin and subsequent adaptationist theory defined its way out of the problem of the difficulty of environmental complexity, and in a manner that has worried many a thoughtful student with the niggling sense that a tautology lurked in the catch-phrase notion of survival of the fittest. It looks as if fitness is defined by survival of the selection process. However the contingent status of fitness is conferred by the fact of selection, while the concept of selection stands by definition for the mess of environments that have surrounded the ancestral lineage of organisms. This was, in fact, a handy old scientific ploy: to solve problems by convention. Newtonian physics, for example, had made life easy for itself by defining force and momentum and energy in ways that, at the time, were most mathematically convenient, and which now seem so natural: physical nature could be divided and had, as it were, divided itself at its mathematically given joints. Likewise, for operational convenience, nature could be carved into organism and environment, and the indescribable complexity of environment could be referred to the much more discrete adaptations of the organism itself. By virtue of its own self-referring, self-maintenance, and by virtue of the relative historical persistence of its lineage, the organism was effectively one of a so-called natural kind or species. It was therefore a much better behaved scientific object than an environment. It is also better behaved than an ecosystem or community, or various other such things that ecology has used to try and carve environment up into something more useful. The concept gene is also, for that matter, quite well behaved. It is noteworthy though that Darwin had to treat the mechanics of inheritance as a black box too. As things turned out, genetics has proven to be a science whose 143

once utterly cryptic objects are quite conducive to observation, theory and technological application, and its contributions back to evolutionary theory have been very handy. Not as much can be said for the science of environment. Its subject matter compared to that of genetics is so visibly obvious yet so theoretically intractable. Apart from its being such a miscellany of objects, there is a appalling excess of history and contingency over general laws. Darwin’s theory, as one of the characteristic stages in the developing historical consciousness of modernity, had actually assumed the mutability of the eternal species themselves, but it had been able to demonstrate how, out of the obvious and fleeting mutability of the generations, those species could become apparently, relatively or effectively eternal. Perhaps Darwin’s theory was the progenitor of ecology’s hopeful project because it seemed to discover one way of looking on messy historical matters with the eye of relative eternity, and clawing back a little universality from a surfeit of particulars. Sadly however, humans had never had any trouble thinking that species were eternal; disabusing them of that had been the problem. In the division of the sciences, evolutionary theory held on to quasi-eternal timescales and ecology took on the profane riff-raff. Environments, ecosystems, communities, populations and whatever other objects ecology set its sights on were never going to be so easy to conceive as species. Natural kinds of things they may seem, but neither an ecosystem nor a community is one of a natural kind in the sense that philosophers of science use the term. It is not one of a class of things that exhibit characteristics that are strictly or effectively universal. It is not such a wonder then that ecology’s interest in the bits and pieces of environments, and also its holistic ambitions present it with a hotchpotch of different kinds of objects that do not seamlessly combine into discrete, unambiguous wholes. Knowledge of these heterogeneous objects like ecosystems, communities, populations, and food webs, must be derived from several other disciplines, and because science is not a unified discipline with a single language, the languages of these descriptions are not always inter-translatable and the descriptions of one set of objects (e.g. the organisms) are not reducible to or compatible with descriptions of another set of objects (e.g. the geo-physical or the biochemical). Coining terms such as ecosystem or community to refer to composite phenomena or more hopefully to emergent phenomena is to risk abstractions that reduce or sacrifice relevant information. Throughout its long history, nature has managed to build some composite phenomena that have emerged as systemic wholes. Organisms are a composite of cells, and cells are composites too, yet both may be described as emergent phenomena, that is, at a level of description that need not revert to description in terms of the composite elements. At stages of evolutionary history these things evolved into self-referring systems. In turn, cooperatives of individual organisms have evolved in social insects like ants. In human society we can observe the emergence of wholes from composites of individuals. These social things though are already starting to exhibit less than a systemic selfreference. Only by the ingenious definition of society as a system of 144

communications rather than of people can a social systems theorist like Niklas Luhmann make the claim—much disputed at that—to be working with discrete, emergent objects that yield useful sociological universals. Beyond these things, most of ecology’s composite phenomena are much messier than the deceptively singular terms that refer to them. And mere faith in their being emergent phenomena is not enough. Aspirants for holistic ecology have the habit of firing off accusations of reductionism, but they practise it themselves with the vengeance of justified sinners. The pseudo-emergent composite phenomena that have interested ecology—classically, ecosystems and communities—are not effectively of a natural kind, they share few useful, measurable properties, they can seldom be causally related without ambiguity, and they are seldom amenable to reliable prediction. A science that is concerned with well defined, causally discrete kinds of objects is more likely to generate a reliable body of predictive theory than one that deals with the kinds of composites and vagaries that interest ecological inquiry. Think of physics and chemistry. We get the feeling that these sciences, within their carefully prescribed horizons, get a hell of a lot right. Forget absolute truth. There might be concepts that need correction at times and new objects to contemplate, but the descriptions and explanations are remarkably adequate to their objects, accurate in prediction and very useful for our technological purposes. With the aid of a bit of calculus, everyday descriptions of certain of our common experiencesfalling bodies, accelerating vehicles, discharging batteriescan be reduced to precise (and predictively accurate) physical or chemical descriptions. In physics, whether we’re describing lead or feathers or wood, mass is mass, a kilo a kilo. Not so in ecology. In ecology those feathers might have a duck in them—a duck with a mind of its own. The reduction from the level of lead or feather descriptions to that of a description of sheer mass is really a reduction of information. We lose the duck. In physics, information in one description can usefully replace the unwieldy surfeit of information either of many descriptions or of a complex ecological description. Any information lost or ignored is of little relevance, so the reduction may be deemed at least effective if not exhaustive. Those who think these sciences pretty well get their prescribed department of reality down pat are sometimes, in philosophy of science circles, called realists. Other sciences might have to posit whatever makeshift entities they need in order to get whatever epistemological purchase they can. Such sciences have been termed instrumentalist. By using the terms realist and instrumentalist I don’t mean to suggest that the objects of an instrumental science like ecology don’t have any real existence independent of us and our concepts. In some philosophical contexts these terms are used to distinguish between the attitudes of being ontologically committed or not to the objects of a science, or indeed to the objects of everyday experience. My use of these terms, however, is epistemological, not ontological. It is a matter of knowledge and power. The sciences all share an instrumental imperative but different sciences want to move and shake different kinds of objects with different kinds of physical or functional organization 145

operating at different spatial and temporal scales. This disunifies them. Ecology’s instrumental intentions force it to use concepts that refer to only roughly differentiated kinds of objects. The instrumental purposes of the more realist sciences do not demand such a sacrifice. They have the good fortune to be interested in well-defined kinds of objects. This is not much help though when it comes to describing and explaining the objects of particular interest to the more instrumentalist sciences. A quasi-functional quasi-systemic thing like an ecosystem is made up of functional systemic things like organisms, and organisms are made up of physical particles, but imagine reducing a description of an ecosystem to particle physics. If it were feasible it would be useless. Consider that problem in the biological sciences of translating between descriptions of the functional physiological features of organisms or the Mendelian genes for such features and descriptions of the nucleotide biochemistry of the organisms’ DNA. It is not possible to reduce a set of descriptions at the former level to a single explanatory description at the latter level, or vice versa. An observable feature of an organism may be due to any one of several biochemical descriptions; or a particular nucleotide configuration may explain one or another of several features. As Alexander Rosenberg argues, this is because natural selection selects an organic feature for its function, and it is effectively blind to the precise molecular biology that causes that feature. For this reason Rosenberg characterizes biology as an instrumentalist science. Technologically it is pretty effective. Translating talk about physiological features and Mendelian genetics into talk about DNA gives plenty of epistemological and technological purchase. Each kind of description has it uses and depending upon your purposes, one may be more useful than the other in order to get the job done. This is characteristic of an instrumentalist science. Genetics is a successful instrumental science because it does in fact still have remarkable powers of reduction. Ecology is another matter. Trying to understand and manipulate an ecological community by reducing community ecology to population zoology and population botany is much less feasible. Ecology is given to functional rather than physical and chemical descriptions, but even the functional descriptions of the different ecological subdisciplines with their different ecological objects and interests do not translate well between one another. Yet this is just the sort of translation instrumental ecology has to do all the time.

The origin of ecological objects Community ecology is so conceptually complex that we rarely have any difficulty in explaining any result we encounter, have very little difficulty believing the explanations, and may feel that we even expected the result. —Stuart Pimm, The Balance of Nature?, 388 146

Not just ecology, but all the biological sciences are descended from the older discipline of natural history. Their differentiation from natural history is a feature of modern scientific society. The main differentiating trait has not always been the development of a consistent body of predictive theory, but rather the development of a set of norms, particularly the norms of empirical research specifying the rigours of observation, statistical inference and publication. Sometimes—especially in ecology—these norms can seem to have taken on a life of their own, the show of compliance seeming to be more impressive than the body of valid claims and predictions that their institution is expected to generate. Biology is liberated from the accidents and the particularities that characterise historical descriptions when it can generate a body of claims that apply to each and every process or object that is of a kind. What may be said of a kind may be said of any individual that belongs to that kind, and hence is very useful when making predictions. In addition, unless objects can be observed as objects of a kind, then the repeatability of empirical observation becomes unachievable. The observation may still be empirical and open in the sense that it is of something external, spatio-temporal and physical —i.e. it is not an inner observation of a mental phenomenon—but it is a once only observation, an observation of something imprisoned, not in inner life, but in the particularity of history. In order to make predictions, a science must be able to properly and clearly designate the kinds of things that, as it were, are given to it by nature. Its concepts must refer to the salient phenomenaor as Plato said, ideas must rescue phenomenawithout letting whatever is relevant fall through the net of its observations, and without letting itself be distracted by a multitude of extraneous details. Science is quite an art. Socrates used the term natural kind in Plato’s Phaidros when talking about the way science must carve nature at its joints and not break up any part as a bad carver might. Of all the modern biological sciences ecology is the one that is least differentiated from natural history. It has managed to apply the norms of empirical research, but has been less successful developing a resourceful body of theory. This is because of the subject matter of ecology: it is a science that has not yielded, and by its interests perhaps cannot yield, much in the way of concepts that can refer to natural kinds. Thus it is a science that has had difficulty replacing particular historical descriptions of processes with general descriptions of kinds of processes. None of the concepts ecosystem, community, population, species, habtitat, niche or adaptation could be said to refer unambiguously to natural kinds. Perhaps population, and species come close. Under the eye of eternity, a species is subject to mutability and not strictly a natural kind; but for many of the purposes of a merely human if not a geological timescale, it is effectively so. Meanwhile it is hardly worth mentioning things like biodiversity or keystone species. None of the concepts succession, assembly, competition or population growth/declineto name a few of ecology’s favouritesrefer to processes that can be easily reduced to 147

general descriptions. At best, perhaps population dynamics have some nice mathematical descriptions. As for properties like resilience, persistence, resistance or relations like carrying capacity, species/area or predator/prey, they are the stuff in trade of conservation and restoration ecology. Ecosystem managers want to know how resilient a small population is, how resistant a community is to weed invasion, how large an area a viable population needs. Yet each of these relations and each of the processes depends upon the primary conception of objects like community or population. And they are all so fraught with irreducible historical contingency that researchers find themselves loath to make particular predictions from any general theory. At best all these concepts are given to us by our meddlesome, conniving human interests—by human nature—and they say as much about us as about the rest of the world that we would like to carve up in to them. Here the philosophy of biology, as a reflection on the biology of epistemology, can assist the philosophy of ecology. The insights of evolutionary epistemologyboth natural and socialcast some light on ecology’s epistemological labyrinth, if not to lead us out at least to show how we got here. The things that our ecological concepts designate seem like such a mixed bag because our interest in them is result of the jumbled history of genetic and social co-evolution. The things we have developed our most intimate relations to thingsrelations such as sustenance, shelter, ownership and belongingare precisely the objects that now interest ecology: ecosystems, species, populations, communities and areas. When we gather oysters from a seashore we gather a certain species from a certain ecosystem. We have been doing folk ecology ever since we evolved, just as we have been doing folk physics, psychology and sociology. We have developed terms for communities and species and for cobbling together as best we can the useful explanations and natural histories that we have needed as ecological players. The terms and explanations may not carve nature at joints of its own but we use them to carve it up as well as we can for our own purposes. All humans are genetically predisposed to recognise species and populations for good evolutionary reasons, even if what we call a species is anything but a simple type of thing. Despite the natural human ease with which we identify a species as a type, it is actually a very complex, composite individual—a temporally strung out population of genealogically related organisms—not clear cut and quite difficult and contentious to define. Compared to the time-span of a human life though, the features of its individual organisms do usually appear persistent and clear cut, so that we may refer to the species as a kind in order to satisfy such everyday and evolutionary significant interests as, for instance, eating it or avoiding it. Or, as I am doing here in relation to the human species, to refer to its relatively persistent and therefore effectively universal epistemological proclivities. The evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr had a revealing experience when he compiled a bird taxonomy in a remote area of the New Guinea highlands. Apart from the local highlanders lumping two little warblers together as the same 148

species, their classification and Mayr’s were the same. They agreed on hundreds of species. A dollar bird is a dollar bird is a dollar bird. The members of such a species are highly likely to recognise others of their kind. This is a very good adaptation for successful mating. When members of a species are differentiating their own kind from others it is temptingand usefulto say that nature is making its own distinctions. Such species are anything but arbitrary categories. The recognition of different speciesat least of bird speciesis pretty much pan-cultural. It is effectively, if not strictly, a human universal. Effective is good enough. Biologists have differed over just what the status of a species is. Stephen Jay Gould (1987, 173) used Mayr’s story, and similar evidence from other ecologists and anthropologists to argue that species are “real” units in nature as a result both of their history and the current interaction among members. However this does not make a species a natural kind in the sense that a natural kind is a strict universal. The evolution of species is ultimately a matter of branching family trees, so when it comes to the fine taxonomic point of drawing a line between one species and another, the final cut can often seem somewhat arbitrary. It is as arbitrary as the separation of parent and child. Yet nature discovered virtual reality aeons ago: when it comes to natural history what is real is virtual reality or effective reality. It seems to have been philosophers, like Plato, who were fooled by nature and got it into their heads that the only things that could be really real had to beglorious confusionideal. Although the term real unit might traditionally (and confusingly) have been used to refer to strict natural kinds, Gould’s view —with his real couched in scare quotes—is not really at odds with Darwin’s view that we have to treat species as…merely artificial combinations made for convenience. It is just that it would be inconvenient indeed to ignore the effective units that natural selection has occasionally managed to generate. In fact, natural selection itself is effectively a natural kind of historical process. Natural history might not generate perfect natural kinds, but members of most species are about as close as ecological objects get to being instances of such a thing, and the ecology of such species enables many a reliable prediction. What about ecological objects other than species? As members of the human species we are by nature very interested in biological communities and ecosystems, whether they are cultivated crops, or forests, gardens, grasslands, woodlands, rivers, lakes, dwellings or whatever. A particular biological community is an individual thing, but our human nous enables us to abstract, albeit with some conceptual violence, a typology for our descriptive and managerial conveniencea convenience that ecological communication could hardly do without. Ecologists around here readily refer to Tallowwood-Blue Gum Forest or Blackbutt Forest or a White Booyong Rainforest. Community typologies however are fuzzy, and fuzzier still in the predictions that they enable. All Blackbutt Forests are sort of the same—computerised measurements of similarity are generated to cluster similar forests under the same name—but they are not always usefully the similar enough. 149

One ambition ecology has had has been to try and find some general principles of how these things called communities develop or are assembled. Succession is a kind of historical processthe process of the development of a community. Unfortunately though, kinds of succession look like they are going to be at least as fuzzy as the kinds of communities that are going through the succession. Successions of a kind of ecological communitywhether a Tallowwood-Blue Gum Forest, or one of the many ‘kinds’ of lowland subtropical rainforestseem all to be more or less different from one another. There is pattern there to give us hope of a universal theory, but just not enough pattern. Too much relevant information is lost in any explanatory description that purports to be universal to all successions of a particular kind of community. A process like succession is always somewhat subject to the accidents and specificities of its particular history: whether it was a dry year or a wet year, whether there was seed available for this species or that species, whether those wallabies grazed it or not, whether highly competitive, historically unprecedented weed species like lantana or Madeira vine were present or not. Succession is an important concept in ecology, because a valid theory of succession would provide the scientific framework for engineering community restoration. And restoration ecology is of special interest because of the damaged state of so many prized ecosystems. Ever since F.E. Clements’ Plant Succession (1916) there has been a debate about whether succession was individualistic and largely determined by unpredictable historical events or whether it was governed by developmental rules. In its strongest versions the developmental school has conceived ecological communities by analogy with organisms: it has argued that community development is controlled by the community itself. The different schools of thought were already implicit in Clements. Although his theory of community succession is usually cited as one that understands succession as a usefully predictable process of development towards a final climax community, Clements recognized that the appearance of a species in a succession depends on particular factors. He also said that the real control, however, is exerted by the factors of habitat (Booth & Larson, 211). That is, the conditions applying within the community itself determine the successful appearance of species, somewhat like the way the condition of an organism controls its development notwithstanding the variable circumstances of its environment. If we take a strong organismic view of succession, engineering community restoration could amount to sitting back and letting nature look after itself. As I said, there is pattern in succession but not enough —certainly not enough to just sit back and let communities restore themselves. Communities and successions are just not that predictable. Perhaps by some clever, counter-intuitive take on things we might eventually distinguish objects that are very like what we now call communities or ecosystems—composites of organisms and physical phenomena—objects which will be best described not at the level of the bits and pieces of organisms and processes and such that make them up, but in terms of emergent processes, 150

the way Newtonian mechanics does not describe all the atoms in a projectile, but only the behaviour of their combined mass. Or, as the theory of networks and of self-organising systems suggests, we might develop a mathematics that enables us to carve nature at unforeseen joints. But the new ecological objects, properties and processes that such mathematics define might not be exactly communities or ecosystems or resilience or successions. If we find them, although they might be of little interest to us now (we can’t even say what they are yet), they will be useful to know about and we will become interested. On the other hand, there might not be any such things to find. One half-clever contrivance that long interested ecologists was the niche, a term first coined by C.S.Elton in 1927. In the 19th century the Latin word habitat became a general term of Natural History, used in its floras and faunas to refer to the area, the station or the kind of landscape in which a specimen was found. It is still a common term of folk ecology. Niche is a bit like the ecological heir to habitat—habitat rejigged to produce a useful concept given the new paradigms of evolutionary and ecological biology. Using the concept niche to refer to a set of functional opportunities for (and constraints to) occupation within a community—opportunities and constraints to which an organism might or might not be adapted—ecology has tried to develop an operational partition of the big concept of ecosystem or community down into useful ecological somethings. Conceiving new ecological objects called niches seemed like it might have been just counter-intuitive enough in a certain ingenious way to rescue important and useful attributes of communities. Similar communities in different places often seem to share similar functional niches occupied by similar if unrelated species. In Australian tall forests, marsupials such as possums and koalas seem to occupy something like a warm-blooded arboreal herbivore niche. In South America a similar niche might, I expect, be occupied by species of monkeys. It looks like there might be some general functional pattern here whereby we can predict the functional assembly of communities. Niche theory for example proposed rules of assembly, such as the principle of competitive exclusion: namely, that when two species compete for the same niche, one will eventually exclude the other. (When Jared Diamond proposed community assembly rules in 1975 he included similar precepts: namely that some pairs of species never coexist, either by themselves or as part of a larger combination.) It is debatable whether such a theory should be empirically falsifiable or whether it should be some core principle of the research program of niche theory. It does look like it might be useful for predicting the outcomes of ecological invasions. More often though, I suspect, it is used after the fact to explain them. Lantana is sometimes said to be a successful invader because it out-competed native occupants of the same niche. But just what niche is that? The scrambling-shrubby-birddispersed-colonizer-of-disturbed-moist-forests niche? What about the fact that lantana also competitively excludes trees (which would seem to be occupiers of quite a different niche) or that it coexists with native, scrambling, shrubby, bird-dispersed colonizers of disturbed moist forests like cockspur and giant 151

native raspberry? I feel the urge to just talk about a lantana niche, or better still, just lantana, and leave it at that. As soon as two species look like they might be occupying the same niche, the definition of the particular niche is deemed to be falsified rather than the principle of competitive exclusion. That comes with the whole research program package of niche theory. Despite efforts to define a niche wholly abstracted from any particular species—e.g. as a multidimensional hyperspace of physical and biological variables—pretty soon things get so complex and detailed that you end up defining the particular niche by the particular species. No wonder one of the main debates about niche theory has been about whether a niche could be defined independently of a particular species that might occupy it. Since the niche is conceived like the glove that a set of adaptations fits into, it seems like a way to provide a usefully abstract division of communities based on an important idea of evolutionary theory. Evolutionary theory seemed to provide the clever way of carving up communities into operational units. A community could be seen as something constructed from a set of such functional niches. However, demands for precision in defining the functional parameters of the niche lead back to defining the niche by the species that occupies it. So why not just define the community as a set of organisms in the first place? Well, there is no reason except that by doing so the description crashes back into the particularity that you were trying to avoid in the first place. There are other problems with the theory too. The idea that a community is a system of functional niches making up a working whole looks like a modern descendent of a notion that has persisted throughout the course of natural philosophy and is still strong in popular ecology: the old balance of nature. Nature does nothing in vain, says the Aristotelian precept. As Thomas Browne, the 17th century essayist and natural philosopher, put it: ‘Natura nihil agit frustra, is the only indisputable axiom in Philosophy; there are no Grotesques in nature; nor any thing framed to fill up empty cantons, and unnecessary spaces.’ This is almost a 17th century formulation of niche theory. People like to think that each of the different niches (or the organisms that occupy them) has its allotted place in the design of the whole. This way of thinking has a lot in common with the notion that community succession is analogous to the growth and development of an organism. Something recycles this litter, something else that litter. Insectivores do insectivory, herbivores do herbivory and so on, all working together when and as needed. When ecosystem managers talk about the functionality of rivers or wetlands or forests, projecting their own managerialism onto nature, they are usually taking some encouragement from this old and enduring precept of balance and design. In modern versions of the balance of nature it is typically human destruction that upsets the balance. This kind of thinking conveniently allows humans to do so by preconceiving them as outside nature. With the old habits of nature’s providence and teleology lurking behind quite of lot of conjecture about niches, it is not so surprising that the

152

operational division of a community can end up getting more and more metaphysical, more and more divorced from empirical nature. The immense effort that has gone into formulating some general assembly rules for communitiesparticularly since Jared Diamond published his tantalisingly unsatisfying suggestions in 1975has resembled the search for the philosophers’ stone. Useful certainly, but we still await its evolution like that of alchemy into something as useful as chemistry. Perhaps forever. Yet, even if communities and ecosystems are not well conceived as organized systems, community ecology and systems ecology have their uses. Along with population models, they have provided a modicum of conceptual structure for description and analysis of the functional dimensions and operations of ecosystems. Even if it is only a makeshift for modeling the way an ecosystem is put together, and even if modeling produces weak predictions, some of the predictions that management demands are at least generated. On the other hand, a lot of ecological labour is devoted to fancy techniques of limited usefulness —‘techniques in search of problems,’ Kirkpatrick (294) calls them, citing satellite remote sensing and geographic information systems. Socially, doing such science has satisfied the bureaucratic demand to appear to be managing and conserving ecosystems according to the best standards of scientific society, and it has employed a generation of ecology graduates collecting data, developing models and running them, even while they have consoled themselves with the vision of more data and better models. Much of the time though this kind of science has only been useful for explanations after the fact —explanations based on assumptions that no-one is ever going to be able to put to the test—while the management has proceeded on ground often without much benefit from the science at all. At some stage most ecosystem management has depended upon the little natural histories—or myths—that managers tell themselves. Predictive ecology, or ecosystem or population modelling, cannot say everything about the natural world that we want or need to say (see Kirkpatrick). Descriptions of particular observations seldom fit neatly into known and well-theorised kinds of ecological processes. Just keep a naturalist’s eye on nature and you will be entertained by novelty for life. So natural history lives on not only as observational grist to ecology’s mill, but also as the only discourse that would account for all those complexities that exceed the conceptual reduction. More than any other biological science, ecology has evolved to serve two masters: to be general enough to make predictions, and not to sacrifice relevant particulars. It is not easy. To protect their validity, general claims have to be confined to circumstances so restricted as to verge on particularity (to a particular kind of community in a particular place and time); or hedged with provisos about confidence (we need more data and better models); or so general as to be trivial, or quarantined against empirical falsification deep within a dubious research program (principles of competitive exclusion, or Diamond’s assembly rules). Typically, too much of any particular information that gets sacrificed for the sake of universality turns out to be 153

relevant. Ecology’s function as a reconciliation of natural historical particulars and scientific universality is a dream function. It survives in the attempt to do both, not in the achievement of both. As an artefact, it is just as telling about the human species and about society as it is about its would-be ecological subject matter. Although ecology might like to propose general theories with high predictive power, a lot of ecological papers report research that has collected specific data and crunched the numbers in order to make particular observations about particular species or communities. You might hope it is supplying basic data for the big models, but at best we learn something about particular members of a species in an experimental context, and we can use it to make predictions about other members of the species in a similar context. On the one hand, in its concern with humble details, this is not so different from the everyday work in all sorts of instrumental sciences. The bread and butter of experimental ecology, the kind that graduate students practice and the kind that fills most journals, is testing based on the statistical procedures known as hypothesis testing and analysis of variance: replicated plots, treatments and controls, and crunching data to see what statistically significant conclusions may be drawn (Underwood, 1997). On the other hand, rather than a great advance on natural history, such ecology is just the continuation of natural history’s uncompleted project—which by no means counts for nothing. It is a delightand a useful oneto learn how, for example, slight changes in water depth, salinity and the duration of inundation can determine where cumbungi, giant jointed twig rush, common reed or water ribbons will grow in a swamp. When it comes to communities or ecosystems the predictive power is reduced because we have not got the same effective degree of universality as that which applies to the members of a species in an experimental context. By observing several communities of a kind we might be able to use statistical inference and what we know about particular species to make more or less accurate predictions about what will happen to a particular community if we do such and such to it. When it comes to practice, would-be universality must rely more or less on the rough expectations supplied by models or the generic narratives of natural history. I should say, in an aside on the philosophy of statistics, that the words more or less need not be an embarrassment. They need not be used loosely. The cunning of statistics is that it supplies a way of assessing the validity of claims. How more or less accurate are they? Statistics is not a way of describing some supposed objective randomness of the world. Randomness is, after all, neither absolute nor out there. It is a measure of our subjective incapacity to compute and discern pattern in things; and it is a matter of degree. Observation is necessarily subjective and statistical inference is a way of dealing with the problems of subjectivityagain by multiplying them. It gives a means of subjectively assessing the value of subjective observations of complex events whose randomness consists in their irreducibility to the terms and nous at the observer’s disposal. Sometimes the randomness comes from the errors of 154

measurement, errors in the procedure and machinery of measurement that cannot be eliminated from experience or experiment and that must remain inscrutable to the observer. This is the case in the estimation of a physical constant like the speed of light. In ecology the randomness more often comes from the inscrutability of the objects. By making observations of many objects of a kind we can average them in order to produce results that are more or less repeatable. Most ecological statistics are used to make particular observations with a weak power of generalisation rather than, say, to estimate something as objective as a universal constant. As in the case of the repeatability of empirical observation, statistics makes use of norms. The best known are the importance it places on estimators like mean and variance, and on p-values or significance levels. By these conventions, statistical practice can coordinate the observations of scientific society and compare the likelihood—the more-or-lessness—of the validity of explanations. Powerful explanatory discoveries in science are not everyday. Statistical inference is one way of grinding out claims of at least assessable validity about the things that fascinate our subjectivity even if they exceed its cognitive desire. Statisticians debate these things though. There are schools of thought. That’s why there is philosophy of statistics, and this is only one brief take on it. When all else fails of course, we narrative animals are always ready to draw on experience and the jargon of ecology to confidently cobble together natural histories that explain it all to us anyway. The discussion sections at the end of ecological papers are like a sigh of relief. Conceived initially as a science of the relation of organisms to their environments, ecology and its objects of interest still make their appearances according to the familiar concepts of folk science and folk natural history. In this pool of shared understanding, the biological world is divided according to common human interests handed down by the past. We think of ecology as a modern science, and it is, but it is haunted by interests and concepts that weigh on us with all the weight of their obscure, unreflective past. These interests and concepts refer to things that society has deemed worthy of working on and with, but the history of these concepts is, as I have suggested, one of generations of selection resulting in inherited formsboth interests and conceptsthat have a kind of arbitrary quality. Although their relevance is given to us by our own nature—by our natural and social history—they are not, as it were, natural kinds for themselves. They are the ends of our interests. As such, they are final causes as Aristotle and the philosophers called them, rather than effective causes. As Bacon long ago warned ‘they are clearly more allied to man's own nature than the system of the universe; and from this source they have wonderfully corrupted philosophy' (§48). Ecology’s objects of interests and how we conceive them are adequate when we have nothing else and have to make do; and we have to make do because these have been and remain the very kinds of things that are of particular relevance to us. Ecology’s adequacy then, is an adequacy for certain instrumental purposes and for this reason ecology is an instrumental science—all too instrumental.

155

In the hurly burly of instrumental endeavour, ecology has to rely on rough and ready translation between the functional descriptions of its quite different and often-irreconcilable kinds of objects of interest. In the process it can succumb to confusion of what is functional for human interests and what is functional for other ecological objects. In its more naïve pop ecology moments it can assume that certain ecological objects, e.g. other organisms or natural ecosystems, have human interests at heart. Even scientific ecology runs the risk of assuming such an abstract, providential kind instrumentalism that it can think of itself as the antithesis of an instrumental science, as the purest and most natural of the natural sciences.

Ecology, pure and applied.

The simplest reality we can come to terms with is that people who inhabit our study landscape and own the fragments we study are the most powerful force acting upon them, yet we tend to ignore them in favor of examining ‘natural’ forces such as edges, climate, and so forth. —Francis Crome, 1997 As well as its unreconciled ambition to be both an historical and universal science, ecology has another symptom of schizophrenia. Despite holistic aspirations, it cherishes the thought of a nature without humans. Because of holistic aspirations, it nurses a fascination for a nature in which humans are insignificant. Of course, as an instrumental science it is anxious to develop efficient technical processes: it sees the advantage in observing things in situations from which all but specific experimental treatments have been excluded. Undertaking some defined and repeatable action on the objects of interest and then letting them behave themselves as they naturally would is a paradigm of efficient practice. All of the physical sciences just want to get a look at nature behaving naturally, without humans blundering in and confounding things. Even the social sciences betray a hankering for this. Ecology though, has evolved as a modern science just when all too much earthly nature is showing the ugly symptoms of its abuse at the hands of humans. A first response has been to urge that whatever remains of undamaged nature be left well alone. This nature, protected from human meddling, has taken on a special place in modern sensibilitythe nature, which in existing for itself, has become the very image of nature. This sensibility doubtless touches those inveterate nature lovers, the ecologists, who are busy making a living out of doing science on the object of their desires. Aesthetic impulses resonate with those of scientific society, and inherited scientific and aesthetic commitments to 156

extra-human nature persist as a kind of second nature in ecological practice. So ecology has a habit of studying so called natural ecosystems rather than human ones. It inventories species for the ecological communities it studies, seldom, if ever, listing Homo sapiens, even when H. sapiens is the most significant population affecting the community. Sometimes a kind of theodicy lurks in ecology: nature’s providence is assumed; no need to justify its ways. Although instrumental researchers who are looking for management procedures might try to eliminate confounding human intentions from their ecological subject matter, nature itself could well hijack their research with its own wilfulness and autonomy. Restoration ecologists have been known to have their doubts about testing the efficacy of their methods: whatever their theories, whatever their experimental treatments, nature’s self generating capacity may well confound things and ‘reduce the value of restoration as a crucial test of understanding' (Jordan et al, 16; see also Bradshaw, 28). Nature may well take over and do its own thing—by definition the right thing—making all human efforts ill conceived. Given a metaphysical commitment to the primacy of extra-human nature, perhaps it is a little scandalous to suggest that ecology is merely an instrumental science. Even if such a theodicy, the instrumental quietism that attends it, and the rigorous dualism of humans and nature that feeds them both, are ecologically untenable, it is still a bit demeaning to call ecology an instrumental science. In common sense, an instrumental science is an applied science and contrasted with pure science. It is a commonplace in scientific society to say that pure research is ultimately more useful than applied research. Pure science is supposed to discover how things work in themselves or in general. Like all platitudes its truth is worn as sheep’s clothing for falsehood. It promises the power of universals, even if in ecology the details have a nasty habit of getting in the way. True or not, it persists because scientists want to direct their own research to their own interests; because the critique of market or political directives needs a ready-made argumentespecially one that can cite usefulness; because, if a science is worth doing then like anything worth doing it should be worth doing for its own sake; and because, as the pure form of a science, it just must reveal the most profound findings. It has its analogue in artistic society in the critique of art that is not for art’s sake. Surely ecology is worthy of the dignity of a pure science. Surely ecology should be describing and explaining how nature works rather than meddling and manipulating it. Surely it has got to get the former right before it can even contemplate the risky business of the latter. If only it could be a science purified to untrammelled observations of natural history and with a body of theory synthesised from sublime observation, brilliant thought experiments and dazzling mathematics. Or if it cant quite do things that way, it could settle for some big time modelling, or for the bread and butter of hypothesis testing and analysis of variance. Anyway and meanwhile development of applications and management procedures is for the mere technicians of applied ecology. Given that ecology has traditionally had such a peculiar fascination with the extra157

human, it would be more demeaning for it than for any other science if, after all, it were really the most beholden of the sciences to arbitrary or impure human interests. Surely ecology has always been the purest, the most pristine, and the most disinterested of the sciences, just as its principal object of study has always properly been pure, pristine nature. When the idea of a little applied ecology is entertained, in order to solve some pressing ecological problem, there is an unreflected desire for technologies that are purely, authentically ‘ecological’: water treatment technologies made of real ecological objects like reed and sedge communities rather than artificial chemicals or physical filters; cropping systems based on natural community succession rather than tillage or herbicides or genetic engineering; rainforest restoration that uses foliage canopy cover; biological control of pests or ecologically ‘integrated’ pest management rather than chemical pesticides; riverbank stabilisation by planting trees and rushes rather than construction engineering. To imagine and desire that ecological management technologies, of all technologies, should be the most authentically ecological might seem like a case of confounding ends and means, and of being confused about ecology’s extra-human purism. After all chemicals, genes, physical objects are all, in their own ways, ecological. In popular culture the great technological ask of applied ecology is to use authentic nature to save the environment. This is when the idea of big applied ecology is entertained. Nature is advertised as the best tool we have for regulating and safeguarding human habitat. All that biodiversity out there saves us from stuffing up the planet. It keeps farms and cities viable. When things get this big though, and the story becomes TV infotainment, ends and means really get confused. Forests, they say, are the lungs of the earth, but when a researcher finds that a rainforest is a net producer of greenhouse gasses this becomes the story: Rainforest Causing Global Warming! Things reach such a state, only because we have become inured to selling rainforest as a tool of applied ecology. We forget that, whether or not it is a means, rainforest is more importantly an end. Nevertheless perhaps an instrumental ecology does suggest that sometimes the apparently more ecological means might be, in the long run, and for wisely conceived ends, more effective. Provided we have not deluded ourselves about our goals, this looks like a question for ecological research, that is, it would be a matter of risking a bit of applied ecology in order to find out the answer. Ecology may be an instrumental science, but for what purpose? Management, of course. In a managerial age, management is just the word we have for everything worth doing. It is also just the word for what we do to everything else when we let it do its own thing. It makes things sound busy, efficient, useful and above all not unmanaged. Everything else is just dreaming. Ecological management could stand for all sorts of things in all sorts of environments. It could just as easily refer to regulating the air conditioning in a skyscraper or the genes in a crop. However ecology has cultivated a particular set of interests in certain natural objects. Agriculture can be conceived as a kind 158

of applied ecology. Cropping, say, is a matter of manipulating a community succession under strictly controlled conditions. We might conceive the prehistory of ecology in agricultural terms—just as Darwin used pigeon breeding as an introduction to the idea of natural selection—but modern ecology has an almost defining interest in objects and processes that deliberately distinguish it from the starker instrumentalism and simplifications of agriculture. It has tied one instrumental hand behind its back by not being contented with such strict control as would allow, say, a crop—a population that is also effectively a single species community—to occupy a central place in its research program. That’s agricultural science. Ecology, having become the scientific vehicle of modernity’s incorrigible interest in the biological riches bequeathed it by natural history—the things beyond the pale of agriculture and industry—got the job of finding and solving the problems that dog and diminish those riches. Ecology is a shallow science, its objects so intractable to theory, because its subject matter is so deep, so historically deep. Conserving and restoring these biological riches, so long in the making, has a peculiar historical interest for humans, particularly here in postcolonial Australia. So many Australian ecosystems, which are the result of long and gradual evolution complete with a resident human population for the last 40,000 years, now degrade under the new dispensation of globalized, industrial culture. If we start to think too generally about ecology we start to question whether this long evolved nature should have a special significance for applied ecology, and whether yesterdays GM crop, say, should not be just as much its subject matter. Or whether conservation and restoration ecology should lead to any more important reflections on the philosophy of ecology than, say, agricultural ecology. Or whether conservation and restoration ecology should not be just one example among many of applied ecology, with no special claim to being the epitome of applied ecology. Yet once we start to doubt the prestige of certain ecological subject matter, I suspect that we are starting to think too generally about ecology. Like the natural heritage that most interests it, and because that natural heritage is what most interests it, the science of ecology has an historical particularity that limits philosophy’s power to generalize about it. Of course agricultural systems and air-conditioned buildings are environmental issues and fit subjects for applied ecology. Yet even if the preeminence of conservation and restoration ecology over the applied ecology of agricultural systems or air-conditioned buildings were in doubt, the specific historical problem of defining the proper subject matter of ecology, and the consequently arbitrary domain of its subject matter, would still limit the power to generalize about ecology. Not only is ecology’s subject matter rendered intractable by its historical content, ecology’s constitution as a science is steeped in a specific historical context and therefore as the subject matter of philosophy, ecology itself demands reflection that registers its historical character. This is because of ecology’s special historical place in the critique of instrumental reason. Too much science has got away with pleading abstract 159

pragmatism. It has validated its claims simply by citing that some practice works best. It wears the blinkers of specialization and assumes that it need not be critical about concepts like ends and best and useful. Ecology can’t do this. Nor can it shun instrumentalism or pragmatism. The opposite in fact. It can only recognize ecology’s peculiar instrumental predicament, and wonder at its constitutional shallowness. Ecology developed as a science around a specific research project: to be instrumental reason’s own means of redressing the environmental problems it has created, problems seemingly inherent in its attempted mastery of nature. Right back when he was spelling out the ways and means of instrumental reason, Bacon had to speak in a paradox about it. ‘Nature,’ he said, ‘is only to be commanded by obeying her' (§129). There are quite a few old standards in critical environmental philosophy. One is the critique of Francis Bacon’s environmental legacy. All it takes is couple of quotes from Bacon’s Novum Organum. Bacon gets the blame for science and science gets the blame for this mess the planet is in. It is rivaled in frequency only by the critique of the Bible’s declaration of the human right to mastery of nature. Even one of my favorite writers on nature tries it. A Long Walk in the Australian Bush is a walking meditation on the nature of southwestern Australia. William Lines and a comrade take a long walk along the Bibbaluk track and it turns out to be a road narrative of infamy and shame, a journey through country trashed by cruel use and passionless neglect. Whether contemplating the managers of CALM (the Orwellian name for the Western Australian department of Conservation And Land Management) or bored, supercilious tourists, Lines can reveal what is truly strange and astonishing in common human behaviour. Among his many reflections though there is the following narrative: Scientific narratives about the world and our place in it are usually based on premises first articulated by the Englishman Francis Bacon (1561-1626). Bacon rejected Aristotle’s advice that we look on the physical world with wonder, awe and reverence. (154-5) God knows Lines had cause for complaint and his essay delves into the occasional delights of diatribe. But the story about Bacon is as throwaway as the litter of consumerism that the walkers find along their way. Lines knows how all those advertisements for the existence of choice in consumer society take place against an unconscious society of what are already relentlessly and inescapably chosen forms of life. The same unfreedom haunts us when it comes to the reproduction and consumption of ideas. Rather than leading inquiry through problems, stories like the Bacon yarn are well adapted to the task of gratifying an unreflected habit of thought, a wild desire for handy historical explanation. They use us for their survival and reproduction. Sure, Bacon can be quoted saying things like: ‘Let mankind regain their rights over nature, assigned to them by the gift of God, and obtain that power whose exercise will 160

be governed by right reason and true religion' (Novum Organum §129). He can also be quoted saying that ‘nature is only subdued by submission' (§3). Consider this: In short, we may reply decisively to those who despise any part of natural history as being vulgar, mean, or subtle and useless in its origin, in the words of a poor woman to a haughty prince who had rejected her petition, as unworthy and beneath the dignity of his majesty: ‘then cease to reign;’ for it is quite certain that the empire of nature can neither be obtained nor administered by one who refuses to pay attention to such matters as being poor and too minute. (§121) This is not a rejection of physical wonders. It is a defence of the useless minutiae of nature, the mere particulars ignored by grand universal vision. And the poor woman’s reference to the desire to obtain and administer says as much about the blind ambitions of modern instrumentalism as of haughty princes. Applied in ecological science, Bacon’s arguments could be a critique of those excuses for technocratic exploitation that presume to dogmatize on nature, concealing complexities with convenient abstractions. They who have presumed to dogmatize on Nature, as on some wellinvestigated subject, either from self-conceit or arrogance, and in the professorial style, have inflicted the greatest injury on philosophy and learning. [Bacon is referring to the devotees of Aristotle here, generations of natural philosophers dazzled not only, understandably, by the brilliance of Aristotle's writing, but, perniciously, by the sheer authority of the legacy that had come to bear his name.] For they have tended to stifle and interrupt inquiry exactly in proportion as they have prevailed in bringing others to their opinion: and their own activity has not counterbalanced the mischief they have occasioned by corrupting and destroying that of others. (Preface)

Of course, to claim that Bacon’s argument is a critique of technocratic ignorance is anachronistic, just as the standard attack on Bacon is. Actions and deeds, including written documents, survive and reproduce in different times by using the same inherited features in different ways with different meanings. Socalled great works, the ones that survive the judgement of history, are able to address the desire for meaning over and over again. The actual intentions, the real meaning of the authors, often belong to that impossible romance goal of historicismthe past as it actually was. History can never do better than find the past as documents that survive or are reproduced in the present. ‘Every image of the past that is not recognised by the present as one of its concerns threatens to disappear irretrievably' (Benjamin, 1970). Because it is the fate of historical objects to face the problem of persisting through or reproducing 161

themselves in every age, it is not just the predicament of historical inquiry, but its methodological principle, to reveal the meaning of old ideas by shedding the light of the most recent thought on them. At best history can be a satire quoting documents selected by the ravages of time. The applied ecology of restoration and conservation develops the paradox that Bacon appreciated in instrumental reason to its nicest conclusions. Only a violent dualism of nature and humans, and an absolute and dogmatic critique of instrumental reason could lead to ecological quietism. Inherent in ecology’s utterly instrumental predicament, the paradox injects ambiguity not only into the traditional problem of instrumental science—namely into the question of efficacy of means—but into the formulation of wise ends. Useless objects— scrub, wilderness, swamp, heath, Lewin’s honeyeaters—have come to be conceived both as ends and useful means. The deeper the historical threads woven into nature’s fabric, the more value ecology suspects it of, whether as an end or a means of instrumental ecology. Modern societies, in their own ways, conserve or restore whatever nature they regret having lost or would regret having lost, inventing all sorts of utilitarian rationalizations for doing it. You’d be forgiven for thinking it was really an affair of the heart, and almost a guilty one—for which ecology is the post hoc rationalization. Blissful contemplation of nature and ecological observation almost become one: watching the little thornbill nabbing the aphid, the echidna with its tongue in the termite track, two rearing black snakes rivalling one another in a dance, the goanna swallowing the fledgling dove, the osprey lifting the mullet over the river bank, the little fantail feeding the fat cuckoo are all as ecological as they are aesthetic observations. All too happy, such a coincidence smells suspiciously utopian to managerialism’s long cultivated masochisma habit developed by can-do functionalism for cutting to the chase, i.e. to the product. The result is that ecology as an instrumental science is apt to misconstrue its ends. It has a pinched notion of function. Sure, it can see a point in thornbills, or rather in insectivore management, but selling the ecosystem function of teams of thornbills for agriculturethat would only happen in a joke about wide-eyed of organic gardeners. At best, practical farmers or international agribusiness might glance at an article about scientists somewhere overseas caging wrens in hydroponic greenhouses. Otherwise it is about as silly as leasing echidnas for household termite control or harnessing black snakes to our chariots. Functionalist management becomes so intent on not losing the plot, that it loses sight of its ends. They just don’t look enough like product. However, to use thornbills and echidnas for something else that’s supposedly more important than they are is not the primary application of this ecology. Ecology is for the pleasure of thornbills, echidnas, black snakes, goannas, pigeons, ospreys, mullets, fantails and cuckoos. To feel OK about this, management has had to label them biodiversity. It makes them sound more like product or heritage or useful. Restoration ecology is sometimes suspected of being in cahoots with exploitation. Its instrumental intentions are advertised as successes and used to 162

license ecological destruction. Afterwards we can put Humpty Dumpty back together again. When he was Deputy Prime Minister, Doug Anthony said that Fraser Island could be sand-mined once the community becomes more informed and enlightened as to what reclamation work is being carried out by mining companies. Such suggestions have flushed elaborate defences out of environmental ethicists. Roger Elliot (76-88) argued that restoration is faking nature. It is inauthentic like a faked painting. There is no need for metaphysics though. Just the empirical will do. Cheap restoration ecology is not that good. Like I said, ecology is shallow to start with. And the words in the Doug Anthony type line are even cheaper than the restoration they advertise. You only have to consider the time and the investment of natural history required to build the wealth of an ecosystem to see that restoration ecology is no excuse for destruction. Natural history is deep and time is money. If you want good restoration you will have to spend more time and money than the mineral sand is worth. And all the volunteers in the world have got enough to do. Sure you can rebuild some things quicker than others. An old growth forest might take 300 years. A heath might take 20—if you are really good and lucky. And Roger Elliot will be calling it fake anyway. You might as well destroy and rebuild Opera Houses or break legs and reset them—and, of course, go without opera or walking while you are doing it. Restoration begins with conservation. In conservation ecology the critique of instrumental reason is not so poignant with paradox as it is in restoration ecology. Yet although conservation looks like it leaves all instrumental meddling to ecological restoration, distinctions between conservation and restoration ecology are not so fundamental. It’s all management anyway. Whether it is busy making reserves or restoring them, ecological conservation can hardly sit back and pride itself on being the absolute negation of instrumental intervention. How else to manage nature but like engineers of nature? You keep an eye on it to see that it works, or you work on it until it works. The restoration engineers have a machine to tinker with and they learn about it by tinkering. An ecosystem in need of restoration or management is like a machine that is not workingif it is permissible to use this misleading metaphor about an ecosystem working. Many have done so. Many have said it is like a broken clock. You try somethingclean a connection, fix a spring, re-align a gearand see what happens. Only nature is not a machine for doing things. It is a machine for doing a hell of a lot of nothingingeniously, uselessly, with absurd flurry, with appalling waste, with dreadful efficiency, to no endand in doing so it manages, fiendishly, to appear as though it works, as though it is busy doing something and it has all been put together by some ingenious designer, as though it has its climax and unity, perfect, balanced and complete. Wonderful accident, beautiful illusion, sublime and ridiculous. You try something: you kill the weeds, you burn the place, you flood it, you plant something, and you wait and see what happens; and then you try something else, you kill the feral animals, you bulldoze the place, you salt it, you treat it with kid gloves; or you try the same thing again; and again; and again. Or you 163

try one thing after another after another after another. Or maybe it is more like weaving—textile engineering or handicraft—and you find that you can gently, patiently knit its damaged fabric together. Or you find that you will kill it with kindness. Or you find that you must violently overthrow the damaged order. Or you find that you only damage it with cruel blows. As many have said, here is the raw material of ecological science (Jordan et al). We learn about ecological objects and processes by working on them. Time and again environmentalists resort to saying that what we need before we do this or that is more research. When it comes to restoration though, the only way to do research is to do a bit of this or that and see if it works. Here and now, ecology is primarily conservation and restoration ecology. And ecological restoration is the great laboratory for ecology. Because of its peculiar interest in objects so complicated by their history, ecology can’t avoid the historical complexities of its subject matter. Natural history has its role in formulating both the end and means of restoration and conservation. Show a bunch of naturalists and ecologists a patch of bush and they will start running a speculative history on what it might once have been, how it got to be the way it is now, and what is likely to become of it. No wonder. Humans are animals who, thanks to their own natural history, are peculiarly adept, narrative animals. It is our habit to divide the firmament of time into beginnings, middles and ends, befores and afters, causes and effects, thereby to make sense of it and help us plot our courses of action. The term natural history originally referred to inquiry into natureto what has also been called both natural philosophy and natural science. It is still sometimes used to refer to the study of organisms in their natural habitat too, but with the increasing differentiation of evolutionary and ecological science from the old concerns of the naturalist, the term natural history now has to designate a slightly different, less formal or rigorous kind of ecological discourse, a certain kind of narrative knowledge of naturethe kind that a naturalist, a restorer or a scientist has by dint of long experience rather than by theoretical hypothesis, rigorous observation, and statistical inference. Natural histories see patterns in ecological processes, but usually they are patterns somewhat casually observed. Humans are a little too fond of the good story, and always ready to cobble events together according to any handy rationale. The chronological and causal patterns of our natural histories are inveterately unreliable. If it’s not our bad storytelling habits, which may at least be made subject to the checks of empirical norms of observation, it is the unpredictable subject matter itself. When we use natural histories to plot the courses of action we undertake when working on nature, no wonder we have to be prepared for things to happen in more or less unexpected ways. Then we have to include these more or less unexpected events in our continuing natural history of a particular community. This is why restoration ecology often relies on what is called adaptive management. You try something and then, depending upon what happens afterwards, you then repeat what you have done or try something else. You keep building on what you have, a principle that implies 164

that you start where you already have something to start with. The fact that restoration ecology is not entirely unsuccessful shows that we have descriptions of ecological processes that are adequate enough for the purposes of restoration. The fact that we have to follow a procedure of adaptive management implies that our predictions about what will follow from a particular management action may be fairly weak but not hopelessly inadequate. Adaptive management follows from Bacon’s maxim about commanding nature only by obeying it. With so many different kinds of communities and every community different in its own way, what rules are there to obey? Contingency rules but there are some patterns. Experimental ecology beavers away to formulate some; modeling runs some scenarios in the hope of predicting some outcomes; natural history adds its genres; and adaptive management supplies what can only be called experience. Adaptive management is designed for contingency. It lets the bush teach us its rules, or break them. It lets the bush decide. If such and such obtains, try this. Otherwise try that. See what happens and move to the next operation in the algorithm. Funny: the first great ecological theory was an algorithmic one: natural selection. Ecological modeling is already doing ecology a bit like this. However the models are mostly too slow for the practice and too slow in feeding their predictions or enough predictions back into restoration practice, which still just has to carry on by experience and the seat of the pants. Adaptive management almost runs its own model for itself, there on the ground (or in the water) with the actual stuff of nature itself. Somehow ecology has to do science and mathematics that can make good such a predicament. That sounds like it is half exhortation, half announcement, half proclamation, half manifesto, half wishful thinking—which, suspiciously, adds up to two and a half statements in one. Just the kind of philosophy of science that science usually ignores. Last minute conservation and adaptive management based on narrative experience might not fully live up to the great historical destiny of ecology: to rescue the future of nature. According to Peters (10) this is the real test for ecology as a science. ‘The problems that ecology should solve are not being solved. They are worsening, growing more imminent, more monstrous.’ This more than anything shows ecology’s weakness as a science. In its greatest task it seems ecology’s diffidence about the humans in its study landscape could be its fatal flaw. If there were such a thing as social will, failure to solve ecological problems could be attributed to the lack of social will for solving them. Outside ecological society most ecological problems are not registered as at all pressing. Inside ecological society, apart from the purist and quietist distaste for applied ecology, much more time is spent making and responding to speech, print and graphic forms of culturethese matters are more pressingthan on the actual work of ecological restoration and management, so the problems grow and become more difficult to solve. 165

Perhaps ecology should paraphrase and take to heart Karl Marx: ecologists have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the point however is to change it. If its instrumental failure demonstrates ecology’s weakness as a science, then the problem for ecology is not just one of devising techniques of restoration; it is one of devising techniques that will solve the social problems that thwart ecological restoration. However this would demand that ecology treat society as one of its most ecologically significant objects, that it see itself as a social as well as a physical science; and that it solve formidable problems of sociology, both political and epistemological. Ecology would have to get shallower and therefore harder. In society as in nature massive contingency rules, but some patterns emerge. In society it might seem that people are free to change themselves and to change cultural forms, but to some extent the pattern that emerges in society is testimony to these things being less than amenable to freedom and change, and more like forces of nature. Again the processes look more algorithmic than like the stuff of big decisions, leadership or one fell swoop. And even if ecological restoration that worked on society as well as nature were not suspected of being social engineering, or even, in managerial parlance, managing cultural change, it would still be quite extraordinary. No other science has to do such a thing—that is flout the circumscription of its proper subject matter. Physics, chemistry, even medical biology do not have to, nor could they, solve sociological problems. Sociology itself can’t solve them. All this is politics and public policy. Like any physical science, ecology has a constitutional incapacity to think about the social character of both the objects it studies and of itself as a discipline. By a kind of catch 22, ecology at its shallowest is constitutionally a thoroughly instrumental science yet it is also constitutionally incapable of being instrumental in the solution of its most important practical problems.

166

11 Out-there-in-the-Community Ecology, or Natural Resource Managerialism The contemporary culture of ecosystem management and Landcare (Warning! The following paragraphs contain language that may offend.)

Expect from me no word of my own. —Karl Kraus, Dicta and Contradicta

Landcare, Bushcare, Wetlandcare, Coastcare, Dunecare, Rivercare, Caring for Country. Who cares? The neatest, correct answer is the community. Whatever that might be. If the community did not exist, repeated references to it would have given it its own kind of reality: it is out there, people are out there in it, and whether you are out there in it or in here pointing out at it, you can’t ignore it. Neither can ecologists. It’s a fact of nature, like climate. Environmental management sometimes gets divided into two types: the lock-it-up kind and the out-there-in-the-community kind. In Australia at least. The former builds a system of national parks, public reserves and environmental law. In doing so it bureaucratizes nature. It might also, to some extent, be defying the ideology of deregulation and the privatization of public assets, as if it were the last bastionor consolationof socialism. I might add that locking it up is a misleading term for freeing nature up from abuse and degradation. Although its success has been meager, it is the best Australian environmentalism has managed to do. It is still an uncompleted project. The out-there-in-the-community kind (the OTITC kind) manages environmental issues outside the state nature reserve system, the issues impacting on farms and other private land, and at various community spaces like riverbanks, urban parkland, beaches and roadsidesplaces where stakeholders decide they just have to do something about the state of things, places where the state can’t or won’t or doesn’t want to, or where it is not wanted, the places all those cares were set up to care for. With government assistance, and some careful naming, branding, packaging, networking and selling ecosystem services, Landcare et al have come to denote the official form of community in environmental bureaucracy, a top-down promotion of the bottom up, or as they say, linking

167

top-down processes with grass roots concerns to achieve positive outcomes. It’s all about communication. It is a bureaucratization of nature too, proceeding through a piecemeal bureaucratization of this thing called community. (Of course the word is not bureaucratization it’s management.) Obviously, this is a division too simplistic to be trusted. Perhaps the lock it up kind is mainly conservation and, the OTITC kind is mainly restoration ecology, or natural resource management. Perhaps the former is more professional and more a matter of state conservation agencies and environmentalist politics, the latter more dependant upon volunteerism, farmers and the community. Rough divisions, rough alignments, dot point ways to explain the world. Whether one or the other of the two kinds of environmentalism is more important, urgent, feelgood, sexy, radical, cool, conservative, green, leftwing, rightwing, feral, family-oriented, selfish, community-minded, hands-on, pragmatic, technically difficult, scientific, worthy or heroic is not my concern. Nor is getting the balance right. That is the job of OTITC environmental bureaucracy: to move on from the well-known social antagonisms of ecological politics. It is the constitutional principle around which its managerialism is organized, as a pearl is organized around a grain of sand or pus around a splinter. Before I go further I had better comment on the ownership of the words I have been using. The following is a list of suspect terms used so far in these paragraphs: caring, the community, out there, lock-it-up, issues, impacting, spaces, stakeholders, branding, packaging, networking, selling, ecosystem services linking, processes, grass-roots, positive, outcomes, communication, biodiversity, management, natural resource management, feelgood, sexy, family-oriented, community-minded, hands-on, getting the balance right, move on and ownership. There may be more. They’re not mine. I try to avoid using themespecially when they lurk in certain much-practiced phrasesbut often I find them using me (and others) anyway for their own propagation. Environmental managers become quite lackadaisical. They never wear protective clothing when they handle words like these. It’s an OH&S (occupational health and safety) issue. They only seem to glove up to draw scare quotes around words like nature and natural. Irony, italics or scare quotes are like condoms: they don’t always work and they are a bit of an encumbrance. Amongst other things, these words, like mucous, manage the irritations in the system of OTITC ecology, soothing it and clogging it up. Grumbling about the abuse of language has become a cliché. Certainly since Orwell’s essay on politics and language, it has become a standard genre of diatribe indulging its own indignant melancholy. One of its own abuses of language has been to proclaim and lament the decline of the language. That’s one of Orwell’s—what he would have called inflated style or pretentious diction or maybe dying metaphor. As Orwell said, we all do it, if only because, as a great tradition in the philosophy of language has concluded, language speaks us rather than the other way round. For having been so often repeated, the complaint about the abuse of language now needs to be rethought in order 168

to be thought at all. Otherwise a writer can use it as a tool for selfaggrandizement, concealed ad hominem arguments, revenge for being ignored or harshly judged, or the idle indulgence of offended sensibility. That is, to abuse it. Repeated formulations, excused by some as efficient communication, cast their referential moorings once redundancy makes them needless of interpretation, and imperceptibly they undergo semantic drift, foregoing any function of incisive observation while still pretending to it. They are adapted to the trivial demands of topicality and immediate conversation. Clichés and platitudes are summoned without effort to fill the void of conversation or the space on a page. Especially when combined in vague combinations, they pad the differences between interlocutors with the loose packing of ambiguity. Once combined in incomprehensible or inconsistent formulations, bored distraction or infinite logical possibility forestalls disagreement. Among other functions, use of the lingo is a membership card that gets you in the club. Once inside, many thoughts are prescribed; original thoughts are proscribed. The danger for anyone who tries to think and write what is not already predigested is that their ideas cannot infiltrate, let alone nourish the culture they want to address, or it gets them into trouble. The culture is self-perpetuating. In the presence of repeated stimulus, sensitivity to deceptions or mistakes becomes dulled; misapprehensions become received wisdom; not only facts but also mistakes become norms. Now. Let me cite a brief description of out-there-in-the-community ecology based on a scientist’s field observations. The observations were apparently made at various sitessteering committees, public meetings, workshops, forums, seminars, field days, occasionally perhaps the sanctified elsewhere of the coalfaceand they are worthy of an ecologist’s wit and attention for being populated by the following species: representatives of local and state government agencies, non-government organizations, business and community groups, environmental managers, scientists, stakeholders, community leaders, landowners, farmers, locals, indigenous representatives, mums and dads, meeting hounds, spanner throwers, revelers, warriors, obfuscators and, of course, ordinary people from OTITC. (I have augmented this species list the better to indicate the biodiversity of these gatherings): In among this remarkable and almost bewildering arsenal of social interaction I was hoping to find advice about how I could effectively assess the relative impacts and hence importance of multiple environmental pressures in priority setting exercises involving a range of government, community and scientific stakeholders. I found the strong-willed and non-compromising position adopted by ‘warriors’ perplexing. But it was not the warriors who really concerned me. My bigger concern was the evident distance between local communities, local governmental officials and scientists. [My italics]

169

Although this follows a witty introduction, that first sentence gives the reader’s mind nothing but encouragement to wander off. Not because it is too longit’s notnor long-winded. Anyway, there is such a thing as a deep breath, and a concept that is worth a long sentence. That final phrase, beginning with about, is probably incomprehensible. Perhaps the sentence means something like I wanted to know how to work out the importance of different environmental pressures for different people in different places. It is a case of a scientist stooping to write prose like an envirocrat, perhaps stooping to conquer. It is the generic style of natural resource management, a culture that shares its stylistic and intellectual features with other forms of contemporary managerialism. Despite the use of I, the prose is anonymous because it is the system itself speaking. An envirocrat like me has to read far too much of this sort of stuff, and in order not to write it has to go to lengths that are unlikely to prove worth the effort. Not to talk this talk is to risk incomprehension, pity or contempt. If you aspire to being an environmental communicator it will be your stock in trade. Since it is merely incomprehensible in the conventional manner, everyone will understand it without anyone having to think. This particular sentence marks the point where an amusing and to that extent a discerning paper gets stuck in prescribed thought, or stuck in prescribed unclarity of thought, the permutations of the permitted phrases only allowing so many comprehensible sentences. Breaking that long phrase up would force clarification, but clarity would have revealed trivial or redundant ideas, and the avoidance of such a revelation is a major function of the phrase. From here on the article reads like most other priority setting exercises, assessment and vision reports, opinion pieces and mission statements circulating in the envirocratic nebula. Envirocrats are of course common at the kinds of meeting being described. The article refers to the genus under two speciesgovernment officials and environmental managersand makes it clear that the author is a scientist and belongs to neither. The managers, the article complains, ‘have a stronger say in environmental decision making’ at such meetings than ‘local communities’ or ‘scientists’. The scientist might like to keep a scientific distance from the environmental management culture, but this description can’t help but sound like yet another self-description of envirocratic society. Such is the gravity of the managerial system. It absorbs descriptions of itself into its own system and into its own generic styles, whatever the professed profession of the author. The Wentworth Group report—a recent authoritative overview—is an envirocratic not a scientific document. Even if its authors thought of themselves as professional scientists they managed to promote themselves to honorary or de facto environmental technocrats. They managed to say little that was of other than envirocratic interest. Documents that succeed in belonging to another system, the scientific one say, are, for their troubles, seldom going to have as much say in environmental bureaucracy. They are too technical. Talking the managerial talk is one of the things you have to do to have more say, although the trouble is, if you can only get away with saying what is not worth saying, 170

it’s difficult to say what having more say is worth. It is these systemic gravitational forces that lead to that evident distance between managers, scientists and people OTITC. Ecologically, it could hardly be otherwise. It follows from the predictable response of managers, scientists or people OTITC to the most immediate pressures of their respective social environments. The internal social pressures in each of their working worlds are more urgent than those exerted by the other groups. This may be so obvious it goes without saying. Among ecological technocrats and ecologists it also goes unsaid because it seems like social science, not environmental management or ecology. Outside social science it does not have the habitat of its own social system so it is discarded into a kind of social unconscious. In order to achieve currency, any would-be envirocratic communication, including a scientist’s critique, has to be understood, accepted, and reproduced by natural resource managers. Creativity seldom extends beyond traditional genres such as a blueprint, a restructure, a program rejig, a vision statement or some obligatory new acronyms to advertise innovation and product differentiation. In most cases of course ideas will be reproductions rather than original insights. Already-reproduced ideas are thereby proven in their reproducibility—a feature that, despite the prestige and because of the difficulty of innovative science, is also important in the everyday scientific world. In either system, pretty much everyone is communicating in the same language and communicating much the same things most of the time. It is, as they say, all about communication. No wonder managerial language thrives. Since locals have one another, government officials have officialdom, managers have their networks, and scientists have their colleagues and the institutions of empirical science as their main environmental pressures, it would be perplexing indeed if the members of any of these different social systems, or the systems as such, did any more than just bump up against one another and register one another as irritations or minor perturbations. They are forces of nature. With all of its internal communications whirling around in their busy constellation the natural resource management system is characterized by its own inertia, but seen from afar it gradually changes. The bureaucratization of nature has evolved through many stages. Typically a new stage evolves because it can thrive in new circumstances where previous stages demonstrate their inadequacies. Thus the national parks systems evolved because there was a social niche for a new kind of reserved nature, a nature whose resources were not simply timber or water or soil, but wildlife, indigenous flora and fauna, biodiversity, even, by a suspicious blurring of the nature/culture divide, indigenous cultural heritage. The older natural resource bureaucracies now manage a lot of country clapped out by agriculture and forestry. So although compromised by their historical role in its degradation, they have inherited a role managing ecological restoration. National parks services persist as agents of conservation ecology and have dabbled more in restoration ecology only as they have been handed degraded country from their bureaucratic ancestors, as more of it has been found worthy of locking up. Greens, who have fought long 171

and hard to lock up nature, still guard the separation of these bureaucratic powers, wary of combining conservation with resource management and thereby handing back what conservation ecology has managed with so much effort to salt away. Landcare evolved because it was adapted to top-down and bottom up pressures. Small-l landcare was happening already in the 1970s and 80s. Conservation volunteers, landholders, farmers and peripheral government projects where doing ecological conservation & restoration. Big-L Landcare was a badged political contrivance devised to reconcile ecological conservation and restoration with private farming and agribusiness. It was about communication and working in partnership with the community. It was adapted to the political antagonisms and the adversarialism OTITC, and designed to take advantage of the private motives of individual and the public culture of volunteerism by giving financial assistance. Win win. Because evolving environmental law had burdened national park and state natural resource managers with the task of policing compliance, they were not well adapted for sidestepping the antagonisms OTITC. There are all sorts of rationales offered for why park rangers get saddled with uniforms—tradition, OH&S, they look smart, they look robust, they save workers’ clothing costs, they look uniform, they badge employees, they signify a certain level of officialdom, and most important in this context, they make staff look like friendly nature police. Environmental law is seldom policed by real police. It’s not like real law. Non-compliance has been a de facto right of freehold title and an Australian way of life ever since the Rum Corps grabbed development acres of prime Sydney real estate. The law has been feeble and prosecution for noncompliance has been half-hearted. Regulators and nature police struggle in OTITC ecology. Instead of conservation, their main effect has been to maintain that ‘evident distance’ between the bureaucracy and OTITC, and this has hampered conservation and restoration on private land. Not only landholders intent upon ecological degradation, but also those planning restoration try by fair means or foul to avoid getting obstructed in the envirocratic pipeline. As a result, local and state bureaucracies can plan and regulate restoration and conservation all they like, but they can’t do much OTITC. Hence the need for Landcare and its sisters, the unbureaucratic bureaucratization of OTITC ecology. The individual coordinators and the committees of Landcarers who employ them are sometimes tempted by the sensed, temporary power of regulators. However, apart from ensuring that the limited funds at their limited disposal are used by people OTITC actually to restore and conserve their bit of nature, policing compliance is not a primary function. Indeed it is a function to be avoided precisely in the interests of achieving outcomes. Compliance is a curse on those who have to compel it. It might be imagined that the Landcare bureaucracy evolved to execute nonbureaucratic actions such as the famous on ground work, or that state environmental bureaucracies do this. They seldom do however. Primarily they produce inventories of biota, maps, databases, management plans, feasibility 172

studies, directives to contractors, technical advice and liaison to people OTITC. They distribute and account for certain forms of financial assistance and remuneration to contractors and landholders, and they regulate management in order to ensure accountability back to the bureaucracy, the government and that final placeholder in the political system, the taxpayer who is, of course, OTITC. Desktop management, facilitation, PR and networking are cheaper and deemed to have a big multiplier affect on the natural resource dollar. And they are less likely to be perturbed by external irritationsespecially nature. As databases, programs, networks and other structures grow they exert greater and greater gravitational force, drawing all into their orbit, all eyes fixed on their dazzling screens. Management plans, inventories, financial records, monitoring and evaluation do, to a certain extent get read outside the system, but their main function then is to satisfy legal, political and, still, internal pressures. Their main circulation (if they circulate and get read at all and do not just get filed) is still within the system. Their main bureaucratic function is to dot all the legal i’s and cross all the political and public relations t’s, rather than to get read or reflected upon. Apart from the educational stuffand these are the merest tip of fascinating mountains of knowledge kept as arcana for envirocratic plannersprobably the only ones that get read OTITC are things like the published environmental assessments that green activists have to read. These are mainly read to find missing dots and crosses, and they draw the activists into the dispiriting bureaucratic orbit. In an immune response to this bureaucratic infection the green lobby develops symptoms of doctrinalism. The doctrine’s precepts are adapted to the imperative not to let the agents of degradation loophole there way around regulations. Whether or not they are the best means of long-term conservation and restoration is less pressing. In turn, the regulations and the bureaucracy are adapted in response to the pressures brought to bear by environmentalist doctrine. The whole process takes place in the social environment of envirocratic politics. The natural environment is less immediate. A similar process takes place in the contest between bureaucracies and farmer’s lobby groups. Meanwhile, dullness is a fine adaptation for a document designed to be not read. Bulk is too. Where dullness is not available, confidentiality and intellectual property are bogeys used to prevent a document’s escape from the system. Even the published educational stuff gets utterly corrupted by managerialism. In the guise of promoting awareness or sharing knowledge, it reifies limited attention spans by keeping it simple and selling dot-pointed vision on eye-glazing glossies. God help the audience that wants local ecological detail and technical questions answered. Despite the desire to have a say, having a say is seldom the main function of documents in this culturecertainly not having a say beyond the orbit of the system. I assume that those multiple environmental pressures back in the anonymous quote, the pressures that need assessing in those priority setting exercises, are supposed to be of the biophysical kind rather than the equally problematic social kind. Even though the author is a scientist, it is not society that he writes about scientifically. That would have to be sociology. Yet, although he is an 173

ecologist he is not writing about society ecologicallynot if society is a major ecological player. He is ignoring the ecologically significant social pressures. The description of the social interaction begins as one of exasperated wonder, amusement and aesthetic appreciation, but the reflections on the task of social interaction and building links between science and the community sound as vague as a bureaucrat or someone OTITC discussing the finer points of empirical or theoretical ecology. Even though ecology has scarcely managed to drag itself up out of the primeval swamp of natural history, social science has an even more difficult task to separate itself scientifically from the folk sociology and psychology of everyday life. Everyone claims expertise in these folk sciences simply as a birthright. Yet society is a strange and fascinating thing, much stranger and much more fascinating than pop psychology or envirocratic sociology with their reports and vision statements, clichés, catchphrases, pleonasms, non-sequitors and acronyms, would ever be able to recognize and describe. In fact the halfbaked social science of those reports and vision statements is better thought of as among the natural wonders of society. All those explanations of society are themselves strange and fascinating social objects. Rather than explaining society, they contribute to its complexity, making it all the more in need of explanation. Categories like community, out there, big picture and the triple bottom line become the obligatory descriptors of the only possible world that anyone is game to call the real world. Question concepts like leadership or outcomes and people look askance. But this famous real world is mostly all image. It can scarcely be anything but what we are required to talk it up into. A society is like that—a galaxy of communications in which the most misleading are the received descriptions of itself—so the reality is mostly unconscious, making it effectively non-existent. Assumed knowledge of society and everyday familiarity with the community breed contempt for thoughtful reflection—as all that half hearted, recycled prose demonstrates. Sociological and psychological findings popularized for community consumption sound like the bleeding obvious, self-improvement or marketing tools. Original reflections mostly sound odd or irrelevant. Having made the effort of objectification they are estranged from their object—i.e. from the society that can no longer find the comforts of its misleading self-descriptions repeated therein. So catch 22: once they no longer talk the talk, they are ineffective. Politics is applied social science, a technology of social management sometimes described as the art of the possible. I certainly can’t claim a talent or relish for it. To me it looks like having a say in natural resource management is mostly a matter of things like mundane observation, political cunning, dogged persistence, the right friends, attention to detail, earning respect, being driven by a vision that is not too visionary, i.e. detailing plans that others can agree with, being one step ahead, setting agendas, knowing how to play the game, and good fortune. Just being a head kicker or a mover and shaker are not enough. I can only approach the society of natural resource management as its amateur naturalist agog at its wonders. 174

You may have noticed one species that is not listed in the observations of biodiversity at community meetings: the environmentalist. They may be there as representatives of community groups (i.e. green groups) or in amongst those warriors who are presumably of various persuasions. However environmentalists are often absent by choicetheir own or others. They are said to prefer the lock-it-up kind of environmentalism. They may in fact be excluded for harmony’s sake from many environmental discussions of the OTITC kind, in order to get the farmers on board. There are all sorts of pressures, assumptions, and agendas operating in these OTITC situations, beginning with the selection of those who get the seats at the table. It makes management easier. Another unlisted species is the ecological restorer or bush regenerator, but then this is an unscheduled threatened species. In lip service at least, its habitat is sanctified as the coalface or on-ground. It is quintessentially OTITC. However the bureaucratization of nature is evidence of the ancient hierarchy in which intellectual labour ranks above manual labour. Its effect is immense. Hardly anyone really wants to get their hands dirty, especially when they would get paid poorly for their efforts. Managerialism absorbs almost all the action, and that includes managing a modicum of the budget for physical labourfor the menial necessities, for a few sexy projects, and for some carrot to tempt volunteers. Terms that fall too often and too easily from managers’ lips deserve a scrutiny that might seem excessive. Let me begin by analyzing out there in the community into two components. First the community. When managers or leaders or legislators or even two or three people gathered together register the irritations from outside their own system, they find it convenient to describe them by using a singular term to designate a seemingly single phenomenon. The term environment is used to denote the complex of an organism’s surroundings simplified in the image of the organism’s own unity. Likewise management uses the community to reduce its environment to something simple. Such a term enables what is utterly disunited and unwieldy to stand in the system’s conversation as the single object of its ministry, service and manipulation, administration to the needs of which should not be complicated by the fact of the contradictory character of those needs, especially not when the function of management is to move on from conflict and antagonism. As such, the community has a peculiar value in the conversation of a managerial system: it is the goose that lays its golden eggs, the almost sanctified, almost powerless source of its power, the propitiation of which and seeming responsiveness to which may justify and preserve its systemic existence and that of the individual managers within the system. There is evidence of this seeming responsiveness in the evolution of the term community, and indeed in the fact that the term itself is perhaps more substantial for the system than whatever vaguely irritating object it pretends to refer to. The present legitimate term must have passed through gates of selection erected and later torn down throughout the history of the society. The gates bar old terms as primitive and taboo and allow new terms through precisely for their seeming to signify the antithesis of the outmoded 175

and taboo ones. Hence the specific historical nuances of terms like citizens, the people, the masses, the society or the public make each one of them sound in its own way anachronistic, improper, illegitimate or downright unneighbourly when compared to the community. Margaret Thatcher declared society dead, and the way we use community now, her declaration seems to have been timely. However this string of more or less passé terms should also warn us that the present incumbent is also temporary. Each of the terms represents an adaptation to local pressures, in particular to the demands that no term should be seen to be revealing the social antagonisms that management is charged with making disappear. Each of the predecessors of community appeared to be becoming partisan in some rapidly changing world. The masses sound undifferentiated and unfree. Society sounds like socialism. The accusation politically correct can still be used to damage the legitimacy of terms, and could even soon prey on community, so long as it does not itself fall victim to the modish evolution of platitudes and find its own powers removed. I have heard people use neighbourhood as if they were becoming wary of the community. Soon you might only be able to get away with saying the family. The evolution of other managerial terms proceeds similarly in a kind of ceaseless arms race of new terminological adaptations succeeding one another in successive historical contexts. For instance, managerial problems are relabeled as issues and to that extent and in that historical moment signify that they have been addressed and we can all be a little less negative about them. And of course bureaucracy itself became anachronistic once bureaucracies were to think about themselves as selling themselves and their product. They ceased to describe their operations as bureaucratic, which long ago had derogatory connotations, and became managerial, by which term I choose to denigrate them here. In managerial parlance metaphors, already platitudinous, get extended to allegorical lengths, mainly because managerial systems like to describe themselves thoroughly in the terms of their latest official vision. As the market had displaced social democracy, managerialized bureaucracy embraced the market as the model for its self-description. The descriptions are a bit like medieval allegory working at different levels of metaphor. Apart from the dominant level of the market there is a spiritual level in terms like vision and mission. And at the secular level, the community remains as a kind of homely cipher for that residue of civil society that could not be entirely subsumed as staff, customers, clients or followers. By the way, don’t let it be said that I am being negative about the community. The community is like motherhood or the family. Although I am tempted to call it a necessary evil, all I should say is, it’s all we’ve got so read the label. Whatever the community denotes, in some of its forms it deserves to be defended against its lip-service devotees. Therefore, two cheers for the community. Second, out there. The X-Files registered out there’s popular reputation as the place where the truth is. The phrase locates the source of truth, power, authority, data, information or knowledge elsewhere and thus away from where it would be questioned as self-serving or subjective. As an external guarantee of 176

authenticity it distracts a managerial system, and its critics, from the system’s own arbitrariness and from any worry that things could be otherwise. It also distracts a system from its own contradictions, in particular from the contradiction between, on the one hand, its own self-generating existence and, on the other, its self-description as being entirely dependent upon and at the service of what is outside it, namely out there in the community. The fully formed phrase out there in the community has many uses: to suggest that the speaker can read the popular will and takes its issues on board; to imply that the speaker speaks for that will and at the same time decorously to distance the speaker from the hoi polloi who are merely out there in the community and not in here speaking. Its use is a display of democratic intentions, a waylaying of suspicions of professional or envirocratic elitism, an advertisement of one’s appreciation that others OTITC, specifically volunteers, must do the ecological management or restoration work, a veiled renunciation of one’s own individual responsibility for doing or not doing the restoration, and of course a seeming reference to some actual thing that is out there, something whose members share some kind of collective interest and some kind of systemic unity themselves. Despite users’ intentions, the term can usually be read as a pretty reliable symptom of some degree of paternalism, slight of hand, conceptual cloudiness or unfreedom on its user’s part. Whenever we think we are using it, it is probably using us, piggy backing its replication and dissemination on the back of our often less than honourable, less than conscious intentions. If a community is anything, then it is more like a can of worms or a multitude of evils than the unproblematic unity that the simple singular term seems to denote. It is a hotchpotch of people, sometimes fractious, sometimes just shambolic, less ideologically consistent than the scientific or envirocratic communities because the members don’t share a unifying a system of social discourse and their views are not so subject to a regular set of pressures that would determine conformity of discourse. It is hard to imagine a community forumone that is representative of the communitythat would not be divided ideologically and personally and that is not, on many occasions, prone to vexatiousness. It is no wonder then that when natural resource managers and scientists meet with people OTITC, the managers and scientists, who each represent a relatively united or consistent ideology and who are paid to turn up, have ‘a stronger say in decision making.’ Given that the ‘government officials and environmental managers’ hold the purse strings, plan the management, and are employed as intermediaries between the political system and the electorate, it is also little wonder that they have more power than the scientists, whose power hardly extends beyond the laboratory or the ivory tower. Although managerialism has pretended to functionalize the role of manager as just another division of labour, the ethical prestige and self-esteem that goes with leadership have hardly been renounced by managers, and the managed still resent their powerlessness—the more so for the sensed illegitimacy of their managers’ prestige. 177

At a meeting between natural resource managers, scientists and people OTITC, the fractiousness of the community is exacerbated and the democratic credentials are belied by the arbitrariness of just who turns up (unpaid) and what hidden agendas and personal animosities they bring. 90% of a public meeting can lie under the surface. And it can be more like the seething entrails of a beast than the cool gravity of an iceberg. To make matters utterly confusing (to me anyway) part of all this seething is that people are actually reading these entrails, and feeding their superstitious readings, rumours, theories, suspicions, enmities and idiosyncratic proclivities back into the seething mix. Also, part of the seething is the managers’ unstated agenda. When they call meetings and seek community representatives, their work is made easier if they can play with a stacked deck. They assume they have to, otherwise the meeting will be a shambles and it won’t get the best outcomes. Meeting-wise, that’s world’s best practice. Or it is second nature and they do it unconsciously anyway. Out of these convolutions of feedback all one can hope for is a kind of emergent, superordinating pattern, or maybe just a bit of good old settling down. As with ecological restoration, this takes time. As if to let the community itself speak, the article cites a speech from someone OTITC: Surely someone with wisdom and respect could have guided us rapidly through the mire and helped us work through the conflict and growth process? I think our lesson is that we did not seek such guidance, we had a chance to have a say and we took the time to do this in our own way rather than deal skillfully with that and rapidly move on to focus on the bigger picture. ‘How can we move forward,’ the article asks, ‘and ensure that we can undertake valid scientific assessment in unison between scientists and community members and more effectively jointly influence environmental decision making?’ Three points about this: First. This belated request for guidance is interpreted as ‘a positive exception’ to the way that ‘at least some members of the community do not make it easy for scientists to become actively involved in decision making or on-ground assessments.’ But doesn’t it just flatter the presumed wisdom of the scientists (and the natural resource managers, and the would-be community leaders) who like to fancy they could lead this unruly beast through the mire? I suspect that ‘someone with wisdom and respect’ might not be someone who sees their self-appointed role as that of a guide: the two attributes might be mutually exclusive. Doesn’t this call, like calls for leadership, also sound a bit desperate, the desperation or even resentment of someone whose seeming cry for help is really a denial of responsibility or an apportioning of blame to some non specific others who have failed to provide leadership in the past? Why didn’t they guide us? How could they have just dropped us in this mire? I 178

would also predict that if a community committee did seek guidance, such guidance would probably be provided by some facilitator or community liaison officer and it could well be abysmal. If it wasn’t, the committee members might well not appreciate it anyway, no matter how well delivered. Diplomatic delivery would meet with disregard. Strong advocacy would be taken as pushiness. Expertise would be too technical. The voice of experience would be dismissed by impatience. Especially when working through a conflict and growth process. I suspect the cry is just another way of saying surely we could have had the benefit of experience without having to go through the experience. Second. How about, instead of rapidly moving on to focus on the bigger picture, we apply ourselves at our own pace to the job immediately at hand. Why move on and in a hurry and for no better reason than getting a look at some picture that is too big and too limited in its detail? Indeed isn’t it a bit fishy that this person from OTITC is talking in, or being paraphrased in managerialese. And just in case all this seems like too harsh a judgement of the community, remember that the community, by definition, is out there, and not, like this paraphrased representative or the paraphraser himself, in here at the table. Third. That how can we move forward sentence is another mind number. I quickly gather the fruits of stylistic analysisthe platitudes like move forward and decision making, the worthiness of in unison, the double-barreled adverb effectively jointly, the redundant environmentaljust to show how talking the talk so diverts us that we can be deceived into thinking that decision making is itself the proper end of our endeavours. As with that conflict and growth process and rapidly moving on and focusing on the bigger picture, it is a way of not thinking much and not doing much either. Science may be what scientists do, but knowledge and especially a little knowledge are what everyone does. It’s dangerous and fun. There is a folk science of ecology that is as passionate and half-baked as the pop psychology and pop sociology with which it is so synergistically and inextricably combined. This body of knowledge may well be as inconsistent as the community is divided, but it is as powerful an epistemological force as any in OTITC ecology. And it is as powerful an ecological force as climate, soils, markets and managerialism. While it is, of course, a force of nature in political environmentalism, here I am concerned with its influence in ecological management and restoration. Under the sanction of common sense it is able to present itself as pretty much indubitable. It is a set of social assumptions whose validity is assumed to be manifest to all. Edmund Husserl (1954) called such shared, mutually manifest assumptions the lifeworld. 20th philosophers of language discovered again and again that there can be no communication without some such social basis. As such it informs the judgements of scientists and environmental managers as much as those of people OTITC. As I have said, ecology evolved as a modern scientific rationalization not only of the 179

already specialized disciplines of natural history and natural philosophy but of this common sense understanding of the natural world. The lifeworld understanding of ecology (or society), although it evolves somewhat under the pressures exerted by scientific ecology (or social science), persists as a shared conceptual domain, if only because the pressure to communicate persistently maintains it in some formhowever much it is perennially changeable and contestable around the edges. This makes the synergistic mix of lifeworld ecology and lifeworld sociology that famous common ground between scientists, managers and people OTITC, and also therefore that dreaded place to link up and that dreaded place from which we can all move forward together. The received opinions of OTITC ecology, like all repeated platitudes, suffer their own deformations of meaning and use. Misapprehensions and self deceptions have thrived, and having thrived become norms. Scientific concepts feed back into the content of the lifeworld, for lifeworld science is not innate knowledge unmediated by cultural evolution. Indeed, the term pop ecology better describes folk ecology in its contemporary cultural form. Most of what enters pop ecology from science does so half-baked, which is hardly surprising when scientific ecology itself is hardly a completed project. When the adequacy of ecological concepts to their objects is blurred by constitutional limitations to empirical testing, terms struggle to keep to a strict sense, and feedback from the scientific to the pop scientific world becomes as risky as feeding beef waste back to cattle or photocopies back into a photocopier. Likewise when a science is burdened by irreducible historical descriptions, and when chronic seat of the pants instrumentalism is always tempting weakly generalized descriptions into prescriptive formulation. Likewise also when claims to knowledge are motivated by the need to delude either oneself or others, in which case magical prescriptions, rural myths or unconscious judgements of taste pose as knowledge claims in pop ecological management. This is mostly armchair instrumentalism. Just what kind of ecological effect pop ecology has, is no doubt poorly indicated by the saying a little knowledge is dangerous. However, the concepts of pop-ecology have ecological consequences and to that extent demand the attention of ecological research, even though that would illegally cross the border between ecology and the social sciences. Among the myths and magic that persist in this part of the world are things like: the tree canopy will shade out the weeds; a strangler figs planted in a camphor laurel will eventually kill the host. My favorite is the one about lobbing a few ripe chokoes into a lantana scrub and letting the ckoko vines blanket the scrub and hey presto—no lantana and more chokoes then you can eat. Then again why would you want to get rid of lantana when it is an important native bee and bird habitat or a pioneer for rainforest regeneration or a vital soil conditioner? Or camphor laurel when it is important pigeon feed and arboreal mammal habitat. Lantana and camphor are not the only serious weeds of native vegetation with redemptive powers. Broad-leaved paspalum is a Landcare grass and an excellent understorey in forests. Maybe one of these legendary prescriptions might have appeared to work once somewhere, or 180

someone thought it did. More likely they just hoped it would. In the report, hope turned into fact and rumour did the rest. Along with dredging native wetlands to free them up and get the water flowing deep and clear these or getting these formulations have a stubborn persistence that only wishful thinking could give them. I hear them all the time. But they are not my main concern here. There is the more serious stuff. The stuff that sounds universal and wise rather than half clever and wishfully ignorant. There are now scores of theses-cum-prescriptions with an unassailable status in the lifeworld of OTITC ecology, and pretty much everyone is OTITC assuming them. To intone them at a meeting or to powerpoint them on a screen is to automatically earn the nod of assent. Or of dozing off. To challenge just one is pretty much to lose it. You will be laughed at. Let me list some. There are the realities of the present predicament: that there is so much to do; that we have not really even started yet. There is the first principle of means: that without funding nothing can really be done. And the principles of the necessity of promotion OTITC: that sexy projects are a priority; that the community needs to be educated; that the kiddies have to be involved; that environmental awareness needs to be promoted. There is the first theorem of consolation; that although we haven’t really even started yet at least we have been raising awareness. There is the principle of whole-of-community involvement: that liaison is fundamentalwith local government, the National Parks service, the Department of Infrastructure, Planning and Natural Resources, Aboriginal Land Councils, stakeholders,… and of course people OTITC. There is the metastrategic principle: that things have to be prioritized. And there are the strategic principles: a management plan is a priority; seeing the big picture is a priority; having a whole of landscape strategy is a priority; connectivity is a priority; targeting the top of the catchment is a priority; targeting hot-spots is a priority, a scatter gun approach is not; and without clearly defined goals, outcomes can’t be measured and are therefore useless. Then there is the principle of what we need is more information, i.e. research, monitoring and evaluation: since all our knowledge is best brought together so that we can all see that big picture all at once and undertake informed decision making, it is vital to establish, or better still, to work towards establishing a set of metadata for a standard across-the-board format for project monitoring (data are good but metadata are better); without more baseline data, measures of outcomes and therefore outcomes themselves will be useless; we need more research, whether for getting that baseline data or because ecosystems are too complex to risk touching without more data. And finally there are the principles of practicality: that we can’t be precious, we have to be pragmatic; and that there is no point doing it if it’s not world’s best practice. You read all of these and you pretty much have to agree, don’t you. They have the buzz of managerial style. They are conditioned by ecology’s epistemological vagaries and its urgent but unclear intentions. (Little wonder then that managerialism, thriving on vagaries and vaguely grand intentions, should have so thoroughly invaded pop ecology. Little wonder that, other than 181

ecological management, it is hard to think of a general term to describe both restoration and conservation ecology in one go.) These principles might not sound like scientific ecology, but that is because they are lifeworld ecology and therefore they have to be something that not only scientists would say. Whether you are a scientist, an envirocrat or OTITC, to cast doubt on, or express misgivings about any of the principles of OTITC ecology is to risk intellectual or even ethical condemnation. Not to take them as common sense begets incredulity. At best you must be naïve, stupid or a crank; at worst, negative. I am happy to assert the contrary of each and leave it at that. Together they constitute a terrible impediment to ecological management and restoration. To reread them and consider how their negations could be true is a revealing exercise in ecological thinking and in thinking about society as an ecological object. And about ecology as a social object. I’ll leave it to the reader. Although I am only an amateur naturalist of society, I find it useful to theorize that social institutions, bureaucracies, managers, or people OTITC can be predictable in their own ways. As forces of nature they are a bit like floods, droughts, vandals or herbivores. I have known restoration projects in which bureaucracies can be worked around, like mountains. They can be predictably slow and really don’t want to know what really matters. Or they are like drought or fire or floods: they have their uses as long as you don’t get caught in the middle of them. I feel a kind of security in this, as I do in the predictable randomness of vandalism. On the other hand, bureaucrats or managers should not be confused with bureaucracies. Unlike bureaucracies or mountains they are people and they appreciate the little things of life. Vandals are people too, although for the purposes of ecological restoration they are like a species of herbivore. The principles of OTITC ecology are also like a force of nature. When you encounter them OTITC, do so with a light heart and cunning. Avoid a head on assault. Attend to the ecological or ethical detail. Go and do some restoration somewhere else. Like weeds they require patience and persistence. Unlike weeds they are not especially rampant at the coalface. And there is another force of nature: some people OTITC are actually busy doing ecological restoration instead of just being predictably uninterested or vexatious. Such people are predictably going to do restoration, and persist. You don’t need the softcore porn of a sexy project to arouse them. They’re already in bed with nature. Since, in adaptive ecological management, you keep building on what you have, they are as much something to build as a good reach of river or patch of bush. Targeting them is a better bet than targeting the top of the catchment. Given the thoroughly social nature of nature, they are the best thing to build on. Their works are the primary documents of OTITC ecology. Disquiet about the delays of ecological restoration and the pathologies of environmental bureaucracy are legion. Conference papers, journal articles and opinion pieces reflect on this problem, offer critiques of social organization, diagnose the pathologies of environmental managerialism, keep our spirits up by re-assuring us that at least we are raising community awareness and building community capacity, and draft blueprints on ways to move forward. 182

Even if all this activity is not exactly causing what it is diagnosing, most of it doesn’t help. It gets society wrong and it gets nature’s social nature wrong. Planners and change-managers trick themselves into thinking they can solve social problems by first making society simpler to conceive. So they misconceive it. It makes the thing familiar and it does the job at hand. That is, it makes planning easier, and outcomes definable and therefore measurable, achievable and accountable for. Getting the timescales wrong is a typical form of simplification and it feeds the habitual sense of social and biophysical inertia that haunts restoration ecology. Natural resource management always appears to be only just getting started because ecological processes and restoration mostly happen at timescales that exceed easy intuition. Not only nature but also society moves in ways that are mysterious to the human sense of time. Neither natural systems nor social systems conveniently synchronize themselves to human lifetimes, terms of government, yearly budgets or everyday activity. Social goals are disputed to begin with and so are means. Then, society changes, science changes, technology changes, and goals and means end up changing quicker than ecosystems. They become outdated when they are half completed. When even our intentions about nature end up defying our intentions, how can nature do anything but elude our plans and predictions? Sure we might number the months or years in our timelines, and flowcharts but abstract chronology is too neat for all the tangled processes of ecological society all working at different timescales. Natural resource management exceeds conceptual integration, except perhaps at some such emergent level as that described by social selection—but then the social phenomena that confront us are likely to be alienated from our intentions to the point of downright arbitrariness. Similar problems beset environmental management in the spatial dimension, not only because mastering space takes time, but because land tenure alone ensures that both the ideological antagonisms and the functional differentiation of society are spread out like a dog’s breakfast over the culturescape. The dots just don’t join up. And managers and everyone OTITC love the dots to join up. We like corridors and connectivity and the maps and flowcharts that go with imagining it. Desires to see the big picture, to integrate landscape scale and local processes, ecological scales and institutional structures are the barely disguised re-statements of the original desire to restore nature itself. Like a fetish, we transfer desire from the seemingly unattainable (a well-engineered natural environment) to the seemingly attainable (a well-engineered social structure for working towards a well-engineered natural environment). Although we appear to be prescribing the social means to ecological goals we are substituting descriptions of ecological goals with descriptions of social goals and assuming they can be achieved in the no less intractable matter of social organization. One way we make it seem less intractable is by another misapprehension. We fail to see that biophysical objects are the primary social objects in the culture of nature: as well as being just rivers or bush or biodiversity, rivers, bush, and biodiversity are the principal documents of the culture of environmental 183

management. The social organization of such a culture is not primarily in offices and institutional structures and maps and flow charts or even OTITC. It is actually, dare I say it, on the ground. You don’t build community capacity or raise community awareness much at all without working on these documents. Culture and nature can be separated in analysis but not in the substance or practice of nature culture. Health and education systems have their managerial symptoms, but they are rooted in the bodies and minds they work on. Natural resource management barely touches the ground. It is more entertained by the groundless problem of itself. Its apparent fascination with its own administrative organ is the result of its social ancestry and social pressures. Health must, as it were, get its hands dirty. There are urgent imperatives of life and death, and there is the historical prestige of the physician’s healing hands. Education need only work on paper, screen and talk. Those are the tools at the coalface of minds. But natural resource management, which must literally get its hands dirty, has little pressure to work on the ground—its primary medium and object. It prefers paper and pixels. There is no sense of personal life and death urgency. Its social forefathers have been administrative, regulatory and passive conservation agencies. Not everyone even agrees it has serious job to do, especially not on their land. Funding is scarce. To such a social environment the system is perfectly adapted: it’s a filter-feeder in a muddy, low dollar, low nutrient habitat and its administrative organ has hypertrophied into managerial foie gras. Its distinctive call is the abracadabra that attracts the trickle of the envirodollar and, it is said, multiplies its power: the community. An envirocratic colleague once proposed delivering a paper at a Landcare conference entitled ‘Ad hoc is good’. Circumstances, ad hoc or otherwise, prevented him from doing so. Perhaps such an idea had little hope of ever getting a hearing because it sounded too flippant or too negative to get a place on a tight programa program that had to demonstrate deference to the received principles of natural resource managerialism. He was right though. Projects do not have to all link up in an integrated landscape scale approachnot all or even the majority of projects. Not initially. Ecologically, linking it all up is a case of fighting against some of the most implacable ecological forcessocial forces as powerful as gravity. Some goals are distant. Linking up is a means that is so distant it looks like a goal. It just can’t be the first thing. When objects and ends exceed our understanding, and where, in the absence of understanding, platitudes thrive for giving us false comfort or bogus understanding, muddling on and working away is the only prescription. Each deed is one step in an algorithm of adaptive management. Ad hoc is good mainly because just doing it, or even just thinking clearly about it, is mostly not what restoration society, with all its busy managers, is doing.

184

12 The Image of Nature How nature is represented not only in painting, photography, cinema, TV, national myth, pop culture and environmentalism, but also in national parks and wilderness.

Being is unrecognizable unless it succeeds in seeming, and seeming is weak unless it succeeds in being. —Gorgias of Leontini, c. 430 B.C.

Intro Nothing now escapes the ontological capers of becoming an image—not when all of life, in Guy Debord’s words, presents itself as an immense accumulation of spectacles. Not even cultural criticism, which deteriorates from copy to copy, and degrades into cliché and the image of critique. Everything that has directly lived has moved away into representation. Try and discover the real thing behind its image and it will disappear altogether. In societies where modern conditions prevail, image making is like commoditization: it is a force of nature. Nature cannot help but be product, commodity and image. Yet surely nature, of all things, should remain solid and resist melting into the air of mere image. Is anyone really going to be able to spirit away nature with a bit of that old postmodern magic? Only, I suspect, in all those clichéd images of a postmodernism degraded for the sake of slapdash critique. Anyway, if they tried to, it would come down on them ruthlessly. When it did though, they would probably be watching it live on their TVs, even as the firestorm hit the house, consuming the TV and them as they consumed it, all melting into air, into thin air. As the image-makers say, it’s all about image. Hence this album of the images of nature by means of which people pursue their social relations to one another by enacting and experiencing society’s relation to nature.

185

12.1 …In Art.

That Milky Stream; Or Landscape Art Contemporary nature photography has a habit that is quite bizarre and pretty much run of the mill. It is the custom of depicting clear streams with milky water. In photo after photo wild rivers look as though some white pollutant is seeping into the water. The image of flowing water is blurred by prolonged exposure of the film. Yet how odd to deprive the camera of its nimble power to hold water’s shape, to disclose a unique instant in the clear liquid’s ceaseless flow or still the detail of turbulence. What shape is turbulent water? What must it really look like? Without photography, the longing to see such a thing would epitomize impossible desire. Before photography, painters, even idle watchers from a bank, would have sold their souls to see this. In order for these milky images to be published over and over again, the culture of nature and the minds of nature’s devotees must press photography to adopt this devious adaptation. The problems of shutter and film speed on a shaded riffle might account for some of these imagesat least they used to oncebut more than that, there is a genre of stream photography here that licenses or demands the exhibition of images that might otherwise have been discarded as blurry failures of execution or blots on the landscape. How could such a genre evolve? If I think of the history of those images of milky streams or, at least initially, if I remember my own experience of them, the Franklin Dam campaign comes to mind. In the no-dams campaign such photos came to symbolize the wild, undammed river. Think of Peter Dombrovskis’ icon of Rock Island Bend. Bob Brown (1984, 60) once said that showing pictures of the Franklin allowed nature to speak for itself. Back in the 1890s in Melbourne, the Argus had said much the same thing about photographs of Sassafras Gully taken by Beaky Campbell and R. S. Sugars. They were silent but telling protests against the destruction of forest in the Dandenongs (Bonyhady, 123). 20 years earlier, Joseph Bischoff’s Blue Mountain streamscape, The Valley of the Grose (1875), complete with milky water fountained through sandstone boulders, joined a photographic custom already co-opted into conservation rhetoric by Carleton Watkins’ 1860s photos of Yosemite (Bonyhady, 195). Over a century later, it was still supposed to be the voice of nature, beyond rhetoric. Yet, from the moment watery nature was photographed at a slow shutter speed and encouraged to speak like a milksop, it ceased to speak for itself. Constrained to emphasize nature’s naturalness, it skirted expectations and started signifying murkier things. At first perhaps it might just have been a way to make water’s path visible and indelible. It perhaps started to signify free flow, or, more murkily, in its whiteness, purity. From there it was not far from being taken as some kind of watery Victorian fairy gossamer, and on it goes to soporific Arcadian 186

enchantments and heavy New Age ethereality. That is just a hypothetical history. In the social game of association and semantic selection, layer upon layer of sensibility, at first delicate, is superimposed on fleeting perception in an extended series of little semantic events, almost imitating the moment-bymoment prolongation of the photographic exposure. Soon what was transparent image becomes opaque, and then a murky symbol. The sign given by nature has drifted into graceless arbitrariness and stale convention. What might have been a bright image of clear water becomes an unnatural emblem of naturalness, instantly recognizable for years to come in advertisements for everything from wilderness to washing-up liquid. The milky riffle is not a likeness of a natural streamobviouslyit is an icon of naturalness. In fact the word icon has become a bit of an icon. It comes from the Greek for likeness, and the philosopher C. S. Peirce used it that way in the terminology of his semiotics to distinguish likenesses from symbols. Symbols, for Peirce, were signs that signify by convention, signs that bear no natural or obvious relation to what they signify. Semiotics has long emphasized that theirs is an arbitrary relation to what they signify. Nowadays though, an icon is usually an emblem. The word has undergone a change in its semantic function. And an emblem is a picture that has undergone a change in its semantic function. It has become what Peirce called a symbolno longer transparent and pictorial, but conventional and arbitrary in what it signifies. Although an icon may have begun life signifying just what it depicts, it has become a conventional way of symbolizing something else, the way a gum tree picture signifies an Australianness of landscape, or a lyrebird signifies the National Parks service. Deconstructing the algorithm of an image’s evolutionif it is still possible to work back through the successive layers of variation and selection that have turned a clear natural image or a brilliant act of capture into an opaque, arbitrary signis not a way of getting back to the source and finding the authentic original meaning, or the thing-in-itself. Just go down to the river for that. What matters at the end of such a process are not the first things, but the last things, the images we end up with and in whose image we end up seeing the things themselves. Such processes take place all through the image culture of nature. Landscape for instancenot just on the wall but from the look outis country as image, the spectacle of land. Images of nature cease to be signs that signify by virtue of their likeness to what they represent. They take on a portion of meaning that is theirs by the grace or burden of custom, and they start to signify things other than what they are images of. So if landscape is country as sheer appearance, the country itself becomes more and more hidden behind that bewitching spectacle of appearance. Landscape images cease from showing us the land itself and start signifying certain social attributes of being land. They start to be used rhetorically to persuade, to advertise, to console, to stimulate, to frame or grasp or make one feel at home. They become signs of relations like ownership, appropriation, patriotism, power or aesthetic transcendence. They become 187

themes abstracted from nature upon which painters undertake variations in colour, shape and line, variations that are a responses to artistic tradition and ways of seeing rather than the images of things. Landscape painting is bound by the iron bands of its conventions, its allowable material utterly circumscribed, the scope and detail of its look rigidly censored in an unconscious conspiracy of painters and viewers. Landscape painters would not deign to reproduce the Philistine, coffee table stuff of most nature photographers, let alone wildlife photographers. Land only for themwildlife looks like kitschand the art consists in the way the paint scapes it, and maybe, to add a dash of meaningfulness, puts some figures in. Like the painter, the viewers inclining their heads in appreciation fancy that originality consists in new ways of looking or seeing or showing, ways of displaying what oft was seen but ne’er before so captured. However the credit landscape painting is given for showing us nature and how to look at it, and, in Australia, for disclosing the nation to itself, scarcely conceals how captive we are in the narrow reality that the genre allows. I feel annoyed for the landscape painters and photographers whose images are stolen, despite their intentions, for national histories of their genre or for myths of national self-formation. Not only does it have little to do with nation, the best landscape hardly dares to show us nature, let alone capture it. Subjectivity is present in works almost as a thing falling away, overwhelmed. I think this about the paintings of the Bellinger School. Its attitude is not capture but gratitude. With astonishment, it accepts the gifts that nature gives it—shapes, spaces, colours, lines—as things for it to work with. It is amazed at the shape of that slab of sunlight, the muted colours of that hill, the uncontrived composition of leaf litter, or the squiggles of those trees. Style becomes a matter of courteously, carefully picking up the pieces. The willingness to follow this amazement though is probably what leads landscape painting away form nature and at first to the revelations of formalism and stepwise by influence and derivation to its dead ends. Landscapes become like caricatures. Once someone has struck the mould, or found a vocabulary of features, artists reproduce them as quick and clever ideograms. Eventually, like the gum-tree-scape, they degrade into logos. The take on reality is completely artificial, yet so effective that we take landscape’s conventions, arbitrary as they are, either for clear images of the thing itself, or as brilliant painterly contrivances whereby the thing in itself is captured wild. Original or skilful execution reveals an artist’s mastery of the historical implications unfolding strictly within a genre. Though nature, as Goethe said, has the power to make even a moderate talent perceptive in its presencewhich is why really careful drawings always give us pleasurethe power to incline the head of the viewer lies in what the painter paints: the picture, not the thing pictured. In turn, the thing pictured starts to look like a picture. We come to see nature itself as a canvas. Modern landscape has been founded on the contemplative tradition of experiencing nature as sheer appearance, indeed according to some customary kinds of appearance, kinds 188

that indicate the limit of or reify what appearance can be for us. The bush morphs into landscape and becomes a place alienated form the kind of intimate experience that was conveyed by say a French Impressionist. One ironclad convention of Australian landscape, one that almost defines it as art, is the sublime apprehension of this pre-alienated landscape. The subject of landscape art is, as the environmental management term would put it, at a landscape scale. Since realism is a driving ambition behind such painting we believe in the realism of the images. In order to do so the bush is made into a place of intrinsically heroic proportions, lacking intimacy of colour and form and demanding to be represented by a kind of painterly equivalent of the mythologised national laconic. The Australian impressionism of the Heidelberg painters is said to be conditioned by the landscape and the bush itself. It is a view that sits plausibly with the notion that culture grows out of land, but the supposed realism that the Heidelberg painters are still credited with is more a case of their participation in romanticized national virtues of stoicism and laconic representation. This sent all those 20th century painters out into the desert, instead of idling around the bush in Mosman or Coogee. Imitating the 19th century explorers became a rite of artistic passage. Meanwhile the intimate representation of the bush is mostly to be found in Aboriginal painting in genres descended from traditional Aboriginal representation that fall outside of landscape and morph into contemporary abstraction, or in genres that fall outside of art altogether, such as botanical illustration or kitsch. Actual works of nature are utterly unlike this sheer appearance; they teach us how much landscape is founded not only on conventions but on conventions of what appearance is, can and should be. Landscapes, not just on canvas but even wild vistas or prospects seen before us, are cryptograms of specific stages in artistic history, not natural history. Landscape painters show us emblems of ourselves, human being not natural being. So completely does the genre take us in that we are for the most part unconscious that landscape is the negation of nature. Perhaps nothing prevents us more from seeing nature and nothing limits our aesthetic experience of it more than the great tradition of landscape. The same should be said of landscape photography toowhether we are looking at others’ work or taking our own. We are like the character in the Truffaut film who has to frame everything like a camera between his fingers. Landscape photography is probably more difficult than painting. That is just its historical predicament: So easy and democratic is the technology, so difficult to rescue style from the oligarchy of advertising. Landscape painters, according to Louis Aragon, ‘even the most gifted of them—became true ignoramuses' (Benjamin, 2002, 241). This began when they saw that the camera was a competitor and they tried not to do things the way it did. Perhaps now this is what those milky stream images are about. Perhaps photographers saw the camera as too easy too and tried not to do what it did. Peter Dombrovskis, whose best photographs turn away from landscape views to meditation on nature’s minutiae, apparently did not have a high regard for Rock Island Bend. Even without milky water, such images are degraded to the status of 189

advertising. They are the stock in trade of tourism, environmental rhetoric, promotions, education, and national art. Like visual muzak, they appear on glossies with that tedious sheen that deflects all our idle glances away from what little is left of their subject matter and into a realm of redundant messages so instantly recognized that you can’t bear or bother looking any further. Your eyes can glaze over. There is nothing to see anymore. You cant even light a fire with the stuff, or mulch a patch of weeds. Any message of such iconography is subdued by the iron hand of conformity. The wilderness calendar shall have rugged landscapes mellowed by morning or evening light. The latest car shall be displayed before a backdrop of sea cliffs or wide brown land. The stream shall be naturalized by milk. Of course, we were all postmodern once, and maybe this would all be just good old postmodern nature by now, but we still yawn and take it seriously enough not to risk doing away with it because we expect it and expect that everyone else expects it. Certainly, no one seems nostalgic yet for all this old pop cultural naturalism. We still think it’s timeless Nature, rather than yesterday’s Nature. We are not game to grumble about it because that would not be being positive. Someone might think we are sick of nature itself. It would only encourage them to trash more of it. That is the trouble with natureit’s just natural and givenso the images of it start to be taken that way too. Worse though, unless it is rediscovered in the flesh, nature itself starts to be a yawn. When, as in Dombrovskis later work, photography meditates on natural detail, the effect is still not one of intimacy but of sublime apprehension. The beauty remains that of something seen with an estranged rather than a familiar eye. It still owes its sensibility to the genre of wilderness photography, a genre in which Peter Timms (2004) diagnoses rugged, anti-intellectual inclinations, as a result of which it exhibits both a resistance to the less salutary excesses of fashionable artworld innovationalism and a ‘certain degree of stagnation.’ These images of plants and rocks and lichens might scarcely escape the iconographic gravity of advertisements for the natural environment. Yet the subject matter, although it promises intimacy and familiarity, at first disguises and then reveals something about nature even in its minutiae: that it is almost terrifying in its unconcern for others. This is worth showing. It is still something astonishing about nature, and for that matter, humans. Perhaps it is time for landscape no longer to be view or prospect or generic formality. Art has often rescued itself by rescuing the object, and with it subjectivity, form the burden of convention. Perhaps it could turn to the details of natural historywhere once it illustrated those of religious, classical or social narrativeand do it using the sensuous potential of empirical science, although nature documentaries and wildlife photography might suggest this is a vain hope. Perhaps the dissociation of scientific from artistic sensibility, in painters, photographers and viewers, makes landscape art no longer possible beyond its now aging customary forms, and therefore no longer possible as new and therefore, as modernity demands, as art. Except, predicaments like this are just what original art gets us out of or makes a virtue of and only in a way that 190

we least expect until, in retrospect, the solution seems to have been waiting to happen.

Cinema Landscape Reviewers of Australian movies like to say, landscape is a character. To someone lost for words it’s a cliché that must seem an insight. When Australians tell themselves they need a film culture that tells stories about themselvesanother clichéthey seem to think landscape tells that story. Sure, landscape asks to reveal its natural and cultural history but Australian cinema seldom lets it. As visual propaganda it ends up being a consolation. When reviewers can only praise the excellence of the performances, the sets or the special effects we should suspect that this is just consolation for disappointment in the film. It is the same when they praise the landscape cinematography. Everything that damages landscape photography damages landscape cinematography, for cinematography is bound not only by convention but by money. Even cinema’s gift of motion does not rescue it. Although landscapes do move and movies show movement, it is usually the camera that moves. The camera tracks or pans or zooms. The landscape remains big, still and timeless. That is the image of the nature of Australian landscape. It is always a view, seldom a place, never a character. It is never so intimate or responsive. At most it broods. In the iconography of Australian cinema it is the marketing opposite of quirky, which is reserved for the suburban comedy. Apart from being view, landscape is emblem. It is unselfconsciously like landscape in an ad for the latest car or tourist destination. Cinema that uses landscape as if it was made to give us gorgeous images, or worse, images of the nation, robs landscape and cinema at the some time. For a quarter of a century though, Australian audiences have been admiring Australian landscape cinematography, mainly just proud of ‘the image of Australia’. Perhaps the worst moment in the cinematography of Australian landscape is in Priscilla Queen Of The Desert where costume and decorative backdrop combine with quirkiness in a confused promo for patriarchal schmaltz in drag. The compositions seem to come from a pattern book of received imagery, each selected as a prescribed symbol and seldom blessed by the intimacy of what Raymond Durgnat (195) called the ‘bundles of feelings’ associated with the characters’ experiences. Landscape may only show nature as alien, undifferentiated oblivion, at once decorative backdrop and symbolic. Its talent insulted, no wonder it broods. In Picnic At Hanging Rock (Peter Weir, 1975) it was spooky bush Gothic. There is a tradition of bush panic in Australian culture and the superstition that generates it might be fitting subject matter, but the sad old attempt to add a dash of Gothic and forge a bit more Australian meaningfulness and mythicality from it is little more enlightened than the superstition itself. In Japanese Story (Sue Brooks, 2003) and Rabbit-Proof Fence (Philip Noyce, 2002) landscape is the automatic signifier of wide brown land and alien desert heart, pure nationalist 191

iconography. Perhaps it was foreign for the Japanese man in the former and the stolen girls in the latter. However any geological insight or passion from the geologist in the former would have dissolved the brooding mystique. Any from the tracker in the latter would have dissolved his as well as the land’s. In each of these cases the elements of nature are shuffled round as pieces in the film’s emblematics resulting in varying degrees of deformation to the reality that was actually being imprinted on the film. Of course cinema can hardly deny the emblematic potential of its images. Sometimes I do have to admire landscape, as in the wild ranges through which Jimmy Blacksmith flees to his tragic end, or in the wide-open soundscape of the roadside in Ivan Sen’s Beneath Clouds (2002). And it comes as a relief to see a film like Rolf de Heer’s The Tracker (2002) or Rachel Perkin’s One Night The Moon, which are frankly melodramatic and emblematic in character, landscape, painting and song. There is a lot to be said for Andre Bazin’s insight regarding the most fulfilling gift of cinema—namely the way it can just show the moving physical world as it is, as if there was no deforming intervention between the thing shown and the viewer. All that is emblematic can and will then form for itself anyway. In Australian cinema though we don’t see the physical detail for the big emblems. They come first and take over.

The TV Ecologist; Or Nature On TV They take for granted that, in the postmodern world, TV has supplanted nature. —J. Hoberman, 1987 We know the rules. TV nature documentary rates best when it is about charismatic megafauna; remarkable photography should be set off by hackneyed voiceover; the entertainment should turn natural history into historical romance or an investigation mystery in order to sell 19th century science (evolution) or 20th century pop ecology (biodiversity, conservation) or a national advertisement (glossies that move). The take home message is that there are killer whales out there, or gorillas or polar bears. This is educating the community. I heard an environmental theorist make this claim about the edifying function of nature TV. I suspect she was right insofar as this does appear to be a conscious ambition, and not one of the other 9 out of 10 unspoken or unconscious ones—which can include nationalism and lifestyle. It is a sad ambition though. If this is the primary function of nature docoes, then it seems to be showing people out there in the community that nature isn’t out there with them but somewhere else, and perhaps a little bit in the past. Although I cant go to the Arctic or Galapagos or Patagonia (and although I am glad the Parers did) I would prefer to see (as I did once in a doco whose title now escapes me) scientists working out the fruit dispersal ecology 192

of small rainforest marsupials, or describing the ecology of a place that was close to their heart and the object of long and curious observation (as in Places of the Heart on the ABC’s Reality Bites). Instead there are great barrier reefs of nature docoes on exotic tourist destinations and megafauna spectacles and none on the nature of Kur-ing-gai, which is just outside the backdoor of 15% of Australians, or on the nature just out the back door of most of the viewers. Shot in some unidentified elsewhwere or some iconic Kakadu or Kimberley, nature docoes are tales of deracinated wonder or national tourism strategies, not natural history. They are feats of photography, but abstracted from nature. Photographers produce astonishing images. Someone then compiles a magazine from it and a script is dashed off as if to patch the images together or to fill the silence. All the brilliant conceptual content in the images is sacrificed to the conceptual ambitions of a brochure. It is not an essay in natural history or ecology. It is televisual muzak. TV is vision, but we are told this so often we had better treat it with suspicion. Actually, TV rivals the second commandment in the bans it places on images. It represses vision with the ruthlessness of serious neurosis. Think of the taboo on maps and diagrams. David Attenborough seldom says where he is, let alone shows a detailed map. TV maps are few and far between, they are mean in what they show, and they must only last long enough to be not contemplated or scrutinized. They must only last long enough to be experienced as mere images of maps, not to be read as a maps. TV is supposed to be about images, not about reading. Why this secret ban on knowledge, all this mystification. Is it to protect the secrecy of locations? A freemasonry of nature photographers? Is it all to make it palatable to the kiddies? Perhaps maps don’t move enough. Perhaps, because of the small screen and the big pixels, the map can show Africa in green and maybe the course of the Congo in blue but never the dot in red where they are filming these chimpanzees. Is it that TV nature is not vision but only feats of photography? Is it also to protect a certain fictive licence that the doco makers like to exploit? Maps are an index, pinning images to the world and reducing a show’s freedom to move unnoticed between locations and make up the usual trite story about the vision. Drawing maps forces detail to intrude, reduces the flexibility of production, and constrains the story. It properly acknowledges ecology’s proper spirit of place. Producers, however, know they know that viewers don’t want detail. TV censors images the way it censors almost any non-redundant information. Just as engineers build a lot of redundancy into signals to ensure the accurate transmission of information, TV producers build a lot of redundancy into TV to ensure easy transmission of an easy message. In this the programs are the same as the ads. Ads work better maintaining known product sales than flogging new product. TV is mainly about being knowing in a relaxing, stimulated sort of way, and not about getting to know something you didn’t already know. And what I know is that only a fool would watch TV nature docoes expecting to learn more than that there are big animals called killer whales out there. 193

By the way, as well as being vision, TV can show vision that moves. Better still, just as the microscope released us from the confines of human spatial perception, slow-motion and time-lapse give access to the non-human timescale of most of natural history. They can reveal the very fast and the very slow. We can see not just flowers blooming but, as in the BBC’s The Private Life of Plants, how busy plants are and how slowly and purposefully they are hastening: the growth of a blackberry is revealed to be also movement and with a goal. Population dispersal is so slow as to be counterintuitive; evolution even more so. If we cannot film them, we can animate them by using the conceptual power of a diagram that moves and changes. Enter the technology of computer-generated images. Just as TV nature shows feats of photography, computer animation can show feats of animation. What goes on show turns out to be a half acknowledged natural history of the technology itself. Widespread praise for the images in the Walking With Dinosaurs series, seemed to ignore the clumsy gaits of the Cretaceous players for no better reason than that the images were state of the art, as advertised, and teams of scientists and technicians had worked on them. The praise ignored the clumsy execution as blissfully as the TV technophobes ignored the opportunity to depict Mesozoic evolution not as historical romance but as a counterintuitive history waiting to be rendered comprehensible, even to children. The only historically revealing thing in the show was that the digital images looked like they have been exhumed from a time capsule buried during the early Silicon period in the Late Postmodern. As for the plotsscenarios I suppose they arenatural history becomes sci-fi, sit-com or soap, with a pretentious voiceover. Geological timescale and a Pangaean landscape (It mostly looks like the retouched New Zealand of Lord Of The Rings) become grandiose backdrop to personal evolutionary dramas played out like scenes from a bad video game crossed with The Bold and the Beautiful and Hammy Hamster’s Adventures on The Riverbank. This stuff was supposed to appeal to the kiddies, and give junior dinosaur lovers the world over a bit of authorized palaeobiology in palatable fast-food, video game form, while their parents could nod knowingly about advances in image technology and be assured their offspring were not just off the streets but giving the play station a rest. Wouldn’t it be nice to have a bit of old newsreel from the Cretaceous; even some stills; even a fossil and a bit about the science of palaeozoology or evolutionary biology rather than this day in the life of the extinction of Rex the Tyrannosaurus? It gets better. We get a reality TV take on nature too. In a British documentary called Going Ape, living with chimps is pitched as a primate slant on Survivor. The talenttwo missing links from the genus Homorun with chimpanzees, living off chimp food and not even carrying water bottles because chimps apparently don’t. The pitch is: Chimps are so like us that if we weren’t such thirsty wimps we could live like them. The show demonstrated that the adventurers shared more genes with chumps than chimps, but also that you can sell a nature doco on the most craven of pretexts.

194

Nature’s other place on TV is in the news, not that nature is often news. Mostly it’s timeless and there is nothing much new about it. It is just nature and it is out there doing pretty much what nature does most of the time and year after year. Besides, only vision is news, the corollary of which is that only vision becomes history. Tidings come second, if at all. So only when it is spectacular in its disasters and its aftermaths, is nature the talent: earthquakes, tsunamis, floods, storms, droughts and fires. If it is caught live nature becomes as good as sport, for sport is made-for-TV history as it happens—the dream news of televisual culture. All TV news—and therefore history, and therefore natural history, in the age of TV—aspires to the condition of sport. Otherwise nature news is just a quirky filler like human interest, or it is a public service or a poetic essay for late in the bulletin, or it’s not on the news but on the 7:30 Report as a story on environmental politics that they have got in the can for one night this week when they don’t have to cross to the Prime Minister, or to Washington, or Djakarta, or, for that matter, to the background on the bushfires that headed the night’s news. I heard someone say that they had built a replica of Shakespeare’s house that was more like Shakespeare’s house than Shakespeare’s house was. Well TV nature is more like nature than nature is. This is the case on two levels. First, the places and animals on the docoes, or the natural disasters on the news look more like nature than nature does when you are there. Not much nature appears to be happening when you are there because it is just being natural (that is why the photographers have to hang around waiting for ages). We know this because, when we actually see this nature that is more like nature than nature is, we say things like ‘It was like watching a movie’ or ‘It was like you see on TV.’ Second, what we are seeing and being knowing about when we watch nature on TV is mostly the nature of TV itself. When people say that we should not separate ourselves off from the natural world, that we and it and the whole are all connected, and that what we are doing is impacting on nature so badly because we are part of nature but we are forgetting that we are, I don’t think that they mean that TV is nature, but that is only because they, with the aid of many social institutions and much ecological trompe l’oeil, have made quite an effort to forget this and as a result they are not thinking anywhere near as holistically as nature actually is. TV is more like the hurricane or killer whale or polar bear than it is like the images it shows of these things. In the world of culture, TV is a force of nature. In its own effects on the world, particularly on human populations and their habitat, it is as ecological as the weather. It is like climate change, sweeping over us relentlessly, and unlike the greenhouse gas induced phenomenon, its existence and effects are pretty much indisputable and already faits accomplis. So since TV is nature in tooth and claw itself and most of us are television ecologists with PhDs or equivalent in the discipline of its natural history, and we observe the small screen with sublime knowing eyes, I think we can say that only a dysfunctionally close, myopic, scrutinizing viewerlike someone with autistic tendencies or someone with a hell of a lot of sophisticated-high-cultural195

criticism equipment or moral-panic equipmentis going to not turn it off or not just leave it on and do something else, and instead, look at it in just the right unironic, unsublime, unbeing-knowing way (and we can all do this too or, as they say, role play it, because it is just another part of being knowing) needed to see past everything else and peer down through all the recursions of TV’s wildly self-referential nature to something like the natural environment as it actually is or even just to an image of it. And mostly, that natural environment is just not going to be there, not just because the nature doco is just one modest genre among many more banally immoderate ones, or because nature on the news is just one very occasional bit of vision, but because when you stare down through recursion on recursion, and through images of images, what is there is not much more than a grain of nature in the oyster of the medium and, indeed, once it has completed its function of irritating the televisual system into its immune response, the grain can mostly just disappear. All that is left is the after image of a killer whale and the magnificent autoimmune response of TV to itself. If TV has supplanted nature, it has supplanted it like the shopping mall has. It has supplanted it as something to do, or as a place to stroll, or as something to leave on in another room, or to turn off. It has supplanted it recreationally not ontologically. Even then, nature as in the natural environment is still a lifestyle choice. Ontologically TV, like the mall or the killer whale, is nature too. Like the killer whale or the ant it is approximately amazing.

12.2 …As The Image Of Australia The Bush, Or The Nature Of Australia Explainers of Australia to Australians sometimes ponder the canonization of Ned Kelly. Perhaps they cannot really believe Ned’s status. After all, his story is a bit dull—more the stuff of the remaindered pop literary novel than the legend that a people cannot help but recite. All too aware of the nation’s foundation well after the great age of myths and in the empty age of humdrum modern history, Australian mythographers imagined they had little else to work with. There was an empty landscape out there and someone had to be made to appear in it. Sidney Nolan did the traditional, profound artistic thing: he fashioned a figure to fill the void. He had to make myth because myth, like war, is what is great and profound. Nation is the handy, profound theme lying around in the junkyard of themes, and myth, like war, is the expected thing for a nation. So, although perhaps not intending any national mythography himself, Nolan put a figure in the empty landscape of, variously, Australian culture, Australian mythopoesis, and the Australian bush. Robert Drewe, Peter Carey, Gregor Jordan and many a would-be mythographer have followed suit, spinning yarns and turning profits, all doing their bit in various states of national selfconsciousness, to build the thing up, until the myth making itself has become a 196

social phenomenon, a media event, a myth in itself. So the real great Australian myth is not the Ned Kelly story, or Gallipoli, but the myth-making, the quest for spiritual profundity, the quest to fill simultaneously the empty heart of Australia, the empty inspiration of the artist, the empty page or the empty screen. The emptiness could be spiritual, existential, or just plain idle. Ned is not so much an Irish-Australian Robin Hood, a defender of battlers, a rebel, a tragic hero, or a symbol of Australians’ much mythologized ideology of underdogs, larrikins, and anti-authoritarians, as he is a placeholder, a cardboard cut-out, just as Nolan depicted him, a cut-out who has grown and grown in just the way mythological figures do, because of the peculiar selection pressures for national self mythologization at work in Australian society. If Ned hadn’t existed then Australia would have had to invent himand it did. The bush is just like Ned: something that we might find a bit dull really, but we need it to make ourselves seem interesting. We need it as the backdrop to our Neds. We need the image of nature for the sake of Australia’s image. People want certain words to be takenor mistakenin many ways. It might be a way of making something big, many faceted and mythic. In one of its guises, the bush can refer to any bit of native vegetationwhat is also called the natural environment if you need to sound technical. In particular, it is used to refer to any bit of useless, hard-leaved vegetation growing on infertile, uncultivated soilssometimes called scrubor to vegetation that is not rainforest (also called scrub). In another sense, the bush can refer to rural societywhat political language took to mincing up in the phrase rural and regional Australia. In its most general sense, the bush is a term for everything that is not the city, socially or biologically. As the saying goes: Sydney or the bush. In this sense it matches the etymology of the word country, the old European term that was to designate what is not (as in contra) the city. In Australia country used to mean rural and regional Australia before that catchphrase became the way to sound inclusive, and before bush took hold of urban namedroppers wanting to sound au fait with bush lore. Bush, like Ned, is schmaltzed rough Irish to the genteel Anglo-Scottish country. Like mate, it is often larded with an over-familiarity that sounds ingratiating, over-familiar, patronising or patrioticbut it can’t answer back with a line like …and don’t call me mate! Nowadays country is used by Aborigines for their country, and by more cautious non-Aborigines trying to avoid landscape because landscape is supposed to sound like a European imposition on Aboriginal country. Land is variously what people own, what Aborigines belong to, what farmers are on, the bush (in all its senses), or country (in all of its senses). Landscape is what painters do, what land managers work on, or the scale (i.e. landscape scale) at which they would like to imagine us all doing their work. Countryside is something in England or Tuscany or somewhere. Only sometimes do bits of it turn up in Australia. There is no doubt that the bush can be plundered for the mythologization of the nation’s spiritual predicament. And it is no wonder that a particular version 197

of the way society reflects geography took hold of the national imagination, namely the suspicion that, like the continent itself, Australian culture has an empty heart; that it is, at heart, a desert devoid of myth. The red centre, the dead centre. So it has seemed to European eyes. The centre, the heart, of this continent remains little known, threatening even, to those of us who have clung for dear life on its coastal fringes. It feels unnerving to be this far from the ocean. Ignorant of the geographic heart of the land, have we at the same time blinded ourselves to its spiritual heart? Many have written this or something like it. It is a traditional way of saying something that passes for profound analysis of Australian society. It is also a guiding and self-fulfilling myth. The nation must struggle to face its spiritual void, and not just, like me, cling for dear life to these coastal fringes. Think of Voss, or the historical accounts of explorers, or all those paintings of landscape that are never just nature pictures but sublime expeditions in spiritual colonizationglorious negotiations with, comings to term with, and capturings of some true Australia. Nowadays heroic tourists still re-enact the explorers quests in their travels; and they re-enact the artistic quest in their photos. Meanwhile those coastal fringes remain as little known as the rest of the place. Less. They are the unconscious nature that we drive by or fly over on our way to the holiday. The bush as spiritual void or as something dangerous to come to terms with or as a kind of Arcadia—these are all romantic delusions. There are few objects so resolutely kept unconscious in Australia as the bush. Perhaps only the beach rivals it. It’s done by constant exposure. Knowledge is assumed by everyone as a national birthright, and it is understood and explained by a litany of platitudes. A topic for all seasons, the bush is always ready for slotting into the weekend magazines as the object of careless, assured, knowing articles on bushfires, bemused foreign tourists, the world’s deadliest snakes, the dead heart and the wide brown land. Nothing is deemed better to demonstrate any topic’s intellectual worthiness than a display of its relevance in the interminable discourse of national definition. The bush ceases to have biological and geophysical substance and becomes a cipher about Australia maturing as a nation. Pressed for a winning environmentalist argument, the ecologist Hugh Possingham suggested that a compelling reason for conserving biodiversity is the national one of forging an identity by developing an intimate relation with the bush. He was falling back on an old standby, patriotism as the last refuge of justification. Tim Flannery, in an Australia Day address about the land called it ‘the only thing we all, uniquely, share in common. It is at once our inheritance, our sustenance, and the only force ubiquitous and powerful enough to craft a truly Australian people.’ Geography is supposed to be destinybut in Australia it somehow hasn’t been yet. Perhaps because Australia is many places and

198

Australians don’t share it all in common. Or perhaps we are just modern and living somewhere else. There are some such as the legal academic Helen Irving who say that calls like Flannery’s for an Australian culture grounded in Australian nature ‘feeds a distrust of the foreign’. Irving’s bit of off-the-rack critique appeared in a semiglossy that runs a lot of lifestyle cultural criticism between uppish-market car, holiday, furniture and tech ads, the Fairfax Good Weekend, (1/2/3). As an argument it is specious enough to get people in. Irving uses the argument as a lemma to singing the praises of a supposedly maligned Australian city culture. In order to praise the city she makes a straw dummy of the bush advocates. Her argument turns on a sleight of hand: having got readers to suspend disbelief in the fact that no one is being forced to choose between Sydney and the bush, Irving concludes that ‘we should not be forced to choose between them.’ One thing is for sure though, what Possingham, Flannery and Irving all share is that pronoun we. And it’s not we the people, it’s we Australians. I can’t see why, whoever we are, we would want to defend Sydney or the bush as merely Australian or merely ours. Natives; Or Nature In The Garden By natives I don’t mean indigenous people or people born in and of a particular place. I mean plants. But not quite plants in and of themselves and not quite plants native to a particular area. In Quadrant once, Leonie Kramer chastised multiculturalism for being a concept and an ideology whose very name and concept was as absurd conceptually and ideologically as, say, something called horticulturalism. However natives are an instance of horticulturalism, although, if it is any consolation, perhaps not a very multicultural horticulturalism. Natives are more a kind of horticultural or environmental nationalism than a selection of plants of entirely local provenance or in proportions that reflect the given proportions of the natural vegetation composition at a particular site. To make this quite clear: in Sydney, which has been built on some of the most beautiful heath in the known universe, and where plenty of people have sung the praises of, declared allegiance to and prided themselves on native gardens, no one has ever planted a garden of natives that might reproduce the wonder that their suburb has obliterated. Well, maybe someone has, but if so, I would need to see it before I would be convinced. A native gardena truly native garden, rather than just nativeswould demand of the gardener a ruthlessly purist horticulturalism and a willingness to get rid of nearly everything that was in the garden at first, a heartless determination to insult all one’s well-meaning (or sometimes I suspect garden-manipulative) friends and refuse all those gifts of cuttings, pot plants, prized hand propagated seedlings (and from native seed too, collected ‘on our holiday’) and the like. Instead of a set menu, gardening is a bit like a bring-aplate barbecueat best with a theme like ‘Mediterranean’ or ‘SE Asian’ or ‘Indian’, or in the case of a native garden ‘Australian’. 199

Gardens are like families: you can’t choose them; and most are a bit unhappy in much the same way. Gardeners are mostly bowerbird types who can’t forever resist that grevillea from Queensland with the mauve flowers, that boronia from Victoria, or that flowering rainforest tree from Mullumbimby. Everyone is a sucker for a little deviant something sometime, and in gardening deviance is straight. There are a lot of good native gardens, but like most Australian gardens their sensibilityacknowledged or notis kind of camp. Outside of being an absolute zealot, a mad-eyed fundamentalist or a bio-Nazi it would be impossible to mount the single-minded vigilance and evil herbicidal genius needed to plant and police the purist native garden of your absolutely unalienated pleasure. And even then, in Sydney say, the urban transformation of famously sandy soils into a complex irrigated anthropogenic geology of topsoil-imported, subdivision-levelled, horizon-shuffled, run-off-enriched, garden-fertilized substrate would make most heathland xeromorphs turn up their leaves trying to get their roots out of the eutrophic concoction. So show me that garden of Sydney flora in Sydney and I will expect to find a maker who exhibits one or all of the above psychopathological traits, and a pleasure garden that is more a sadist’s den, a reign of terror or a state of emergency. Ah, but I would love to see such a thing. More than the most pristine wilderness. And if the native garden is a national thing it is, like the nation, a bit multicultural. So the native garden will have that jacaranda from South America (‘We couldn’t cut it down’ or ‘I always thought jacarandas were native’), those camellias from China (‘I have always loved camellias’), gladdies (‘The bulbs keep coming up, and you have got to admit…’), an orange or a lemon (‘You’ve got to eat’), lawn (somewhere for the kids to play and still more national than natives), weeds (of course) and the red bottlebrush, the five cultivars of grevillea (to attract the birds), the small ‘flowering’ gum, the teatree, the ambitious stab at a waratah or a Christmas bush or a banksia from WA (usually at some stage of unsuccess), andmandatory now on first plantingthe woodchip mulch streamed off into the gardening and landscaping market from shiploads of chipped eucalypt forests that once grew in a native forest as remote in mind and geography as possible. Yes, that is the native garden; and you don’t have to water it, and it looks after itself. Bush Tucker Pablo Neruda began his autobiography declaring that those who had not walked through the great Araucaria forests of Chile had not walked on earth. I would say something similar about eating the Araucaria nuts of the Bunya Mountains. Out of the heavy green spiked cones that drop like maces from these great Gondwanic conifers come fresh cream coloured nuts, as plump as bantam eggs, as fragrant as lychees, as sweet as chestnuts, dense and waxy. Proceeding autobiographically: one way I was led into the bush was by way of my mouth, by taste. The brilliant flower strewn heaths of the Sydney sandstone would not be considered the most fruitful country, but tasting the 200

little green fruits of the five corner and the ten corner, sipping flowery nectar from banksias, grevilleas and mountain devils, nipping a leaf of sweet sarsaparilla in my front teeth and sucking the bitter sweet as I walked, or carrying a skinned geebung in my mouth for an hour and sucking at its matted chocolate bitter sweetness were all part of finding my way into that country. These are all walking foods, things idly chewed and sucked while doing something else. My guides on these walks were Joan and Alan Cribb (1976). Blessed by unappreciation, no one thinks to commodify them and they therefore remain in a kind of paradise of unforeclosed bounty. Not like that peculiar market culture of bush tucker. From out of the intersecting social pressures of commodifiabilityperceived entrepreneurial opportunity, ease of propagation, culture, harvesting, distribution, market demand, Australianness, and culinary convenience, all with token nods towards Aboriginal cuisinesa strange postmodern culture of bush foods evolved in the last decades of twentieth century. Lemon myrtle, wattle seed, rosella jam (not actually native), riberries, crocodile and ‘coat of arms’ (a national variation on ‘surf and turf’ combining the emblematic kangaroo and emu) are all more or less tasty commodities that evoke this culture. Fungi—forest mushrooms, puffballs, russulas, wood ears— don’t stand a chance. Too ephemeral, too hard to identify, too dangerous. Native yams, wombat berries and orchid tubers, too meager. Midgim berries, too small to harvest. Cobra or jidee, the shellless wood boring estuarine mollusk, too slimy, too hard to harvest. Scrub nettle, stings too much. Seaweed, not Japanese enough. Bush lemons, passionfruits, guavas—all growing feral in the Bellinger valley—and weedy greens like amaranth, not Australian enough. Bunya nuts, too long to grow, too hard to shell, too much trouble. Strange that Macadamia nuts are seldom thought of as bush food. Likewise seafood. It is always kangaroo, croc, lemon myrtle, bush tomatoes and wattleseed. It’s always anti-regional because it proceeds from those nationalist ideas of the bush or Australia being all one place and all marketable as a package. It is always postmodern because the uses and recipes have all been made up for the last book. There is no thousand years of cultural selection stored in a particular dish. Instead it always nods in the direction of Aboriginal food but prefers to plate a roo with drizzles of riberry rather than throw a whole beast on the coals and divide the meat and offal among those present. So there a couple of bush foods I would just like to praise. One is the native raspberry or Rubus rosifolius. Just rubus will do. It gives off an extraordinary musky scent when you brush through its low green prickly foliage. A Dunghutti acquaintance told me his mother used the aromatic tea made from the leaves for treating bellyache. They can form a dense cover in moist forest clearings, initially colonizing by seed and eventually establishing and shooting up from rhizomes and growing to a metre high. In a succession of regeneration that followed the weeding of lantana in the bottom of a gully, it took five years for them to become the dominant species. They came after the ground ferns and before perennial herbs gave way to tree and vine canopy. They flower best after 201

rain in spring or autumn. The bright red fruits that follow the white rosy flowers are regarded as kid stuffcolourful but insipid, the sweetness falling far short of the red advertising, a little too seedy, something to taste or nibble while you walk past. They too fall into that unforeclosed bounty of the bushwalk category. You occasionally hear people recall having picked a saucepan-full in their childhood. Maybe their mothers cooked them. Recollection fond, current estimation indifferent. That seems to be as much of a culinary tradition as they have been deemed worthy. But that sweet scent of the foliage is there in the fruits too. It is like nothing else, except perhaps the essence of all the world’s rubus distilled into one species. That bright red does not advertise the simple gratification of sweetness but instead a complex aromatic pleasure. Cook this fruit or make jam from it and it has no equal. The other is the bunya. When I first began collecting the fallen cones from under the limited number of mature female bunyas I know, I used to worry that they would become a widely eaten item and that the source would dry up meeting a huge demand. Now I know that at the end of nearly every January I can find enough to keep the pantry full for the month or two they keep fresh. Quite a few people have tried bunyas. Some collect the odd cone. Few eat them. Fewer eat them in any volume. Most people who have tried them seem to have had them roasted, like chestnuts. They steam and pop and split and squeeze some of their flesh out of a woody shell that is about the thickness and texture of one layer of peeled ply. I guess the great crowds of people who used to travel to the Bunya Mountains in southern Queensland and who would climb the 50m trees using notched toe-holds so that they could get the earliest and most aromatic nuts would have eaten a lot this way. But the great indigenous bunya culture has passed on without much in the way of heirs. No one, say, roasts fresh bunyas and sells them in the street. Roasting them is something people might do once or twice with a few nuts as a curiousity at a late January barbecue. This is one way to cook Bunyas. It is bit unreliable: the nuts can explode if you don’t nick them before roasting; a lot of flesh can be lost; the flesh can dry and burn; the hot nuts are hard to peel. It is mainly a supposedly fun thing to do. I suppose opening the nuts is an issue. By issue I mean that it is a problem that hangs around at a level of consciousness just high enough to discourage efforts and just low enough for no-one to care: whenever the possibility of eating bunyas comes up the issue is lurking if not articulated. It is the same with most nuts, which are sold shelled. With a whole bunya cone in handall 4 to 9 kilos of itthe first thing is to break it up by removing each of the large green spirally arranged scales and stripping each woody, egg-shaped seed (the nut so called) from its housing in the scale. Given reasonable fertilization, one cone yields a basket of 70 or so nuts. I prefer then to split a fresh nut with a cleaver, length wise, and to remove the shell and red brown skin. I then poach the two halves for 20 minutes. If I want the nuts whole, I peel them with a strong hand and a pair of pliers, but this is slower. When a poached nut comes out of the pot it is smooth, dense, slippery, soft and aromatic, and ready to eat plain. When 202

you are ready for sacrilege you can toss it in macadamia or olive oil or butter and herbs. Most people think chestnuts when they try to think of how to use bunyas. The nuts are alike in requiring a similar amount of preparation, different in that the bunya is much more waxy than floury. Some might think of the jackfruit nut dishes of Sri Lanka and SE Asia. Bunyas are perfect poached in aromatic stocks with things like chili, turmeric, galingale, garlic, shallot, ginger, coconut and yes lemon myrtle. Or slowly cooked with meat and stock or tomatoes. The main thing is not to let them dry out. I have also chopped or ground the boiled nuts and used them in sausages, stuffing for poultry and pesto, and in sweet cakes, and nut loaves. The main problem in baking is the tendency for the meal to dry out and bake hard. You can also dry the nuts to a chalky consistency and grind them into a sweet, light flour—a bit like the pulse flours used in Indian and southern European cooking. I think the classic way to cook bunyas is like Brillat-Savarin’s unknown ‘new star’: it’s waiting to be discovered. But you need a culture to do that, and not the niche market culture of bush-tucker. So I am told, one guru of the niche read and reified its requirements by giving the sweetest plumpest bit of the bush no chance of taking off. So weighing in at a creamy, plump 8-10gm per peeled nut with 40% carbohydrate, 10% protein and 2% unsaturated fat, Bunyas are deemed to be too slow to grow, too unknown to consumers’ tastes, too risky to market, too difficult to open, too slow to harvest, and too low in returns to be considered as a commercial food crop. They’re not our culture. Last week I visited a bunya plantation—a couple of thousand trees on a couple of hectares up on the eastern Dorrigo. Last year two friends and I took what we wanted from tons and tons of bunyas left to sprout and rot on the ground. NSW State Forests grows wood not food. Who would want the things? When I got there last week they had cut down 90% of the trees. The wood I have heard is supposed to be the best native timber for guitar soundboards. Taking 90% of the males, and leaving 10% of them to fertilize the females would have been too much like finesse, way beyond the market driven incompetence of industrial forestry. Approximately 0% will end up in guitars. Meanwhile we can all just sprinkle lemon myrtle over everything and taste authentic Australiana that way. 12.3 …As Environmental Issue Apocalypse Yesterday, Or The Natural History Of The Future We are futurist to the point of bigotry —William Lines, 2003 The futuristic is the theology of modernity. Histories of the future are its guiding myths. Out of all proportion to its truth or beauty the future’s highly schematic, counterfactual history is nowadays told more often than that of any 203

other time and in more versions. In environmental culture, the future outdoes the pristine as the most imagined of times, and as even more imaginary. For there is nothing about it. The fact that the future is not a fact and that most of its histories are as wrong as holocaust denials should alert us that the primary function of future histories is anything but truth. At their best they are aids proper to teleological prudence: you acknowledge some future event or circumstance not as a necessity but as some possible end that you have to work at either avoiding or achieving. However future management has become a funded department of intellectual endeavour and, in the ruthless separation of social functions, social commentary, prediction, planning and action are severed from one another. They are separate divisions of labour, separate social systems. The histories of the future become disembodied myths, ads, daydreams or fantasies, their teleological design redeployed to some other function. They take on a life of their own. Most future histories are allegories of the more or less recent past told on the pretext of interpreting the present predicament, and indeed, we are so late finding out about the present that it is something we are obliged only dimly to foresee. Almost every invitation to provide some comment on the meaning of contemporary events is interpreted as an invitation to speculate on the future, to consider something like, but not quite the same as, fate or destiny, to reveal yourself as a prophet and take pride in your story before its proof. We are all familiar with the way that the news, when it becomes news commentary, degenerates into a history of the future. This follows from the intimate relation of time and meaning: the meaning of events is revealed in their outcome. To validate an interpretation of the present, a commentator borrows from the judgement of implacable history, but before it’s either implacable or history. It is an all too tempting transaction, far less risky than futures trading, because the debt may well be forgotten by the time history matures or fails to mature. Histories of the future try to buy prestige and maybe political change with cheap words. It’s advertising at its most obsessive—whether for the product or the teller—and it sounds depressingly (and predictably) like the last few years being writ larger, and again and again. The environmentalist canon has a future day of reckoning as an article of faith. Technophile future optimists are happy to announce a coming golden age, taking advantage of the future’s vast conditionality, since it allows them to loosen all ecological, technological and social constraints. Both sound like the nightmares from the past. Ten or fifteen years ago it was common to hear environmentalist celebrities warn of ecological catastrophe in ten years time. This precise dating was a worryand sometimes out of the mouths of scientists who would quibble about the accuracy of carbon dating or hedge guesses with phrases like sometime in the Pleistocene. The fact that it has not happened might have made environmentalism a thing of the pastwe and nature suffering all the more for it. The problem was that those great communicators of environmentalism were players in a political system where they could resist anything but political fashion and rhetorical temptation, and they resorted to good old apocalyptic 204

claims. They forgot that it takes more than fashionability to survive in modernity’s wilderness of fashion. Nothing in modernity can afford to become dated, and within 10 years they managed to make their future of nature seem so dated that only some kind of camp sensibility might have been able to revive it, at least until it comes back into fashion like the 1970s. They were far too ready to ignore their own advice about looking at the long term, and to exempt their rhetorical actions from their own precautionary principle. And they forgot about the nature of nature and the nature of the war waged against it. It is mainly a long, relentless tyranny of small decisions. It is a social phenomenon largely alienated from individual human intentions and arbitrary in defying our individual interests in good human habitat. Its support is widespread and often unconscious, and those who carry it out usually have an office and they generate cash from it to keep it going. They justify their actions by saying that the effects will be negligible, and any mess will be tidied up (they will replant the trees), and they have little trouble concealing the fact that immense historical changes to the cultural forms of nature are the algorithmic outcome of negligible actions repeated. It is second nature and we are all conspirators. Worse, as it proceeds, we warm to it, depend on it and live off it as we would if we had never had it so good, and we entertain ourselves with our histories of the futureabout that frog breast-stroking in the warming cauldron of history, the ecological rivets popping one by one from the fuselage of civilization, extinctions accruing like the debts of profligates, football fields of rainforest disappearing, transgenics breeding, plagues spreading, teratogens insinuating and oceans risingallegories that are as much about the teller’s mood as the time’s troubles in the form of sci-fi, urban myth, and Hollywood disaster entertainments for aficionados of apocalypse and post-apocalypse genres. It can all sound like the fun the faithful had with their interpretations of the Book of Revelation. It should be no surprise then that there are those who are skeptical of the warnings of environmentalism. There are debates over the existence (now or in future) of global warming, over what it will entail, over whether we can stop or ameliorate it, over whether we should, over whether there is an environmental crisis (now or in future), over whether extinctions are increasing and whether it matters anyway, over whether it is just a blip in the magnificent cavalcade of geological time, or over whether we have never had it so good. Bjørn Lomborg’s The Skeptical Environmentalist more the work of a prurient contrarian than a skepticattracted some dismal reactions. First (and most selfservingly) there were those who embraced the opportunity of a gospel justifying their own faith and misdeeds. Then there were those who demanded Lomborg’s official censuring by the Danish Committees on Scientific Dishonesty. A committee was convened and it deemed that Lomborg’s book did indeed ‘fall within the concept of scientific dishonesty’ and was ‘contrary to the standards of good scientific practice’, although they absolved Lomborg of dishonest ‘intent or gross negligence’. It did all seem a bit like an inquisition against 205

blasphemy in a discipline (i.e. empirical science) whose strength is that claims must openly face negation by good research and well argued denial. After all the book was just another diatribea constitutionally one-eyed genreeven if its rhetorical ploy, aided by a fanfare of footnotes and abetted by the Cambridge University Press imprimatur, was to look like a formidable scientific treatise. It is a ploy that is not exactly unknown among the ranks of environmentalists. Lomborg’s one-eyed contrariness towards evidence for environmental problems deployed a method of self-deluding selectiveness that is quite common in scientific culture, especially amongst propagandists for abstract skepticism. Indeed, it is not so different from the methodological skepticism used by the critics of scientific culture who have twigged that nothing that is merely empirical can be guaranteed by the hallmark of certainty. Maybe it might have been better for critics to entertain, and be entertained by, the book’s theses and to use them to sharpen wits instead of being provoked into a moral panic that the message would set back the environmental cause for years. The blasphemy panic demonstrated the way that rhetorical demands can distort scientific culture and nature culture: we either censor ourselves (as we do unhesitatingly when it comes to the aesthetics of nature) or would like to censor others. Third (most dismally) there were those unprepared risers to the bait who, in the face of Lomborg’s datacopia, were reduced to blithering calls for assertions of faith in some kind of Green credo of apocalypsethat we should believe we are coming to some terrible end but yes, if we have faith, we can do something about it. Lomborg’s work answers a common kind of controversialist desire. Perhaps it is a feature of contemporary society this cultural warrior stuff, the arse end of the debates between right and left. It fills opinion pieces and pulp non-fiction. People get their daily dose of gratification reading it. It stimulates by mild irritation, but the pleasure is slight, like squeezing pimples or scratching mosquito bites. The book was not so formidable or entertaining as its ads blurbed, and scarcely well enough argued to reward its reading. Environmentalism, so in need of a critique, did not get the criticism it deserved. Lomborg strings together a lot of iconic moments in the history of exaggerated environmentalist rhetoricthe Litany he calls itand shoots off at them in a scattergun approach that tries to look exhaustive. It is too broad, too shallow and too piecemealnot unlike a lot of environmentalist tracts, whether programmatic or managerial. Like all bad critique it defeats straw dummies. It refuses to entertain and thereby be confronted by the strength of its opponent’s thinking. In doing so it fails to marshal that strength in its own theses on what is wrong and what we should do, theses that are more promised than delivered anyway. In Lomborg’s chapter on biodiversity, beyond questioning exaggerated claims about the rate of species extinctions, Lomborg limits himself to a fly over discussion of the value of biodiversity and a quick critique of theories of island biogeography and habitat fragmentation. He asks but avoids answering 206

whether biodiversity is important. This is a hard question and deserves better than the glib answers, environmentalist or Lomborgian. He argues by formulating what he presumes to be accepted popular opinion (or the glib environmentalist opinion) on such a questionnamely that what matters for most people is big charismatic fauna rather than insects and bacteria, and that the latter might at best be valuable for drugs and as yet unknown economic uses. He then refutes these postulated popular opinions, by saying that mostly biodiversity is about insects and such, that people have been misled to think otherwise, and that there is not a lot a pharmacological or other economic value that can be easily retrieved from such biodiversity. He then implies dismissal of the whole questionwithout having actually mentioned the standard ecotechnocratic claim that biodiversity provides ecosystem services, such as, for example, the food chains and niches we need for natural resources. In his critique of theories of island biogeography and related theories of fragmentation he tries to take on what must be seen as the highly conjectural, empirically dubious theoretical basis for so much conservation practice and politics in Australia. He counters theories about the relation between area of habitat and species diversity (and extinctions) with a couple of counterexamples. There is no shortage of them, especially if one’s theory extrapolates from the biogeography of oceanic islands to that of isolated fragments on a single landmass—that is fragments of one type of community (such as rainforest) in a matrix of another type of community (such as agricultural grassland). Despite, and also because of, its applied ecological relevance, nothing makes ecology seem so dismal a science as its theories of fragmentation and their empirical counter-instances. Yet Lomborg botches his critique by underestimating what he is criticizing. In Puerto Rico he cites research that says in the colonial period 99% of the primary forest has been cleared, that some has been replaced by secondary forest, and that of 60 bird species 7 have become extinct. However, he says, there are now 97 species of birds. How fortunate! He does not say where they come from and leaves us to wonderor to assume that colonial forest disturbance has somehow created 44 new species or that 44 species from other places have invaded in the colonial period. Sooner than going to Lomborg’s source to seek the information his argument omits, I would prefer to help Lomborg mount the same argument about Australian mammals. There have been 10 extinctions (6%) out of the 146 species in 1788 when the First Fleet landed (Fox, 1995); but there are many more mammal species now when one counts the introductions that have gone feral. And for good measure, in the case of plants, there are about 100 extinct (0.5%) out of the 20,000 in 1788; but there are many more introduced weeds to more than replace them. There are about fifty new self-propagating species right outside my door. I must assume that Lomborg neglects to say of Puerto Rico what I have neglected so far to say of Australia: that although there are more species of mammals and plants on the continent, there are 10 fewer mammals on the globe. As far as Lomborg is concerned though, we mustn’t have needed

207

them. It all seems so far away from here in the tallowwood forest. I don’t think he mentions weeds at all. Meanwhile. Stories about the future always lack detail. This is true of the science fictions as well as the ecological models and the niggling environmentalist worries about the future. The detail is the most unpredictable stuff, and, of course as detail it is merely mere and not important in the big picture. This makes images of the future variously simplistic, schematic, and strangely archaic lookingeven futuristic visions, utopian and dystopian, are hideously lacking in the cultural and natural complexity of contemporary life. Because nature is so dazzling in its particularity, the future in its lack of detail looks denatured. I cannot think of a futuristic science fiction that was full of wild nature. It is as if the very genre of history of the future is conveniently predenaturalized just for these allegories of ecological dystopia. I don’t believe in optimism or pessimism. I can never remember which is better: only half empty or only half full. Whether you are an optimist or pessimist seems irrelevant. Self-styled optimists seem a bit desperate. So-called pessimists seem to have to remain cheerful to help the optimists forget their desperation. Choosing one or the other seems like no more than swearing to an article of faith, and I reject the faith that foists these categories on us. It only brings environmentalism back to the vexed but banal question: Whether, given the talk of apocalypse and faith, there is too much religiosity or spirituality about environmentalism or at least little too much zealotry. Plenty have said so: some, who in what they see as a sadly faithless age, envy the green faith; others who worry that it is a problem in a fortunately faithless age. Frankly, things just look pretty bleak already to me. There is a lot of wreckage piled up already and things are scarcely getting better. And I can’t worry too much about the future when we haven’t got over the past. Citing apocalyptic history of the future as the ground of environmentalism is useless theologizing a lot of the time. It is a bit like that disembodied voice long ago in Roman times proclaiming the death of the Great God Pan. The death of nature has been predicted, proclaimed and happened many times. It was apocalypse yesterday for a lot of nature, and a lot of people are quite used to the post-apocalypse world. They have grown to quite like it. They have known nothing better, weeds are just another bit of biodiversity, things are going all right, and we will take care of things through good old human ingenuity. That’s progress. The forests of the Bellinger are full of the scare tissue of lantana, privet and camphor laurel. It is just a pitylike the Murray being full of carp or the river red gums dying or there being a bit too much salt in places or there not being much grassy white box woodland any more, but that is all water under the bridge and a small price to pay for modern prosperity. People who worry about it are told to move on and lighten up.

208

Selling Nature By the late 20th century a distinct and unprecedented discipline of environmental philosophy had developed. It had a long cultural descent, paralleled in several societies, and in its latest modification it had all the features it needed to colonize and propagate itself in the society of late modernity: it described and theorized the sensed urgency of the ecological predicament; it worked at providing reasons justifying the practices of the green social movement; it was able to articulate a political program for the green movement; it was able reflect on and generate its concepts within the existing social environment of popular and academic culture; and it was able to supply its thought according to the demands and standards that had come to characterize those of the discipline called philosophy. One of the more persistent features of this environmental philosophyone that might almost have seemed like a defining featurewas a search for the true ground of environmental ethics. This was typical philosophy. You keep questioning reasons until you arrive at the ultimate reason. Ethics has chronically been diverted by metaphysics, and in this search for ultimate reasons you plum the metaphysical depths for the ultimate metaphysical or ethical principle. It had all the features of philosophy in its often naïve but enduring quest for first principles. It is enduring because it finds a recurring psychic environment, in each human generation, namely that of the naïve philosophical psyche that needs to seek reasons and can do so obsessively at least until it recognizes its own behaviour as a proper and new object for scrutiny. Someone might then see that their metaphysical needs are little more than those of winning at argument, or of no longer being discomforted by doubt and uncertainty, or of finding that life is deep and meaningful after all, indeed deep and meaningful in a way that is comfortingly consistent with and justifies their other interests, or of getting out of the torment of obsessive questioning by reaching a final answer. One of the most successful and popular lines of environmental philosophy, the one that in opposing itself to anthropocentric ethics has been dubbed ecocentrism and that includes, at its most ontologically profound, deep ecology, was successful because it was so well adapted to some or all of these needs. William Lines (2003, 94) grounds a critique of the Australian Greens, on the ecocentric principle that they have fallen into thinking we conserve nature for people’s sake, whereas we should conserve it for its own sake. ‘ “Maximizing human welfare” is not the chief concern of conservationists who have a broader, more radical and more generous view of protecting all life. They seek to save nature from humans, not for humans.’ Lines is by no means the first to feel and gratify the need to supply such a principle, but it is the weakest point in his critique. The need to cite the most profound and general foundation produces the most abstract and least solid notion. The hoped-for killer argument is dead on its feet. Firstly, to cite the notion of doing something for humans, implies that we all share understanding of what for humans means. Yet 209

this is anything but agreed. That’s what the antagonism between nature and its sacrifice is all about: what is for Lines is very different from what is for one of nature’s exploiters. To assume otherwise rigs the argument by premising it with its conclusion. It puts the cart before the horse. Much the same would apply to the notion of saving nature for nature’s sake. Like humankind, nature does not have any self-same sake, nor, for that matter is there any reconciled totality of all life. Even less than human society, is nature or life a matter of unitary selfinterest. Taking almost as much rhetorical license as Lines, I would prefer to say we save nature from humans for humans. The idea that we justify saving nature either for human welfare and survival or else for its own intrinsic value does not properly present the options that environmental argument has available. The only sense in which I would be happy to say we save nature for its own sake is if it meant much the same as when we advocate art for art’s sake. Except that art and nature are life for life’s sake. Nature is that part of life which, as Nietzsche said of art, is the great stimulus to life. I want nature like I want artto live the good life. Call it the pursuit of happiness. A society devoid of nature, and art would be an unhappy one. The sense then in which we might say that we save nature for human welfare need not be that which implies that we need nature for our survival and as the guarantee of the resources our lives depend upon. Let’s say we could get away with trashing quite a bit of this precious natureas many believe. There might have been immense amounts of work that went into it—the work of evolution—but it’s just useless heritage like art. For that matter we could trash art as well. Lets say we lived in a world at last uncluttered by yellow robins and dry sclerophyll forests and seashells, and, for good measure, dancing and pictures and movies and songs. We would just be that bit closer to a totally fictionalized breeding and survival battery for humans. Hardly living, barely survival. What can’t be sold has its uselessness thereby demonstrated. Hence so much society is about selling itself, and saving nature for humans is one way environmentalism is solda limited and self-deceptive way. An ecosystem is sold on the basis of its ecosystem services. Sometimes these so called services are sold as functional for landholders. This is common in the Landcare movement. However when landholders see no point in saving some bit of rubbish or woody scrub the appeal is made to saving the stuff, or other stuff like water quality or river ecology or biodiversity, for more than just landholder interestfor downstream or the ‘community’ or the nation or ‘our kids’. I am with Lines on this. The undoubted wisdom of a saving such things for such reasons is not enough for me. It is merely a matter of a very abstract functionality, functionality schematized according to the most limited economic or utilitarian values. The farmer or landowner who has reestablished a Grassy Red Gum Forest on the Bellinger flats and who has dotted it with patches of Lowland Rainforest does not exist. Mere biodiversity is not ‘functional’ enough; there isn’t much downstream (except for ocean) for water quality; and why go to the expense and trouble just to waste that expensive alluvial land. 210

Saving or reestablishing that mosaic of lowland open forest and rainforest is only for nature lovers like Lines and me. We want it not just for its economic or agricultural or utilitarian functionality. I want it for the good life; and for Lines it wants for itself. Obviously, neither argument is the last word; but nothing is the last word on anything. Because selling nature is the main thing, we are told we should not say this because the landholder is never going to buy it; but not to say it is to censor the theory of nature and curtail the culture of nature. It is to persist in a kind of irksome, repetitive somnolence, barely conscious, like the delirium of a sleepless night. Some might say we want nature for non-utilitarian reasons, dusting off the old aesthetic line that Kant called functionality without function (Zweckmäβigkeit ohne Zweck). But society has had enough of this view too that art and nature are just beautiful and useless. Nature, like art, is so generous in its uses, so liberal in its functions, so concrete in its defiance of abstract functionality and so excessive in its catastrophes that beautiful nature serves notice on the dysfunctionality of our stingy system of accounted for functions.

12.4 …As Environmental Norm Ecosystem Services The CEO of an NGO in environmental management PowerPoints® vision and mission onto the screen. It is a flow chart of the organization’s positioning in the ideology spectrum. One end is labelled pragmatic, the other idealist/purist. This is one of those diagrams of the explained world, the arcana of everyday ontology. In the ensuing catechism the CEO prompts, ‘Shouldn’t this organization be positioning itself at the pragmatic end?’ and a ripple of assent runs through those assembleda collective show of thoughtfulness. Pragmatism is one thing that deserves to be rescued from its proudest devotees, lest it be devalued by equating it with some ugly makeshift of ecosystem functions. Environmental managers talk the talk about restoring ecosystems and ecosystem services. Confronted with the predicament that restoring certain biological communities to their former condition is either impossible or impractical, they suggest that the appropriate mission is one of restoring ecosystem function or functioning ecosystems. What does restoring ecosystem function mean? And what does it mean to say function? An organism has features whose functions are the survival of that organism and the reproduction of offspring with inherited genetic information. But ecosystems are not organisms with adaptations for self-maintenance and reproduction. Landholders on the North Coast estuaries see people on the fresh reaches planting the densely rooting lomandras (Lomandra hystrix) on their banks. They assume that they should be able to plant lomandras on their banks. But Lomandra hystrix grows on the alluvium of the fresh reaches. Cheated of this 211

tool, people assume that there must be an estuarine functional analogue. Surely nature has provided such a species because estuarine banks need bank stabilizers too. Nature works that way doesn’t it? If there is functional niche, nature, like a boutique supplier, supplies the design that is lacking. That is the balance of nature, or evolution, or something. But there is no functional analogue of Lomandra hystrix on the brackish reaches; and besides the purpose of Lomandra hystrix was never bank stabilization, until someone recently noticed that they did actually do this. People’s faith in ecological functionalism has yet again blinded them to the subjectivity of function: functional design is not for nature, but for the organism (the subject) with the design. Down on the estuary there are just other riparian things doing their own riparian thing: mangroves, sea rushes, swamp oaks, lots of things and they are more or less useful for the same freehold functions. Meanwhile the ripariana culture caters to the functionalist delusions, and the boutique market for lomandras is extended downstream and out of its zone. The most famous genre of diagrams of the explained world is the list of points, the A, B, C… A natural history of this kind of list would have to consider its adaptations to planning documents and mission statements, to media like the overhead and computer projection, to genres like the report, to communicative ends like summary, management and education, to the typography of the dreaded bullet, to the epistemological expectation that adequate explanation should exhaust the received categories of understanding. (Now there was a list). Other features of the list are an ambiguous implication of priority in the order of things listed, and instant communicabilityensured, mostly, by the customary redundancy of most of the listed information. After all, the honest function of a list is to remind you of what you already know; you don’t want to forget to buy bread on your way home. Otherwise, usually the only way to read a list is between the lines; this is the only way a list communicates anything but an all too familiar, and therefore redundant, message. Typical of lists of the explained world, lists of ecosystem functions are usually neither exclusive nor exhaustive, nor are the categories all of the same kindbut they look like they sort of are. They include, willy-nilly, nutrient cycling, water cycling, carbon sequestration, soil conservation, and perhaps food chains, predator-prey relations, successions, and biodiversity (always biodiversity). And the beauty of a list is you can always make it longer or hodge-podge it up a bit by adding more or less extra-curricula itemstourism, community education and aesthetics are old stand-bys even if they might not seem quite like ecosystem functions. Whatever. To instant environmental understanding, it is undemanding to infer that the function of trees is carbon or water sequestration or soil conservation and, of course timber down the track; the function of tight nutrient cycling is water quality; the function of insectivorous birds is to control insect populations; or that stacking a lot of interdependent species together (i.e. avoiding monoculture) is for hedging ecological bets and maintaining a balanced, stable ecosystem. Nature never acts 212

in vain. It’s all connected, all designed, all workingand for people out their in the community and for the future generations in a technocratic, cost-benefit analysis, sustainable development sort of way. Such faith in ecological function is a modern refuge of theological teleology. It asserts environmental providence and justifies the ways of nature to men. Almost an item in the lifeworld of environmentalist society, it is not uncommon to hear someone ask, or even to catch oneself scratching and wondering just what is the reason for having paralysis ticks? Or leeches? But if any biological community functions, then, one way or another, every biological community functions. Leaky toxic chemical dumps are ecosystems that appear to function pretty well as toxic chemical dumps with their own kinds of fauna and flora, their own nutrient regimes, their own successions. Sadly and happily, nothing is forever in nature and, like even the most imposing forest or the plutonium blasted test site, the toxic dump ecosystem won’t last forever. Give it time or half a chance and nature is unstable, unbalanced, immoderate, profligate, haywire, madcap, strange and antagonistic. Whenever the word function is used it is worth asking the first question of functional analysis: function for whom or what? And when environmental managers talk about ecosystem functions they usually mean what environmental budgeters like to sell as ecosystem services: water cycling, carbon sequestration, biodiversity, and such. There is a complacent misunderstanding that these functions for us are also functions for the ecosystems. There is also the comforting assumption that restoring ecosystem function, is the same thing as restoring community composition, traditional Aboriginal country, biodiversity, and landscape scale systems. I suspect though that these are mostly unreconciled ends. Natives and Weeds, or The Bush and Not The Bush Some weeds are called environmental weeds to distinguish them from unwanted species on farms or in lawns or gardens. They are weeds of the natural environment. They invade the bush. In the Bellinger Valley, Parramatta grass is a weed of pasture but not an environmental weed, it is said. Paspalum and kikuyu are pasture grasses but not environmental weeds. It is said. One species of paspalum—Broad-leaved Paspalum—is a pasture grass that can grow under trees. Farmers plant it so that they can have the best of all possible worlds: pasture and trees. It is perfect. Except, it is an invasive weed of moist forests. It may be said that it is an environmental weed, but its agricultural value makes natural resource managers careful about what they say. No one seems game to list it officially as an environmental weed. All this kind of talk assumes one thing though. It assumes that there is a line that is drawn, or can be drawn, between the bush and the non-bush. Or is it between the natural environment and the unnatural environment?

213

It’s obvious isn’t it? There is the bush over there, where those gum trees are, and this here is not bush. It’s farmland. It has been cleared. It used to be bush, but not any more. That is essentially bush, and this, in essence, isn’t. History is an acid for dissolving essences. It transforms things utterly, into other kinds. Here where I now sit is in the bushit’s the natural environmentand a little over a century ago it was bush too. But around 1900 the big trees were ring-barked, the smaller ones were felled, the place was burnt, the stumps grubbed, paspalum (not broad-leaved paspalum) was sown in the ashes, and post and wire fences divided up the land. They ran up from the alluvial river flats, onto the slaty clay soils of the spurs and gullies, all the way to the main ridges. By 1920 it was grazing country, sometimes rough and steep, a lot of it erupting as regrowth, but with a bit of river flat as well, people could squeeze a living from it. Cattle ranged through the ring-barked pillars and shaded themselves under a few spreading blue gums and tallowwoods. But it was still like an unruly colony at the limit of the civilized world. The indigenous bush kept fighting back, farmers kept burning it back to kill the woody growth, and ran their cattle through it to eat off the green pick, and sowed more grass if they could afford itat least in the most accessible and fertile reaches. People continued to log the forested remnantsmany of which were State Forestand they might also have re-cleared a patch of wattle regrowth and grown a slash-and-burn cash crop of peas or beans. After the Second World War bulldozers and chainsaws were enlisted in the struggle. Driven to submission, some patches became persistently grassy, others kept struggling back to reform a regrowth forest of eucalypts and wattles and lantana. Eventually the slash-and-burn and the burn-and-graze economy fell into decline, milk and beef markets squeezed the struggling cow cockies, houses were abandoned, the lantana infested regrowth swallowed the ridge-andgully country, and a paper pulp company—Australian Paper Mills—planted flooded gums on cheap old cattle properties. After the 1970s a metropolitan diaspora arrived, bought up the repristinated backblocks of what Les Murray called the land of the holidayof their childhood holidays that isand the line was drawn. It was even clearer than the line the old settlers reported between the rainforest brush and the gum tree bush, because, although it was drawn imperceptibly by the many small decisions of agricultural history, it was the famous anthropological line between nature and culture drawn their on the great diagram of the landscape. This here is essentially bush, even though 70 years ago it was ridge grazing country up the back of a farm. And anything that grows in it that’s not native is an environmental weed. That country down there is farm even though a century ago it was bush and the farmer still has to slash it and graze it and fertilize it and sow broad-leaved paspalum on it to stop the bracken, blady grass, wattles, lantana, privet, camphor laurels and eucalyptsthe rubbishfrom taking over. The line drawn between native bush and exotic vegetation is also drawn at the level of individual species, but determining what is native is not always easy. If a plant or animal was here before European culture arrived it is usually 214

called native. All this can sound a bit strange to someone from another country. In Asia and Europe thousands of years of Neolithic agriculture combined with climate change since the last ice age and there is little cultural memory of plant invasion. In Australia such memory of invasion and with it the degradation of natural beauty is part of individual memory. Migrants have to learn it. It’s part of native nature culture. It can all seem terribly culturally constructed and therefore ideological or arbitrary. Justifications based on arguments about conserving biodiversity can sound like desperate excuses for mindless perpetuation of anachronistic lore or mere taste. Hair splitting and quibbling can sound like medieval theology. Problems arise when we don’t know the historical biogeography of a species or when a species fails to behave as decorously as we expect natives to do. Around here privet and camphor are weeds. Lantana is a weed too but some have come to think of it as an honorary native. People often think of wild tobacco as native, and many who know of its exotic provenance still think of it as a harmless exotic. I think of passionfruit, bush lemon and cape gooseberry as harmless, indeed fruitful exotics. Exotics like jacaranda, Rhodes grass and broad-leaved paspalum are often mistaken for natives. Natives like river oak, cockspur, mistletoe and burrgrass are accused of being exotic weeds. The line between native or not can be a fine one: silky oak and black bean are natives on the Orara River, 50km north of the Bellinger but are they natives on the Bellinger valley? Even the botanists and biogeographers puzzle over plants such as tropical chickweed, five-leaved morning glory, and Sigesbeckia indica, and sometimes mutter provisos about weedy natives or about cosmopolitan natives. We place a lot of store by history but can we always know it and is it the best standard? Are humans more native than Dingoes because they were here long before them? Standards: Deriving Norms From Natural History What is history good for when it comes to the history of nature? Is natural history just a quaint old nature lover’s way of cobbling together stories about casual observations that lack the rigour of empirical biology and statistical inference? Many things in the culture of nature can be characterized using historical terms. A little historical reflection can save us from being used by parasitical terms like environmental values or biodiversity or ecosystem services or even the environment. Karl Marx once said that the past weighs on the brains of the living like a nightmare. Consider the inherited burdens of feuds and warsagainst one another and against nature! In these wildest, most alienated kinds of society, forms of life like punishment, tit-for-tat, retribution and revenge prey on humans for their own survival. But the past is not only present as a nightmare; it is also present as wealththe immense, accumulated commonwealth of nature. A beautiful creature doesn’t evolve overnight from clay. A rainforest doesn’t work just by throwing all sorts of green things together on a clean slate and letting it all sort itself out into some complex 215

order. Compared to that of a weedscape, whatever order there is in a biological community like a rainforest or a heath is something that has taken a long time to sort out and build up. The labour of nature was going on long before humans, who are one of its products, got into the act. There have been countless generations of suffering and failure that have gone into the design of the smallest insect and the design of its relation to other organisms, and therefore into the design of the relation of those organisms to one another. Suspicion of things artificial implies an appreciation of this immense labour of natural history, although when, say, Immanuel Kant expressed his misgivings about artifice at the end of the 18th century, he could hardly have appreciated just what natural history had to do with it. When the philosopher, who had seldom if ever left Königsburg, says in his Critique of Judgement (§22) that we would tire of the neat rows of a pepper plantation long before we would tire of the surrounding jungle it is because there is more order and more history in the ‘free beauties of nature’ than in the regularity of the planted rowsso much order and so much history that it can look random or arbitrary. That is what biodiversity and the Threatened Species Act are all about. Random, it turns out, is just another word for complexity, for a surfeit of information beyond our powers of reductiontoo much order built up by too much history, so much order it no longer appears orderly. Arbitrary is a word applied to things whose design is estranged from our designs and understandingoften as the result of its being the effect of an unreconstructable historical accumulation of design upon design. This is why we cannot imitate or emulate nature by throwing plants and animals together at random or arbitrarily. Nature looks random and arbitrary quite often where it is designed in its own inscrutable way. We cannot expect to build functioning ecosystems by throwing things together according to their separate functions (nor, for that matter, at random). Though each might thing be chosen because it is conceived in abstract as serving a function that the community would seem to needthis is the beetle that pollinates the tree that shades the shrub that feeds the bird that spreads the seed...each component has its several needs and several functions and several relations to other components, most of which will scarcely be appreciatedespecially given the limited idea of function that haunts our particular brand of instrumental reason. The trouble with instrumental reason and its call for pragmatism is that it is not instrumental or pragmatic enough. It is mean and puritanical about function. Assembled with the utmost care, all those components would hardly be likely to get on togethernot without one of the assembled species being the humans who will tend the species and maintain the order. It is hardly an advance on the pepper plantation. Remove the humans and the place would become an abandoned weedscape. We have to read off the components of a collection that works together and the process for assembling the components from what natural history has bequeathed us. The natural history of nature is about the best plan, the only plan we have of what works in a complex way. And I don’t mean this just in the reduced sense of 216

working as a functioning ecosystem; I mean it in the sense that we speak of an artwork working. Natural history provides us with the genres of the poetics of nature. Natural historical descriptions are apt to be transformed into prescriptions. Humans are inveterately given to turning facts into normsor for that matter mistakes into normseven though the philosophers have long doubted the propriety of deriving an ought from and is. There is a fascination with the pristine that often drives environmental histories—especially in Australia. Consider works like Eric Rolls’ Million Wild Acres, Stephen Pyne’s Burning Bush, Tim Flannery’s Future Eaters, Marcia Langton’s Burning Questions, David Horton’s Pure State of Nature, or even Tim Low’s Feral Future. Lurking behind their fascination with natural history is not only a nostalgia but with it a kind of will to power: to declare the facts of the pristine world is to declare standards for working on nature. Just how natural the natural history of Australia is has been a central theme in all these works, with only Horton preferring to argue for a pure nature mighty enough to overcome the ecological consequences of all human labour up until the unleashing of modernity’s destructive technology. A second questionthat of the normative value of the pristineis not entirely unconscious in these works either, but there is less specific articulation of it. It is mainly there by implication in arguments about which description of the pristine represents the past ‘as it actually was’. Where this is the case though, the question of the normative value of the pristine is, as a rule, answered in the affirmative without actually being asked; and the question of the possibility of historical narrative’s adequacy to such a thing as the past ‘as it really was’ is answered in the affirmative too. This question has been a constant one in the philosophy of history. The notion that history’s task is to describe the past by careful reference to and argument from the empirical sources is a fair enough thing. It is the only thing. If you are serious, its pursuit is unavoidable, yet unavoidably it’s a kind of romance quest. For a start, those empirical sources, if they are documents, are already, as documents, primarily only evidence of themselves as communicative acts of the past, and not of the acts and events they might describe. It makes for a past that must be inferred from the more or less dubious testimony of only those documents that have survived the ravages of the history, and from a palaeontology and archaeology of fossils and artifacts whose individual persistence is massively contingent. This predicament demands a view of the past as anything but irrevocable. While the events of the past fade, history revises its image, giving the impression that it is becoming clearer all the time. To an extent this may be true, as the technical and theoretical means of historical science improve. But then, in order to tell the history, the meagre empirical evidence must become part of the premises of a narrative argument. All history is narrative history, but what people often mean by the phrase narrative history is a narrative that is plausible in a good-read kind of way; and the formula for plausible, pop-literary good-reads is hardly the formula for a narrative that is adequate to the past. There has to be a poetics of narrative at 217

work when telling natural history, as well as a poetics of nature when working on it. And still the freedom of specifying norms and standards cannot be ignored. It is implicit in the fact that there are many versions of the pristine, depending on how far back in time you go; and where you go back in time. In Australia? Before modernity? Before humans? Before the great environmental upheavals of the late Tertiary? The Pre-Cambrian? Tim Flannery toys with introducing Komodo Dragons to replace an iota of the goanna megafauna that has disappeared since human occupation. Marcia Langton and many others might fancy some tradition of Aboriginal fire culture. David Horton would like to steer country back to a less fired up flora and fauna, claiming that this was the Aboriginal pristine anyway. The pristine has a different value in the Aboriginal north from the more thoroughly colonized south. Beyond Australia things are different too. Northern hemisphere temperate ecology is young and simple compared to the long evolved ecological relationships of Australia. Thanks to glaciation of recent ice ages, Europe was almost made for being shaped by thousands of years of cultivation and plant invasion. The disputed validity of claims about the pristine should be a reminder that the freedom to derive a norm from a factwith no license in logicimplies the freedom to derive it from a mistake anyway. In the curiousity about the pristine, the natural history that weighs on us most is that great and still obscure one of the future. In natural history, we pore over the events of the past in order to predict or prescribe the events of the future, forever and rightly anxious that, whatever we decide, time will prove it more or less wrong in fact or unhappy in performance. The predicament of assessing the truth value and the normative value of the history of nature should remind us of the same predicament that confronts historical narratives in what we like to designate as the more strictly human context. As the latter gives rise to a poetics of narrative, the former demands a poetics of nature. History, Big History, Or Even Bigger History When are questions about history too big to be relevant any more? What is the point of weeding out the plants that have all run wild through the bush, when after all, they are now here to stay? It is now natureeverchanging, never resting naturethat grows all these weeds in this country. Even if we weed one place once, we can’t weed every place all the time, and populations of weeds and feral animals are still growing nearby either waiting for the next fire, flood, landslip or bulldozer to colonize, or they are already just invading the bush under normal, relatively undisturbed conditions. It has taken little more than 200 years for them to all run wild, and even if we ceased introducing acclimatized exotic speciesthe pasture grasses, the garden ornamentals, the water and aquarium features, the GM strainsthere are quite enough here already. Their invasion is relentless and they have hardly begun to strike. In 5, 218

10, 100 years wont a big fire rip through it and everything will be back to scratch? In 1000 years, no matter what is done, won’t it all be what we now call a weedscape? If we want to love nature, shouldn’t we learn to love the coming weedscapes? After more than 200 years of modern globalized plant dispersal, the flora and fauna of Australia has changed once and for all. Here we have performed just another great unrepeatable experiment. It is like two super continents bumping together, Gondwana and Laurasia brought back together by ships and planes to form a New Pangaea. I said you can’t just throw everything together, but of course here we have just thrown everything together, the new with the old, and with no worries about any ‘ecosystem functions’ at all. And it works! We still have ecosystems! And it will take time to sort itself outto find species, for instance, that will happily grow along the humid subtropical riverbanks with Anredera and Balloon Vine and Catsclaw. Maybe to find a whole suite of species that get along together in what we might call the future plant communities of Southern Pangaeathe bamboo and queen palm forests, the camphor and privet rainforests. But on the other hand there are always a few things that grow anywhere and if twenty pan-subtropical weeds dominate the places where once the astonishing lowland subtropical rainforests grew, then these are the new ecosystems of New South Pangaea Ecosystems are changing. They have always changed. Change is relative. Time is a matter of timescale. Different biological changes have different timescales: different rates of growth, reproduction, dispersal, successions, the natural, genetic selection of species and the gradual emergence of relatively self-similar communities of interacting species. Society changes too and different social processes have different timescales: rapid thought, conversation, fashion, a lifetime, a generation, a custom, a tradition, the social, memetic selection of customary cultural forms, the long time of civilizations, and the natural selection of the human species. Nature culture has changed a lot in the last century and in the last 1000 years. The passions and obsessions of these times are unlikely to be the passions and obsessions of the future. Natives are time bound. The genres of nature change like the genres of art. But would anyone say about art: ‘Why make tragedies? Why make comedies? Who will want such things in the future?’ Well, even though tragedy and comedy have been around, in one form or another for a long time, why should they or, for that matter, art itself be expected not to change, not to come to an end? Yet like art, the poetics of nature is not hopeless simply because we are all at sea on an ocean of change. We have always been all at seadespite the various foundations we have tried to assert: gods, religion, the moral law, theology, first philosophy, a priori truths. And yet in all this, we are always working on the mobile, floating base given us by history: the nightmare and the commonwealth. This is why art is not just anything and why the poetics of nature is not just anything and therefore nothing. Sure art and nature are contingentthings could be 219

absolutely otherwisebut this is precisely the condition for the poetics of nature, not the condition for deeming the whole undertaking pointless.

12.5…As Bushfire Fascinating Fire Every spring the smoke appears over the Bellinger Valley and the North Coast. You see a plume seeping up from a gully or from a spur tucked away somewhere, and another and another, pooling in a seam of air and lying idle over the warming land. Up close you might see a thin line of flames crackling through leaf litter, flaring in blady grass, sketching a clean patch of black, fresh with white ash. With a bit of wind or heat it might lick up into bushes and worry the leaves. Clean up that patch of bush, tidy up the roadside, get rid of the regrowth, reduce the fuel load. It is time for a good burn. It’s a rite that has persisted from the days when the east coast forests were ringbarked and burnt. It was and is as if in this place the fires that had cleared the forests of Neolithic Europe up until the end of the Middle Ages could be resurrected, their power felt and wielded again. After the initial clearing, seasonal burning became a way of clearing away the dry grasses left over from the last season or burning back the regenerating bush. When it got warmer or rained, up came green pick for grazing. Croppers burnt stubble to kill disease, untangle the way for the plough and get a pulse of nutrients from the ash. After the might and glory of the flames comes the clean slate, that perennial, unobscured object of desire fit for the revelation of the earth’s renewed riches. It is an old urge and a widespread one. In the Mahabharata, Krishna and Arjuna travel through a forest that Agni, the old Vedic god of fire is preparing to burn. The Sanskrit name Agni is cognate with the Latin ignire. Even Krishna, the lover of natural abundance, agrees with Agni’s argument that the searing fire will renew the life of the forest. Is there a society where fire the destroyer is not also fire the renewer? Dean Yibarbuk has said ‘We don’t necessarily see fire as bad and destructiveit can be good and bring the country back to life.’ To preserve the Manangrida country Yibarbuk encourages the knowledge and practice of traditional burning. Neglected and irresponsible fire management have led to wild summer fires, damage to certain plant communities and animal populations, and weed invasion. Knowledge of burning is not implanted in the soul. It is not a birthright, it is culture. And it is not just ritual, it is technological. Nowadays though it has to be adequate to the postmodern social and ecological predicament. The idea of reproducing the pre-1788 fire regime is one of the great themes in the imagination of the pristine. If only the Aboriginal fire regime could be rediscovered, we would then have the lost key to the continent’s repristination. It is a persistent subtext in the expressions of a particular Australian bush 220

romance. While the ecological conditions and the Aboriginal society of the north are changing, down here on the east coast the fire culture is already transformed. All that remains of the Aboriginal country is encrypted in the scattered ruins of the traditional nature left lying around the country, and in rumours and interpretations that have come out of the past. It is a history of selective quotation and Chinese whispers, the usual social conditions for engendering myth and legend. And fabulous fire is already the natural subject of myth even without this process of selective replication of stories from the past. People like to call on old descriptions. During the high summer fires of 2002, Bob Carr recalled the accounts of smoke seen from the deck of the Endeavour in 1770. Cook’s journal often uses the phrase smoke in several places, or something like it (Evans, 1969). For those gazing at the pleasing variety of ridges, hills, valleys, and plains, all clothed with wood that loomed in the west beyond the barrier of history and surf, smoke, the sign of fire became primarily the sign by which they knew the country to be inhabited. Whether this was campfire or bushfire or wildfire smoke or smoke from a fire kept burning to light more fire is seldom made clear. 50 km south of the Bellinger on a high, round point, Cook made special mention of fires that produced a great quantity of smoke. Cook called it Smoky Cape. From the quantity it sounds like a bushfire. An account from the Gumbaynggirr past suggests that the first fire was a large log burning on a mountain and protected by two Coomburra in the form of eagles. Two young women sent by their people to get the fire were refused it and they in turn refused to bring game to cook on the fire. Then a bandicoot man crept up with a grass tree shaft, the plant of choice for making and carrying fire. He stole the fire, and the Coomburra rolled the log down the hill and could not stop it. North of the Bellinger, in Bundjalung country, the Endeavour journal describes smoke again and people nearby trudging along carrying palm leaves. The English assumed that the sight of their ship sailing past would have been little less stupendous and unaccountable to the natives, than a floating mountain with all its woods. Yet the people on shore seem to ignore the ship or are oblivious to it. In all descriptions spoken across the distances of time, interpretation and culture, there is as much to puzzle over as there is evidence to marshal or claims to venture. The Endeavour sailed past in Maya month of autumn rain and rank vegetation. If you sail or fly from Sydney to Brisbane now and see smoke all the way, it will probably be August or September, the height of the season when modern tradition dictates burning off, or hazard reduction. On the Bellinger, early spring is dry enough to get a burn going and late enough to make any later too late. Any later and it’s too wet or too dangerous. Any earlier and it’s too wet or too cool or you can put it off until later. And September is late enough to get a decent burn, decent enough to get way. Claims by modern burners that they are just following the traditional land management of the Aboriginal society are, in most cases, post hoc justifications. Just how much the modern rural fires of eastern Australia, or the 221

prescribed burning in tracts of bush, or the hazard reduction conducted on urban fringes might be social descendents of Aboriginal burning is obscured by the lack of detail about what features of these practices might be inherited and by the fact that land management by burning is virtually universal in human societies. It is difficult to find direct cultural ancestors in the social evolution of burning because fire culture is highly likely to be the result of convergent social evolution. It is a social practice waiting to happen with no want of precedent. Nevertheless, if the modern burning society of the east coast cites Aboriginal burning as a forebearand it does, even if in ignorance of any detailed understanding of the social functions of Koori firethen an ancestry is established by reification. Society is like that. And fire culture is the epitome of reification: if you declare fire to be the rightful heir of bush management practices, fire gives you the power to make the declaration good. Or rather it will make good its own claim: it gets away and fends for itself. It is around the element of fire more than any other that the problem of confusing history’s factual and its normative value infects the natural history of Australia. Fire dominates the ideological problem of establishing historical facts and environmental norms because fire is natural and cultural, a material and a tool, problem and solution, old and wild, powerful and destructive, at once obvious in the traces it leaves and effective at destroying evidence. And it is so much a shaper of Australian nature, now and in the past. The archaeology of pre-invasion fire on the east coast is not clear. Different evidence comes from different locations, and different methods of reconstructing fire histories produce different interpretations. A recent examination of charcoal and pollen in Jibbon Lagoon in Royal National Park south of Sydney (Mooney, Radford, Hancock, 2001) indicated a low frequency of fire when this was D’harawal country. Just how the D’harawal people lived, and precisely where and when they stayed in different places are unanswered questions that have bearing on interpreting the data. Initially after their dispossessioni.e. up until the early 20th centuryfire frequency seems to have declined even further. Then, when modern Australia arrived with a vengeance, up the frequency went to unprecedented levels. Other studies done in other areas tell a similar story, some don’t. Tell an anti-burner this and the interpretation is: ‘The increased frequency in the 20th century is the result of more sources of ignition.’ Tell a burner and it is: ‘The increased frequency is the result of fuel build up and changes in vegetation structure due to the cessation of Aboriginal fire management.’ Even if we knew the Aboriginal fire regime, could we ever reinstate it, given that so much modern fire culture now is wild and unlawful? Indeed, at what level of social and spatial organization and at what kind of timescale can a given society’s fire history be seen as a regime anyway, rather than a variable sequence of unpredictable events, a mix of the ritual, the official, the criminal, the ecologically determined, the accidental and the just plain stochastic? How much of that regime is a result of human freedom or law? And how much is it

222

the result of wild naturewhether the wild nature of both lawful and unlawful society, or that of extra-human nature? Every summer the news turns to bushfires. It is a media event. A photograph on the front of the Sydney Morning Herald in early January 2002 shows two shirtless boys paddling a canoe in deep green water up one of the sunken sandstone valleys of Port Hacking on the southern edge of Sydney. You can see the oysters on the golden rocky edge. The bush of Royal National Park runs right down to the water’s sandstone trim, and a metre above the water, fire is running through the litter and up the trunks of red bloodwoods. People who have spent the morning at the beach would be looking up from the city through an orange sky at a pink sun. From the suburbs you can look out at night towards the bush around Sydney and see the aura of fires along the sandstone ridgelines. Up here on the Bellinger this wild fire time comes and usually goes earlier in the season, before the Christmas holidays, usually with less ferocity. At night last spring you could stand down near the mouth of the Bellinger and look back up at the escarpment and see a fire burning way above the valley like a red dragon along a high spur of the escarpment. When they are further south bushfires are summer holiday news. While people in Sydney are thinking about evacuating we pull a TV outside into the warm summer dusk and drink beer and watch fires on the news. There will be opinion pieces about it all inside the holiday papers. It makes exciting entertainmentunless you live in a house on the edge of the city and the bush and you have to face the treacherous thing in a howling hot westerly, or you find yourself, as it were, fighting the thing, in heavy clothes and cruel heat, wild flames boiling your blood, smoke in your lungs, ash in your mouth, hour after hour, day after day. Inside the paper and on the TV news there are the usual stories about the fire fighters. There are the stories of loss (the houses, the photos, the lives, everything), about the politicians flying in to be seen commiserating with the victims and looking like they are overseeing the fire fighting campaign, the photo of a shirtless man in thongs, shortly before his death, squirting water out of a garden hose, stories about lightning, stories about arsonists and how if we catch them nothing is too good for them, stories about the lack of preparation, opinion about the irresponsibility of the National Parks Service and environmentalists, about the lack of burning off, about people who build their houses in the bush, about how fast it moved, about firestorms, about fireballs, about how all the fires joined together in a giant ring of fire, and about sightseers hampering emergency services. There will be vision of the smoke and the pink sun over the centre of Sydney, stories about how the experts had or had never predicted this, questions already being asked, and the announcement that the blame game has started. Much of it is understandable. There is nothing so fierce, so unstoppable, so crazy, so implacable, so deadly, and so fascinating as a big fire on a stinker of a day. Mythology is the only way people have to adequately describe it. Even so, the same old monsters always

223

sound so pathetic in the attempt—half technical, half hyperbolic: flashpoints, fireballs, firestorms, infernos. Fire journalism can barely tear itself away from what it thinks is the human story. On the spot footage might show some spectacle of nature, mayhem and anguish, but then comes the personal perspective—the first and last resort of the aftermath coverage. The genre is a straightjacket. Generic victims pick through the smoking ruins, wonder why their house went and that one next door didn’t, crack hardy about rebuilding, grateful for saving their lives, the dog or the photos. The anniversary reflections show the closure or the lack of it a year on. The journalist asks how do you feel? Forced by shock, courtesy and circumstances, stunned people answer like readers from preordained scripts. First the fire and then the media rob them of their individuality. Gawking at fires is judged harshly. It interferes with emergency services during the fire, it is grotesque during the days after, and a year later it is not letting sleeping dogs lie. Yet TV fire news and docoes are mostly pure gawk. They insult the subjects. The human-perspective stuff is the epitome of gawk; and, apart from a few platitudes about fire being a part of the Australian bush, the media avoid the natural history and science of fire and the technicalities of preventing, avoiding, fighting and surviving fires, on the thick-headed assumption that natural history, science and the technical matters of fire are somehow not human interest. At best you get a Koperburg or Winter from the Rural Fire Service. They’ve got a job to do so they are not averse to telling viewers two or three things worth knowing about fire. You might fluke a premasticated bite of a Cheney on fire behaviour, but no more than can be expected to interest TV audiences. And you won’t get an ecologist. No Gills or Bradstocks. No way. You don’t want to know about the finer points of cauterizing a wet eucalypt forest of its rainforest understorey or its mistletoes. That’s not fire in its spectacular self, and its too technical. All you need to know about it is fire is part of the bush. It’s legendary and you already know it. It is all part of the summer news ritual, ready-made vision and copy especially welcome when it happens over the news void of Christmas. Somehow the abstractions of spectacle and trauma are human, but the concreteness of knowledge and experience isn’t. But then news consumerism prefers to flog the proven gratification of the abstract, rather than risk the concrete. The personal perspective leads in to the blame game. People see the victims or the weary fire fighters and want to say whose fault it all is. Arson is on the increase, says a politician or a story in the Sydney Morning Herald, but from the days when the Kooris broadcast burnt or selectors cleared land and their heirs wielded the fire stick, it has also become more criminalized. Deliberately lit fires are a tradition, but the modern state has made a habit of criminalizing and psychopathologizing traditional forms of power and violence and monopolizing the legal forms of such things. Modern social organization, especially the spatial organization of rural property and suburbia makes traditional burningwhether in its Aboriginal forms or its wild-colonial formsdangerously anachronistic. If arson is on the increase it is because 224

unofficial fire lighting has been criminalized to protect property, and like other forms of violence, in its spectacular televised forms it kindles its own profane copycat genre. The burning up of evidence and the difficulty of catching in the act skew the caught unrandom sample of arsonists into a bunch of simpletons, disturbed young men and the odd person who gets off on all the excitement they generate. Pyromaniacs? Attention seekers? Loners? Reprobates? Stupid kids? Careless smokers? Fools? Rogue firefighters? People and politicians can indulge in a little fuming, but the psychopathology of arsonists is mostly beneath the dignity of the main ideological game. In Australia every inch of ground, every ridge, every gully has been fought over by fire and rain. In the balance fire has had the better, if only because the works of rain are long and slow and always fraught with the possibility of catastrophic failure. Fire on the other hand need not only build its empire by degrees, it can attack and win in one great holocaust. This argument between the elements has been matched by a social formthe long historical battle between burners and anti-burners. When fire is in the news everyone becomes an expert on fire. Bushfire lore is taken as a birthright in a society where fire is a social rite and fire culture is a social conflict sport. Fire is a compelling object of fascination, and in the course of mesmerized attention, society divides itself up over the fronts of old antagonisms. Each side can summon up its scientists. The inquiry into the 2003 Canberra fires had to stop the opposing sides calling experts to continually rebut one another. This conflict is like a wildfire itself. Find yourself on one side of the front and you get stuck there. Opinions are lined up for you on the other side to fight and your own opinions are lined up for you too. We say we hold an inquiry to learn from our mistakes but the conflict drives it to other purposes: to point the finger, to punish the feckless, to exalt the chair, and to promote those who covered their arses. Aborigines, settlers, cockies, prescribed burners, foresters and rural bushfire brigades have all used and advocated firewith many justifications, the most winning of which is that fire is, as they say, inevitable. They can say that, because it is self-perpetuating—not only naturally but also culturally. There will always be someone who cannot resist a technology that uniquely combines such great power with so little effort. Immense workhowever imprecisecan be done for almost nothing. In the cultural war burners think of anti-burners as a naive bunch of gentlemen foresters, intellectuals, greenies, townies, bleeding hearts and do-gooders. The anti-burning ideology sides with the lush and fertile sensuality of nature. Fire destroys plants and animals, stops the natural succession of rainforest and less fiery vegetation, sends organic matter up in smoke, wastes nutrients and adds CO2 to the atmosphere. Greens are almost always wary of fire. On the other hand there is a kind of staid gentility in not burning. ‘Intellectuals in particular,’ writes Stephen Pyne are ‘ever distrustful of open fire in all its varieties' (238). For many ‘the spectacle of fire is embarrassing and unwanted’…with a ‘low-tech folklorish image' (240). There is almost an antisensual, wowser streak in the bans on fire. They are a bit like bans on 225

imageshumourless, priestly, power grabs. Fire, like the image, is wickedly fascinating. Dazzling appearance and brutal fact, a wild, dangerous, gratifying and turgid mix of nature and society, of norm and fact, of cause and effect, fire emulates in the environmental sphere the dangers, fun and excitements of sexuality in the psychic sphere. Once, an old neighbour laughed and told me, he could flick a match off the back verandah when a hot westerly was up and get a fire that would burn through to Bundagen and the sea. The great eastern firebreak. The only decent burns in 50 years had been his, and the last one had happened over 25 years ago now. Gleeful in recollection, half mythic, half joking. You don’t get the chance to have fires like that anymore. Someone had to stop the fun. There is also a sensed Luddite streak in the anti-burn ideology. Ever since Prometheus the dangers of technologies have been a perennial cause of complaint, and fire is the arch technology. Of course for these and other reasons there are in fact plenty of intellectuals fascinated by fire. They sense that bans on fire do have a certain similarity to forms of religious and scholarly disapproval, they like the idea of Aboriginal fire management, and they know about native vegetation that is adapted to fire. And then there is always that world-weary knowledge of the bush and human folly. It is now a commonplace that because Europeans did not understand the bush and its custodianship the modern bush has become dangerously volatile as a result. As John Birmingham writes (1998, 129) ‘The firestick kept the forests clear of choking undergrowth and promoted plants which responded to fire as a natural part of their life cycle. When the Aborigines were driven away, this ecological regime, thousands of years in the making, was disastrously undermined. Fuel loads were the problem. Fuel loads and human folly.’ This kind of thing is uttered again and again by all those old softies inclined to a bit of hardheaded world-weariness. It is as poignant and sentimental a claim about the pristine as any other. Burners are hopeless romantics. Most of all the burner romance loves it that the bush, the national icon of national icons, is adapted to fire. It needs fire they say. Like many environmentalists, David Horton (77) has reacted to the claim about native plants being adapted to fire. ‘It is difficult to see how such an adaptation could evolve.’ It is as if, in Horton’s case, a certain sensibility cries out, surely life itself cannot be an adaptation to what is its complete negation: fire. Claimed adaptations to fire could only be merely indirect or ‘the incidental effect of some other adaptation.’ ‘Many plants are adapted to the environment in ways that also happen to be valuable in times of fire.’ I would say however that this is precisely a description of how an adaptation to fire would evolve by natural selection. Adaptations do not come from nowhere. The inherited features of plants of animals are selected for whatever function they perform, provided it increases the average fitness of organisms that carry genes for that feature. Throughout the course of natural selection the functions of inherited traits change. If a heritable trait no longer serves any function for a lineage of organisms it is likely to degenerate in the absence of any selection pressure for its 226

maintenance. On the other hand, if a lineage has an available inherited feature that has been selected for ‘some other adaptation’, and that feature eventually turns out to be useful for survival or reproduction over many generations in a persistently fire prone environment, that feature then suffers a favourable selection pressure for its persistence as an adaptation to fire. The ability to survive and reshoot after fire or to maximize seed germination or seedling survival after fire are precisely adaptations to fire. That ability to reshoot may well have been inherited from ancestors that used it survive heavy grazing by herbivores, or defoliation in drought, but what came first does not matter as much as the latest use. In evolution, authenticity by priority must cede primacy to whatever comes after the fact. In the prolonged absence of fire such species may become rare or extinct. Since many species are at an advantage where fire occurs the use of fire in ecological restoration can increase the diversity of the regenerating plant speciesespecially if some places are burnt and some aren’t, and some are burnt at different frequencies and different seasons. Some species do well without it; some do well with it. Some like it hot, some don’t. Some like it often, some rarely. It depends on how they recover from fire and how they reproduce themselves and how quickly they reach reproductive maturity. The fire itself wont rid the bush of the problem of exotic weeds—it might encourage thembut it is still an important tool of ecological management (McDonald, Wale, & Bear). Some bush though just doesn’t need or want fire. Why would you want to burn a rainforest? Or would you want burn out a wet sclerophyll forest with a rainforest understorey that had taken 50 or 200 years to develop, just to make sure the eucalypts regenerated before they died? But then again, a roaring wildfire might just burn into wet forest because the drier forest on the ridges around it had so much fuel that the fire built up into something fierce enough to consume a rainforest. Just as persistent fire or water puts pressure on a lineage to develop suitable adaptations, ideological alternatives lead arguments down certain paths of adaptation. The opinion that Horton expresses is well adapted to a social environment where counter arguments to the claimsvalid or outlandishof modern Australian burning culture find automatic refuge. In arguing against the romantic burners, romantic environmentalists will often favour a plausible claim because it gives comfort, it augments the armoury of counter-arguments, it helps to allow no exceptions and no room for one’s opponents to manoeuvre in polemic. In the bush a box of matches is more persuasive than any other argument, so anti-burners need all the arguments they can get. Every summer comes with a fire warning. A rainy spring and the prophets warn of a fuel build up. A dry one and it’s a tinderbox out there. Everyone’s a Nostradamus but none, no matter how much they might like to savour the indignant pride of the unheeded, deserves much credit for prophesying fire. A hot dry December is quite enough to cause bad fires somewhere, hazard reduction and normal rainfall until 30th November notwithstanding. Hazard reduction, backburning, and prescribed burning for ecological management are all properly part of fire culture. It is hard to argue against the 227

principle, even if only because fire is needed to respond to the pyrogenic culture in the first place. The situation is like that of warfare where violent means must sometimes be the response to violence. Yet like war, fighting fire with fire comes with its own catch 22. The culture of hazard reduction is a hazard. The apprentices and self-styled experts of fire culture are important causers of fire. Of the 4 fires that have burnt within a kilometre of here in recent years, all were started as hazard reduction or burning off. One got away while its novice lighter had an afternoon nap. The origin of another is a mystery shrouded by embarrassment. One fumed under a pile of litter that had been raked up and collected to protect dwellings. It crept underground in a root and flared up at 10 o’clock the same night, consuming the works of art it had been lit to protect. One lurked in a windrow that had been lit in midwinter, burnt slow, deep and intense along the heart of a heavy log and then sent up a plume of smoke three months later when it emerged at the other end and kindled some blady grass on a hot September afternoon. The last two, probably the last three, were lit with care, experience and good intentions. Even when the most experienced do everything 99% right, fire can go 100% wrong. Cool burn a eucalypt forest as late as September and by October a litter of leaves crisped on their branches by the burn will have been shed and ready to pick up sparks on a fiery day. Unless ground fuel is reduced everywhere every year, fires can, under normal summer conditions, get into canopy. A heat wave with a scorching westerly can always blast through. With the problems of built property limiting the extent of broadscale broadcast burning, and with limited opportunities of weather and labour to kindle a burn, not enough vegetation can be burnt, and reduction must be limited and strategic. When they talk strategy people like to talk about burning a mosaic. It’s a word like balance or diversity. It has enough ambiguity to have community appeal, and it implies an appreciation of uncomprehended complexities. Some burnt areas, some unburnt. Some recently burnt, some long unburnt. The burnt bits where you want them for fuel reduction strategy, protection of property, conservation of flora and fauna, enhancement of biodiversity. Nowhere burnt too often or too seldom. Everywhere done decorously. The rainforest down there and a mosaic of drier forests in various stages of succession up here—the grand, beautiful, clever, diverse, Byzantine masterpiece of burning mosaics, a tour de force in space and time. If only fire, feral and fascinating, furious or finicky, were so compliant. If only the disposition of property, the weather, the arson, the accidents, the greenies, the burners, time and money would give us a chance. If only hazard reduction, biodiversity, property and living close to nature weren’t so thoroughly irreconcilable. Where such natural inconsistency and ideological conflict prevails, received wisdom likes to have it that thorough planning must be the answer. At least it is a democratic gesture, a hopeful diversion from pragmatics and the fall back you might just need when it comes to the blame game. Still, in no field of ecological practice is muddling on and putting out wildfires when called on so patently (and literally) the predicament. Burners say the complexity is no excuse for doing nothing. But fire is too fascinating 228

anyway. Society couldn’t bring itself to do nothing if it tried. Doing a bit of burning here—not enough and too much. Houses there, bush here, a firebreak there, a plantation here. Hazard reduction over there. It getting away here. Letting a wildfire burn there, fighting it here. And firing a few shots in the blame game too. It’s a mosaic out there all right. It’s Byzantine. Some say fuel reduction may temper certain sites for 15 years but 2-4 years is more likely. Most of the fuel has replenished by then. And it is only tempering. It will not stop bad fires, although it might reduce the intensity where it counts. It is a way to divide a landscape into a better strategic organization. And then the burning creates bush that is full of plants adapted to fire and with a tendency to build up dry fuel and burn again. As such burning creates the need for more burning to reduce the fuel load, and the more you burn the more you commit yourself to fire in future, whether prophylactic or destructive. In turn, all our burning is risky and much of it is lawless. Around here it’s a lawful risk in winter and early spring and a lawless risk in late spring and summer. Everywhere is different though (a fact that certainly feeds the confusion about the past and about what to do now because claims about say the Victorian bush or the Sydney sandstone are not valid when transferred to the mixed eucalyptus and rainforests of the Bellinger). Still, such great power comes from a single spark its almost irresistible. And technological society is inevitably pyrogenic. We litter sources of ignitionwhether immediate sources like stray sparks and cigarette butts or potential sources like glass and metal. Our fire culture is a wild and alien beast, and its wildness is amplified by fire’s own wild, implacable life. The bush has changed, but not in the simple sense that fire romantics dwell upon, namely in the sense that it has been abandoned to excessive growth and wilder hotter fires. Nowadays we own immovable property like the houses we live in. When the news says no property was lost this means no buildings were lost. It might stretch to a timber plantation. But it seldom means bush, which implies that the bush must be seen as either ever-present (i.e. burnt bush is still bush) or renewable (i.e. it all grows back), or it needs the good old good burn anyway, or it is not a commodity that you can call property, or all of the above. In a world that is present as a universe of commodities, almost invariably this immovable property incorporates most of that world, notably that portion of it to which we establish our most intimate and financially pressing relations. It might not seem so at first, but this is the biggest change in the bush. That is, it is the biggest change in the bush as a form of societywhich is what it was and what it still is. People build their houses in the bush and therefore, it is said don’t understand the bush. Every summer after houses burn and suburbs flee, voices of popular wisdom make the declaration with a weary shake of the head. It feeds a certain schadenfreude that unAustralian or Utopian green naïveté has had another little comeuppance. Build your house in an urban or rural landscape and you can shade it with as many trees as you like. You can let your garden grow into a forest or a jungle or 229

a tinderbox woodland. But build your house in the bush and you have to clear the bush from around it by at least 40 metresparticularly on the side from which the wild hot winds blowand mow your lawn low or pave over the ground so that there is no vegetation or litter to fuel an approaching fire. That is: build your house in the bush and get rid of the bush. If you live in the bush you can’t live in the bush. Of course this is not a paradox that defies resolution. You can build your house in the bush and many do, but to do so is a treat, a luxury, a risk, a folly, a compromise, an illusion, a maintenance problem, or, in many places a contravention of planning regulations. Not everyone is like the architect Richard Le Plaistrier. His appreciation of the temporality of a building in the bush implies that part of its beauty lies in the risky pact it makes with fire and time. The strategy of fire exclusion and fire prevention is a Sisyphean labour. Burners would say Utopian. Fighting fire with fire sounds witty, daring and bold. It’s kind of can do. Rain fights a fight like conservationists: gains are slow and incremental and never free from the threat that they could all be lost with the next entrepreneur or the next government; its enemy is as persistent and self-perpetuating as capital. Fire fights like market forces. It always has the capital of flammable vegetation and, when it consumes it, the flames only generate more. Nothing better illustrates the wild extra-human character of society than fire-culture. The purported inevitability of fire may be a socially normalized inevitability, but it is such a powerful one because so many for so long have bent their own intentions to it that nature too is given to upholding it. No doubt humans cause most fires, not lightning. Causes include hazard reduction, burning off and back burning gone wrong, inadvertent escapes, cigarette butts, stupid boys, and arsonists. Some say glass and metal litter can do it too. The figures are not always very good, but according to Stephen Pyne (7), ‘during the 1970s in Victoria, lightning was responsible for 24% of fires’, but accounted for 60% of acres. Lightning fires are most prominent where humans live least and when weather is hot, dry and stormy, which might explain why they consume the most. The intentionsby no means coordinated and consistentof millennia of burners are nothing compared to the self-perpetuating forms of super-individual society and the fiery cultural nature that has evolved. But then each generation takes on the supposed facts of that fiery nature as its norms, and, lo and behold, recognizes in them after all its own cherished intentions. What remains unconscious is the existence of the extra-human dimension of the social process. Fire exclusionists can’t seem to shake the notion that if humans cause most fires then humans can stop it. It’s like capitalism or war. Humans, they say, make history. But they neglect to appreciate how they must make it with the materials inherited from the pastin this case the fiery, self-perpetuating, pyrogenic past.

230

12.6 …As Nature-In-Itself

Wilderness, Or Nature Without Culture The best place to see images of nature is where nature is an image of itself: e.g. in wilderness (and in this it is exactly like TV). Only when seen as merely the image of nature is wilderness released from the awful burden of naturalness that is assumed to be underwritten by its ontological preponderance. Now, like TV, nature is another medium. Wilderness, so called, is a curious concept. In Australia it sounds a bit American. Critics of the concept, especially the Aboriginal ones, point out that traditional Aboriginal societies had no such concept and no wilderness as such: the concept and the thing is an imposition of the invading society. In fact, the invading society is an imposition on itself, and wilderness is an autoimmune response of that society. Wilderness was created by it as a place where its imposition upon itself was not to be allowed, where it was to be cured by cold turkey. That imposition upon itself was an imposition on its naturenot only on its remoter nature of wild places, animals and plants, but also mirrored, as it were, in its most intimate human nature. It should not be imagined that wilderness is something extra-humaneven one of its most renowned American advocates, Aldo Leopold, is wary of that. That would be a case of self-delusion, of taking a norm for a fact, an index for the thing indicated, an image for reality. For wilderness, precisely in its being a deliberately maintained image of extra-human nature is thereby most intimately human. It is a case, to return to Adorno’s words, of grasping nature, ‘in the place where it seems most deeply, inertly natural, as historic being.’ Wilderness is a time-bound concept as much as it is a space-bound thing. Yet, by the norms of its constitution, it would like to be bound neither in space nor time— nor for that matter, in normativity. Like its extra-humanness, such unboundedness is what it represents. Even though made from the matter supplied by nature, even though an index of nature and its history, wilderness is an image of naturenature as the modern spectacle of nature. Not only photographs, TV wildlife documentaries and CDs of birdsongs and whalesongs, but now nature itself is an image of nature. Wilderness is a genre of nature, like pastoral. It is a modern form with special appeal to modern sensibility, but it certainly has ancestral forms. Indeed its ancestral formin this case its material homologous formwas in the great tracts of wild country from which pastoral, among other genres of nature, differentiated itself, the country whose ‘appearance,’ in Samuel Johnson’s words was ‘that of matter, incapable of form and usefulness, dismissed by nature from her care and left in its original elemental state’ (Williams, 1973, 128). Like traditional Aboriginal societies, it seems Johnson’s inchoate modernitynot to mention the nature itself of his daydid not countenance a 231

concept of wilderness, except as a kind of antithesis of nature that lay elsewhere. In colonial agricultural societies like America and Australia, this otherness of wilderness took on its own generic prominence as modern forms of the aesthetic consumption of nature became second nature and as the colonial frontier that had marked the end of the pastoral and the beginning of the elsewhere started to sense its historical and spatial culmination. Wilderness became included in the socially recognized forms of nature precisely in its value as outside of social mediationa self-contradictory prescription, but one that was easily instituted and maintained. It was assisted in this by the aestheticcum-ontological status it already had as ‘appearance’ in such as Johnson’s experience. By its wildness and size it is cognate with the modern idea of sublime nature. For that reason it is most often consumed from lookouts or planes or on TV or just as a big roadless patch on a map. Otherwise it is the object of an adventure: wildwater rafting, mountaineering, or at least a long bushwalk. Just as the sublime became especially poignant at a certain historical moment, so did wilderness. For it is part of the same aesthetic phenomenon and it has it historical genesis in the same context of industrialization, colonialism, travel, the rise of the middle class and tourism. In order to maintain the institution, standards have been drafted about the exclusion of roads, the limits to allowable ecological effects of agricultural, silvicultural and industrial society, and minimum area. Setting up this institution makes the differentiation of wilderness a matter of convenience, a matter of kind rather than degree. It distinguishes wilderness from related smaller genres: nature reserves, national parks and such. All of these though are kinds of fiction with their own version of willing suspension of disbelief. Wilderness as mere image, mere fiction? This claim would be scandalous if it weren’t so easy to dismiss as trite postmodern claptrap. It would be the sort of thing that gets criticized for playing into the hands of nature’s enemies, but wilderness is, after all, just so out there, so material, so ontologically weighty. Like the character in the Leunig cartoon, we do not even have to see it to be reassured. It is one thing that can just exist unseen, utterly defying Berkeleyan Idealism, emanating its natural healing beams. But let’s get our thinking straight here. It is a delusion tantamount to believing in complete fictions to think that images and fictions are not made out of stuff. Nothing is not made out of stuff. What images and fictions are is special stuff that signifies usually quite complex thingsobjects, actions, series of events, conceptsin typically quite elaborate ways, including ways that need in no way be dependent upon the existence of whatever is represented. Wilderness and the other genres of nature are made out of living ecological stuff but we perceive all that reality as inveterately semantic social animals. It is not as sheer abstract stuff but meaningful stuff in our meaningful world. Even to say this stuff is ecological reveals my own sense that its very materiality might be indicated by this term of empirical science, i.e. of the distinctively modern high cultural form through 232

which so much of my and your perception of nature is semantically mediated. Walking the wilderness track I don’t see stuff-in-itself when I look beside me. As Kant long ago made quite clear, any such thing as some kind of pure objectivity of things-in-themselves, is beyond our experience. The best we can do is conceive that there might be such a noumenal or purely intelligible thing. I see a tree goanna scrambling up a red ash. Others who don’t know this country only see a big lizard on a dappled tree. When people from my culture walk through a wildernessor one of the smaller scale genresthey are likely to see a lot of extra-human nature, but to believe this is extra-human nature they have to do quite a bit of trompe l’œil and a lot of willing suspension of (dis) belief. They have to ignore themselves, they have to ignore the path, they have to ignore the distant park boundaries, they have to ignore the park management and the Wilderness Act, they have to ignore the norms and the society and nation state that has instituted this bit of extra-human naturalness as one social and functional category of landscape in a thoroughly apportioned landscape, and they have to ignore all the work of arguing in favour of getting this place declared as National Park or Wilderness. Most of this is easy. Not only are we extraordinarily well practiced in this illusion, wilderness itself works very wellits prized attributes of remoteness and uncultivatedness are especially usefulto conceal all the attached strings and stage devices it uses precisely to create its fiction. Out of sight, out of mind. In fact though it is virtual reality: it is hard to actually not believe in the fiction that it signifiesso hard that almost everyone does believe it. There is an old and persistent suspicion of images and fictions. The 2nd Commandment forbade them, unequivocally. Absolutely no images of anything, it says. That is the literal King James, and even fundamentalists sin like devils against it. Plato would have banned images from his republic too. We may kid ourselves we are well over this but, in one form or another, images remain all too, or at least just a little too, fascinating. They are still suspected of being variously distracting, delusive, not the real thing, mere copies, idolatrous, fetishistic and dangerously influential. Think of pornography, violent movies, advertising, TV, video games, and the various moral, political and aesthetic panics they beget at some time in the quarters of almost all of us. The thinking is that, ontologically, images are obliged to cede absolute priority to whatever they represent, and if we don’t get this straight we open ourselves to moral, political and (in the case of environmental ethics) ecological danger. To say wilderness is an image or a fiction smacks of saying it is not the real thing and not worth believing in and we might as well log it or clear it or dump waste there. I think that this kind of thinking though is precisely a case of having confused the representation with the thing represented, and it actually confirms the suspicions of those who feared the delusory power of images. We seem compelled to profess to some credo, to deliberately confuse norms for facts, and invest the socially instituted form of wilderness with some kind of ontological preponderance. To believe in it! Perhaps this distortion of our 233

understanding follows from the need to defend these images of nature against their destruction: to give no rhetorical quarter and then to believe the rhetoric. No doubt a lot of eco-political rhetoric distorts our understanding and appreciation of natureespecially our understanding of the aesthetics and poetics of nature. However, what I like about wilderness, and all those related genres, is that, like fiction and unless we delude ourselves, they frankly invite suspension of belief. They allow us not to get all fundamentally ontological about nature and its naturalness. And even if we are thinking functionally about nature that is not a bad thing. It allows us to free functionality from its usual narrow ideological confines, which have, time and again, with a kind of puritanical greed, misunderstood the ecological functions of nature for us. Indeed usually it is the vulgar functionalist concept of nature that is taken to be its fundamental ontological status. The pristine or even extra-human nature of which wilderness and the other genres are images are utopias of function. In existing only for itself, the wide-eyed Ground Thrush I see walking along before me in the bush is an epitome of design working for us.

12.7 …As Sheer Appearance The Origin Of Views, Or A Prehistory Of The Image Of Nature In our different ways we all bring a little bit of ignorance of history and add it to the pile. —Don Watson, ‘Garibaldi in an Armani Suit’ What is the origin of the custom of looking at views from the tops of mountains? One story has it that on an the 26th April, 1336 the Italian poet Petrarch was the first to discover or invent this experience when he and his brother and their two servants climbed Mont Ventoux in southern France. Could this have been the beginning of a new aesthetic sensibility, of a certain way of looking at nature? When Clement Hodgkinson gazed down on the Bellinger Valley from Diehappy Ridge was his experience of a kind that began with Petrarch and that has been reproduced again and again down into the contemporary culture of nature? In a letter to his Augustinian friend and confidant Dionisio da Borga San Sepolcro, Petrarch said he wanted to see what so great an elevation had to offer. If what you see from a mountain is nature, then this was an experience of nature as sheer spectacle, useless spectacle. There is a related and perhaps competing story, one about mountains only becoming good taste—in European culture at least—in the 18th century. Both stories are likely to be elaborated with the assertion that before a certain sublime sensibility became part of European

234

culture, mountains were seldom visited because they were considered to be ugly and frightening places. Petrarch was inspired by a passage in Livy’s History of Rome (4.21) in which Philip II of Macedon climbs Mt Haemus in Thessaly. Legend had it that two seas were visible from the top, the Adriatic and the Euxine or Black Sea, and that the Danube and even the Alps could be seen. Philip did not climb Haemus for the hell of it. According to Livy he wanted to keep his soldiers active, and also to remove any suspicion that he might be thinking of war with Rome. Perhaps the Romans were supposed to think that Philip had become obsessed by mad athletic diversions. At the same time though, Philip believed that the view would assist strategic planning in a war with Rome. He thought the spectacle might have a use. On his descent, Philip said nothing to contradict the old stories about the extent of the view. Livy doubted the stories and thought Philip just wanted to avoid the subject altogether for fear of being ridiculed for putting his men through a futile expedition. Livy reports that the king and his party were distressed and dispirited by the climb; but they do seem to have salvaged a sacred purpose from the failure of their military aims, raising alters and making sacrifices to Jupiter and the Sun before they descended. Apparently they did not salvage an aesthetic purpose, but note: often the aesthetic is the profane, modern descendent of the sacred; and in turn, Jupiter, the thunderer, and the Sun are deities that have an ancestry in natural wonders. Petrarch observes that various writers had disagreed on the truth about the extent of the view from Haemus. He himself takes an empiricist’s approach to the academic dispute. Had he not been a long way from Haemus, he would have just climbed the thing to see. Being in France he repeated the experiment, by climbing Ventoux instead. In the history of nature culture a comparable question about truth claims arises: How does one verify the claim about Petrarch being the first sublime mountaintop viewer? It is one that is harder to answer though because, while Petrarch could just climb Ventoux, and more or less repeat the experiment, the events of history happen only once upon a time. They disallow the repeatability of empirical observation. The only things that are empirical in historythe only things that a researcher can observe again and againare the documents. That is why history could scarcely get started until the technology of writing was invented. The question about who was first may be an appropriate historical question, but perhaps a better one is why are historical accounts so fascinated by claims about who or what was first? For it is the pernicious habit of historiography to satisfy this particular fascination by ceasing to be history and reverting to origin myths. I might add that myth is a kind of narrative well adapted to the social environment of oral communication. In the absence of writing, accounts of observations are more subject to variation and, in the absence of their original accounts, the variants are then subject to selection according to uses such as plausibility or entertainment rather than according to the accuracy of the variant or its adequacy to events that can no longer be observed. It is all Chinese whispers.

235

On top of Ventoux, Petrarch opened a copy of Augustine’s Confessionsa gift from Dionigi. It opened by chance, or grace, or narrative contrivance—even Petrarch’s documentation of his climb is a secondary elaboration of events that are now as lost to observation as a dream—at the following passage. Petrarch read it out loud: ‘And men go about to wonder at the heights of mountains, and the mighty waves of the sea, and the wide sweep of rivers, and the circuit of the ocean, and the revolution of the stars, but themselves they consider not.’ (Petrarch, Letter) This turns Petrarch’s narrative to devout thoughts on the uses of spectacle and to its spiritual contemplation. In fact all of Petrarch’s letter is written as a kind of allegorical romance leading to this end. Meanwhile, Augustine’s reference to the might of nature says something about the history of wonder at natural phenomena: whatever Petrarch may have been first to do, it had a well known social ancestryso well known that Augustine had referred to it as a bad habit centuries earlier. Rivers rise all over their catchments. Stand on the trachyte cliffs of Barangarnyatta or Point Lookout, or Nguloongeer or Darkies Point. You can see the water weeping out of the rock walls at your feet. You can hear the Bellinger rising in the deep forested valley far below. It also rises way over in the Never Never, Rosewood and Kalang Valleys, and down at Bishops, Diehappy, Boggy, Cemetery and Hydes Creeks, and in all the other creeks and little gullies that flow off all the ridges. Trace a river back from its mouth and it is an indefinitely branching fractal that ends up covering everywhere in the catchment. The one-dimensional line of the river branches so much it becomes a two dimensional surface. Its sources are marked by every dot of rain that falls on the catchment. History is like the Bellinger, or the Nile. There is no source. History cannot be a search for the origin, because there is no one origin. The origin is everywhere, everywhen. Trace an idea back to its origin and the historian must follow a branching ancestry of transmissions. Along any branch there will be separate traditions joining, and also reticulations in the lines of transmission, where joining traditions reveal common ancestors; and there will be drastic transformations in the meanings of expressions or stories or actions as they are adapted to changed social circumstances, and there will be great gaps in the map where loss of historical knowledge means no lines of transmission can confidently be drawn any more. During their ascent, the young Petrarca brothers meet an old shepherd. He is like one of those wild hermits in some old romance. He tells the brothers that 50 years before in the same ardour of youth as theirs he had made the same ascent, and presumably just for the hell of it, and he got nothing for his pains but fatigue and regret, and clothes and body torn by the rocks and briars. However his attempts to dissuade the brothers only increased their desire to proceed. They are a bit like the first two siblings in the folk tale who 236

ignore the wise advice of a disguised wizard, advice that the blessed third sibling is kind enough or cunning enough to attend to. But in this story there is no third brother. Thereafter, the Petrarca brothers’ ascent signified youth’s suspicions of old warnings, as well as the curiosity to see what could be seenboth of which are venerable, but not exclusively, signs of modernity. So Petrarch repeated the act of climbing a mountain and looking at the view, an act that had had a military function for Philip of Macedon, and an act that in the telling had led to a description of a view that was designed to excite wonder. If the veracity of the description of the view from Haemus was questionable it is precisely because of the power of mountain views, like storytelling, to produce wonder and, by transference, to produce embellished descriptions designed to evoke wonder. Clearly, the function or the meaning of mountain views can change not only throughout a thousand years, but also during a single conversation with a shepherd. And it changes again, as Petrarch up on top reads from Augustine, and picks up another branch of traditiona branch about the significance of all merely worldly wonders. And another onethe branch about the human soul as the proper object of contemplation, the humanist branch already growing in the proto-modern Augustine, and one that would remain a theme in the aesthetics of nature precisely because nature would always seem imperilled by its inhumanity. Petrarch was abashed at the words he read from the cunning old convert (Augustine had already had his fill of such worldly pleasures as love, art and nature) and he was angry with himself for still admiring earthly things when nothing is wonderful but the soul, which, when great itself, finds nothing great outside itself. In fact Petrarch is not so unlike Philip of Macedon: he salvages a sacred meaning from his profane experience. Similar pressuresthe guilty sense of the apparently sensualist value of natural spectacle, the sense of its lack of serious human relevance, and the ambition of achieving a fitting philosophical gravitymade just the environment for eliciting a similar reflection from Rousseau 400 years later. In the fifth of the walks in his Les Réveries du promeneur solitaire Rousseau wrote that the happiness that nature gives us is nothing external to ourselves. Even Kant, an admirer of Rousseau’s and who of all philosophers is the first to give nature its due in aesthetics, could not help but make the aesthetics of nature’s sublime vistas a prelude to moral edification: Therefore nature is here called sublime merely because it raises the imagination to a presentation of those cases in which the mind can make itself sensible of the appropriate sublimity of the sphere of its own being, even above nature. (Critique of Judgement, §28) Having been emptied of humans, especially for the for the sake of its sublime form, nature seemed be left wanting human interest. For Kant, the aesthetic contemplation of nature becomes a kind of resolution of tension between the alien might of extra-human nature and moral reason. Something 237

similar is happening in contemporary Australian nature culture in the critique of the concept of wilderness as a kind of terra nullius for greens. There is a persistent feature of the culture of nature here, a pressure to justify the indulgence of the contemplation of nature. In response, nature, as a form of culture, changes. It takes on different functionssacred, aesthetic, ethical and politicaland, therefore, different justifications in different circumstances. In relation to such sophistical justifications, Socrates the city dweller’s appreciation is the best: expecting nothing of trees and the countryside, he experiences them with sheer delight and gratitude. No one, by the way, bothers to ask whether Socrates was the first to discover or invent the pleasurable uses of shady creeks and loud cicadas or the sweet scents and breezes of summer when he and Phaidros went down by the Ilisosthe little creek below the Acropolis. There, the bare footed philosopher lay back on the grassy bank while his protégé read out a discourse on love. In this case, Socrates explicitly credits Phaidros with prior knowledge of the delights of the place and Socrates, delighted too, thanks him for being such an admirable guide. Socrates confesses to Phaidroswith that patronizing Socratic irony of histhat he had gone as a stranger into the country. As befitted a lover of knowledge, he was a city person. The men in the city had been his teachers, not the trees or the country. Socrates goes on to describe how the inventor of a form of culture—Socrates had in mind the technology of writing—cannot anticipate the uses that will subsequently be made of it. The same goes for stories. Petrarch’s account of his climb has itself changed its uses. What began as a story about a reflective and pious meditation addressed to a religious confidant now persists in modern tales about the origin of Renaissance humanism and about the origin of the significance of mountaintop views. There is that other story about the origin of mountain aesthetics in the 18th century that can be used to explain this feature of modern culture too. As in Raymond Williams (1973, 128) version, it can quote Evelyn’s 1640 description of the Alps with their strange, horrid and fearful crags and tracts. It can quote Dennis’s ruins upon ruins, in monstrous heaps, and Heaven and Earth confounded; or Samuel Johnson’s the appearance is that of matter, incapable of form or usefulness, dismissed by nature from her care and left in its original elemental state. And then it can quote Thomas Gray, in 1739, just a decade before Burke’s aesthetic treatise on The Beautiful and The Sublime, saying not a precipice, not a torrent, not a cliff but is pregnant with religion and poetry. The transformations of these stories have given their retellings and re-readings leases of life by virtue of their adaptation to a commensurably persistent social pressure exerted by a widespread custom of historicism: a prevailing habit that seeks to explain a social phenomenon by tracing it to origins, a habit in response to which the work of historical inquiry itself gets adapted by transformation into a mythology of origins. The observer of sublime vistas is, as Williams noted, a self conscious observer, an observer observing his or her own observation, regulating the kind of attention and constructing the self doing the observation in the process. No 238

doubt this reflexivity applies to reflective types like Petrarch and for that matter, Augustine. Reflexivity, as thinkers from Hegel to Anthony Giddens have stressed, may be a feature of modernity, but it has been around a long time. What seems especially to characterize modernity’s reflexivity is that as well as individual self observation and self consciousness feeding individual self-construction, modern social organization is generated by a dizzying loop of feed back between society and its self descriptionshowever much mistaken or simplisticwhich become reified as the nature of society itself. In its primary movement, the sublime is a reflexive gesture. Maybe the subliming of the experience of mountains happened more than once because if there weren’t something to sublime then it would have had to be invented to meet the need for an object to aid reflexive ecstasy. Following the plot of the allegorical quest, Petrarch went looking for something, so he was sure to find something. Now, long after lookouts have become utterly banal, the sublime persists as a way of aesthetically consuming almost anything. It is the self conscious renovation of sensibility, the extension of sensibility beyond its banal objects to carve out a department of aesthetic experience and move it like a bubble through the worldany world: up mountains in Petrarch’s 14th century or the Romantics 18th; into city crowds in the flaneur’s 19th; or into the shopping mall in the postmodern 20th. This intensely reflexive steering of aesthetic consumption may be modern, but this modernity thing has many ancestors, and certainly not only in the West, and it has been going on, fashioning itself out of the cultural bric-a-brac of the past and getting its forms selected in fits and starts for quite a while now. In such a social evolutionary process things that look like they have been there since the start, or even like they were the start, can look inevitable; but their functions have been changed and their persistence and recurrence can be simply because they can function in different ways in different times and be adapted to different social pressures. Williams himself called the new 18th century attitude not an alteration of sensibility; it is strictly an addition to taste…the wild regions of the mountain and forest were for the most part objects of conspicuous aesthetic consumption… a form of fashionable society, and a forerunner of contemporary tourism. Mountainous terrain found itself in an age of increasingly industrial capital, middle class wealth and a shrinking natural environment pre-adapted to a new kind of marketed sensibility. The most persistent pressure though to which perilous heights and wild tracts are tailored is the old physiological one: vision. In a world of light and flesh, natural selection has fashioned sight from scratch many times, extending perception way beyond the confines of the observer’s flesh, and in such visual animals as ourselves sight is the body at its most brilliant. Its extraordinary biology is objective observation incarnate, conceptual understanding embodied in the senses, the source therefore of knowledge and power. Yet precisely for its power of extending flesh beyond itself, vision is riddled by contradictions. The amazing combination of sensuality and distance, of flesh 239

and spirit, makes it constitutionally duplicitous. It is at once the most refined and the most sensuous of the senses. At times just looking is the finest form of appreciation, the image of disinterested contemplation. At other times it is profane and voyeuristic. Vision is credited with rising above the material, and indicted as an indulgence of power exercised at a heartless unfair distance, sensual and detached, safe and dangerous, fascinated and disinterested, erotic and uncommitted. This is quite enough to give the object of vision the reputation of a fetish. It is declared a mere image and therefore counterfeit, and looking is declared taboo. And therefore it is a taboo deliciously to be broken. No wonder the visual image is the image of the image, and no wonder looking became the customary mode of experiencing nature as an aesthetic object. In looking we make nature in the image of the artistic image, especially in the view. The view is nature as sheer appearance, and a chief ancestor of the modern transmutation of nature into the image of nature.

Outro The image of nature—whether spun by media networks, greens, advertisers, the arts, the sciences, the schools, the National Parks and Wildlife Service, bureaucracies or governments, each to their own ends—cannot just be censored by decree, nor deconstructed and laid safely aside. As the image-makers say, it’s all about image. Perhaps it was ever thus for such an imaginative, semiotic animal as Homo sapiens. In fact most of what anything ever reveals of itself is its image, and everything now, including nature, is made in the image of its image. In fact nature has to be an image of itself, and this raises a question. Now that nature has to be made in the image of itself, is there some art that can make a virtue of this necessity? Can truth and beauty—or what tradition denoted by these words—still be enough?

240

III The Poetics of Nature

241

242

13 The Nature Critic Nature considered as an object for criticism

Hitherto I had carelessly generalized with regard to Nature. Now I particularized. —Jack McLaren, My Crowded Solitude

There is good surf and bad surf. At Hungry Head I swim out through the white water out to the sky blue and other blue swells. Fish stream and thrash about a little further out, making their own white horses. I think of sharks and hope for dolphins. I have to swim hard to get over a sizable wave before it breaks. The surf is bigger than I thought, but not too big. Big enough and curling over into the full water of a high tide. I let the rushing curve of the wave sweep me up its face and slip me through its curling lip and shoot me out the back of everything into the calm water behind and the thing I see when I open my eyes is a gannet gliding by under the crest of the next wave in the set, tipping its great wing against the water. It turns and casts an oceanic eye at me, like a lone pilot in a white passing plane. Like the sea, its unconcern is utter and unrehearsed. Like me it is another being, eyeing. I ride over this wave with enough time to graph the famous curve, wondering what its name and the x, y, z and t of its equation might beall four of its stately, timely dimensions hastening through their partial differentials until that t hits the break point where calculus gives way to turbulent topologyand watching a young bodyboarder riding it and studying the maths from his end. I position myself for the third wave and there is no one else near me. It’s free, like money on trees, and peaking just to the south of me where, having loomed up out of the Pacific, it has lifted its head and paraded itself, just here and now, once only on the east coast, and I am able to swim just four good strokes to get it to take hold of me. This feeling of being taken, of being lifted and falling and floating and accelerating at the same time, of having to give yourself to it in order to catch it. It is Bacon’s maxim about only mastering nature by obeying it. Hardly mastering. With my right arm stretched forward across the wave’s open face, holding me up on the curving surface, and my left arm back along my side and

243

my left hand open like a fin and extended out from my side a little to support me on the steep face, I fly across it. Holding myself high on its face at first to feel the power and poise of it, I then let myself fall fast enough to rise up again with the rising curving water. Once up again I see the wave getting steep for a long way in front of me and, knowing that big open face is all about to close out, I let myself fall again, this time diving down into the base of the curve into the water, and I turn to slip out of the back of the wave like a dolphin, letting its power propel me scot free of the white water. Still in the blue unbroken water, I can smell and hear the marine zing of the froth and turbulence closer to the shore, I can see a footloose kelp wandering over the clear sandy bottom, and there is another gannet, a motley young one this time, sitting on the surface. The set is finished and it is a clear swim back out. I turn on my back, rest my arms and, breathing hard, I fin my way back out on the rip, watching that blue sky and the green shore where in summer the low swifts arc and comb insects out of the sky back behind the beach just above the figs and red beans and brushboxes on the bluff. The onshore wind has not started and there may still be a light offshore disciplining the rows of waves—like a ballet not an army— getting them to hold their heads up, keeping them neat, brushing back the spray behind them, like mermaid hair. Dolphins roll through the fine breeze-wrinkled sea, like coastal shipping saluting with their fins, blowing with the easy power of big mammals and passing north. The folding waves force air out like oceanic breath. I go down to the beach in the morning, hoping that the sea it will be yet another form of this beauty and not be choppy, wild, sloppy, flat or any other kind of unsurfable or not worth surfing. It is never the same twice. The linguist Wilhelm von Humboldtthe brother of Alexander, the naturalistonce criticized a grand, rocky landscape for lacking trees. Or so Theodor Adorno says in his Aesthetic Theory (106). Personally, a lot of sunsets look overdone to me, and sometimes those green lakeside forests of the temperate northern hemisphere look a bit bland and chocolate box compared to a swamp heath or gum trees. They remind me why a painter like Jean-Baptiste Corot could quip that nature had too much green. Or maybe something similar is happening when I complain about the surf. Adorno goes on to say, ‘the stubborn insistence on using one’s faculty of judgement even in the presence of natural givens is naïve, to be sure. But it also points to a relationship with nature that is incomparably more intimate than the one implied by complete satisfaction with it.’ While such a judgement may imply a wish to have nature conform to meddlesome and time-bound human purposes, it also follows from a philosophy of nature, like Goethe’s, which ‘interprets nature as intrinsically meaningful’. Reflection on the aesthetics of nature should not turn too quickly to the most abstractto big questions like ‘What is the aesthetics of nature?’ How does it relate to the aesthetics of art? What is natural beauty?’ It seems unmade nature’s sensed lack of aesthetic credentials can compel such grand reflections, but perhaps prematurely. The pressures of academic society force reflection 244

onto such limited abstractions because the felicities of a digressive, interpretive essay—especially on nature, which is wrongly supposed to epitomize the uninterpretable—would be quickly censored as idle indulgence: abstractions have philosophical cachet; single categories can be analyzed until the theoretician can be satisfied at having left nothing unsaid; if abstract categories are explained everything else that is merely particular is supposed to follow from such generality. Yet like art, nature is too quick and too contingent for ponderous categories and it quickly eludes them. A few stillborn conclusions are the only issue of such prescribed academic labour. Like artworks, natural objects rival one another, and artworks and natural objects rival one another too, as if to annihilate their aesthetic competition, at least in the moment of their beholders’ consciousness. All is emulation, and in emulation there is a kernel of imitationas the common confusion-cum-etymological convergence of the two terms impliesfor rivals would negate one another, but according to some shared standards or virtues that are preserved and enhanced in the negation. As with artworks, this emulation is expressed in the rivalries of taste, not only between one person and another, but between different moments of one’s own experience, between one wave and the next. Walking with friends, half by misadventure half by adventure, through swamp heath, one remarks on the gis of a bee-eater, explaining the term gis as a birdo’s term for the look and movements of a bird. Another explains the different flowers of this heath and that heath, this sedge and that sedge. One sticks his arm down into the peaty soil, displaying the layers of its caky depths and speculating on the geological recipe. Another presents to us the red of dragonflies, the craftwork of spiders, the microcosm of a beetle’s back. Another mocks all this stopping and starting and natural history, feeds us chocolate, reminds us we have miles to go before lunch, and wants to accuse whoever got us in this mess. We all struggle with pleasure through dense, prickly flowering heath, wet under foot, slowly enough to enjoy all the more of it. One follows and composes poetry in the rear. There isn’t a single moment of abstract beauty here. Most reflection on art is critical and appreciative rather than philosophical. But such reflection gives art its due and in doing so is more philosophical for not having stolen the art out of the philosophy of art. On the other hand the aesthetics of nature is philosophically impoverished for their being so little criticism of nature. In national parks, not only tracks, lookouts, visitor centres and interpretational signs, but animal populations, river styles and community flora are, like the surf, matters for critique; excess of woodland, lack of grasses and sedges, rainforest fetishes and places with too many weeds should attract critical appraisal. Oceans, surf, forests, deserts, tourist attractions, lookouts, roadsides, bush at the back of farms or beyond the quarter acre block are all deserving of critique. I walk back from surfing through a strip of littoral rainforest and note the beautification: two or three newly planted progress palms (Arecastrum romanzoffianum) plonked into a viny gap of prickly 245

sarsaparilla, each palm framed from the leaf-litter by little white rings of pale sand; the sand along the side of the path dug up to level a bed for a white quartz garden and heaped up over the adjacent ground where weeds have started to invade beneath old riberries, tuckeroos, coogeras and figs that no-one seems to see. I then drive through dense bristling wallumone of the most beautiful things on earth (as Edward Abee says, there are many such places)past a football field carved into the middle of it, with progress palms (again, always) planted along the road for instant beautification, instantly exotic, instantly sort of tropical. But it is not just these things I want to criticize. They are what might be called unworthy of criticism, like vandalism. At best kitsch, they are not like nature seriously, imaginatively meant as nature. Nature is too good to be left to the travel writers. As well as literary, cinema and art critics there should be nature criticsespecially now that we are doing such a lot of making it, presenting it, framing it and selling it. Without them, mentions of the aesthetics of nature will only signify some vague, trifling, emotional bonus, something so merely subjective before all that objectivity of nature. We write our meanings all over nature, not only projecting ideas, but carving and moulding them into its materials. And then we like to read them back, confusing the written and the given. We delude ourselves that the eternal book of nature is being revealed to us as unadulterated appearance, beyond meaning. When you climb up the escarpment above the junction of the Rosewood River with the Bellinger you reach the basaltic cap of the Dorrigo plateau. After the humid valley, Dorrigo is another countrythe air cooled by altitude, the rolling plateau cleared into green grasslands divided up by privet windbreaks and ploughed paddocks of red volcanic soil. Stretching east along the escarpment there are the sweet smelling coachwood and sassafras rainforests of the Eastern Dorrigo. They are growing on metasediment, not volcanic soils. Driving through it you wonder whether you are in Australia or somewhere lost in geological time. Above their sombre Gondwanic greens rise the black masts of hoop pines. Along the misty ravines, old Antarctic beeches that have grown there a thousand years hold on to the past. The beeches grow out to the west of Dorrigo too, back up into the high trachyte country above the head of the Bellinger where the white gum, messmate and snow gum tablelands suddenly end and the land drops away under misty rainforests down towards the coastal rivers. Right on the edge of the escarpment, just where the road climbs out of the Bellinger valley and onto the plateau, is Dorrigo National Park. Just here, spilling over the edge of the escarpment above Rosewood River, there is a little bit of the old rainforest that grew on the richest Dorrigo soils, the superabundant rainforests that were relentlessly cleaned off the red basalt soils less than a century ago. ‘Rosewood country’ people still call it. Farmers still point out a spur or a couple of trees in a paddock and quote their grandparents: ‘That was all rosewood country over there.’ But it wasn’t just rosewood country, it had hundreds of tree species, and whereas the richest subtropical lowland forests were characterized by white booyong, up here at 800 metres it 246

wasif it was anything in particularblack booyong, with its dark buttressed trunk, big glossy palmate leaves, and plump seeds winged with pale gold foils. Years ago, when I first walked into this high subtropical rainforest it was like entering an old museum. The cliché for rainforest is cathedral. As if its former sacred function had been superseded, here the great cathedral, buttressed and vaulted, had been transformed, like so many others, into an attraction for dutiful, uncomprehending tourists, like me. Even then, the handrails were worn smooth by generations of hands, the path under Crystal Showers muddied by thousands of trudging feet. The trees were like old exhibits. The biggest carabeens, rosewoods, booyongs, crabapples, socketwoods, and stinging trees had old labels on them in copperplate or gothic script. The names sounded like archaic poetry out of another century, left overs from forgotten forms of life. The whole place signified a kind of resigned farewell to a once glorious nature. Here, it seemed, time was deemed to have completed its great works long ago. Now we could only look on and marvel at luxurious works that modern efficiency could not afford and precious time could no longer allow. Huge trees, dying in the natural course of things, looked like worn-out, irreplaceable exhibits waiting for forlorn curators to dismantle them. Even then, my sense that it was a museum may also have been an intimation that, unconsciously, the main exhibit was not nature so much as an old apprehension of nature. It was a museum to a bygone mode of exhibition and a bygone concept of nature partly because it was a museum to nature as bygone. It is still a bit like this, but now the style of exhibition has altered slightly with the times. There used to be visitor centre at The Glade. Now, at the Rainforest Centre built in the early 1990s a kilometre further north along the escarpment, you can still see an exhibition of rainforest paraphernalia. My favourites are still the stuffed animalsa moth-eaten feature that was there on my first visit, purged from the exhibits in the 1990s and reinstated after a refurbishment in 2001. The stuffed animals are my favourites because they still seem properly and preciously moth-eaten and museal, like a childhood stamp or rock collection. I like the rock and fossil exhibits too, and the samples of timber, for the same reason. Most of the exhibits though are designed with the edifying purposes of rainforest interpretation and promotion. Some quote old customs of collection and recent customs of interactivity at the same time, using drawers to hide treasures. But as with most museums, the thing that distinguishes the latest refurbishments is that they still seem to be unaware of their own time-bound look. Their quotations look like they date from the good old days of postmodernity. Meanwhile, the best inroads into the interpretation of the rainforest are in the bookshop next door. And then, somewhere outside, there is the rainforest itself. The soft, prolific greens replace the hard-leaved eucalypts as you drive under the lip of the escarpment at the end of the drive up the mountain. In the National Park itself the rainforest proper is first encountered on display beneath a raised skywalk that reaches out from the escarpment over a viny canopy. This is a kind of architectural folly, at once a fetish that keeps leech-ridden nature at 247

a decorous remove, and a birds eye view of the usually unseen canopy and down the Bellinger valley to the sea. And then, for walkers, there is a gentle, paved pathThe Lyrebird Trackthat slips down out of the sun and links the Rainforest Centre with The Glade. With a bit of effort you can get a wheelchair along it. There is another raised walkway just before The Glade to allay the onset of boredom. It leads walkers up through whatin theoryis the middle level of rainforest structure. Here one encounters habitat for a series of signs about the birds and mammals that you probably haven’t seenthe dazzling regent bowerbird, the nocturnal flying fox. Or you used to. Apparently it has been updated too. Beyond The Glade, the track curves around below the escarpment through the columns of black booyong, yellow carabeen and rosewood forest. It is called the Wonga Walk. It passes Crystal Shower, which looks like an old postcard, and Tristania Falls, which sounds (and looks) like a place for the lovelorn to end it all. The track finally circles back to the Rainforest Centre, satisfying those who can’t bear to retrace their steps6.6 km of dark unadulterated rainforest, except for a little tall eucalypt and brushbox at Hardwood Lookout where you briefly come off the volcanic soil and walk out to the end of a metasediment spur. It all has a kind of massive built structure, adorned with the endless detail of floral invention. You can stroll through the great halls and promenade to ambient music piped in by real birds. Often though the staff at the centre must forget to put on the music, or the house musicians are put off by noisy interlopers. The forest can go quite. Tourists can remark on how little wildlife there is. They seem to be overwhelmed by the monumental quality of it all, which obscures any sense of animate life. But hurrying tourists approaching their 6.6km goal can be obtuse too. They can walk past a performing lyrebird in the middle of loud electronic variations on other bird’s themes as if it were just another audio-visual. No wonder they miss the yellow robins watching from tree trunks, the scrubwrens and ground thrushes among the ferns, the parrots and pigeons in the high canopy, or the pademelons, wallabies and ringtail possums secreted from dawn until dusk. It is like wandering uncomprehending through a grand museum whose treasureseven just those that are not in storageare too plentiful, too demanding, and, by the end, all looking alike. For many, the walk is now a procession between stations labelled with interpretive plaques. What is designed as the interpretation of the forest becomes the actual meaning of the foresta series of goals to relieve the longueurs of a surfeit of natural historywhile the meaning written in leaves, fruits, birds, beasts and flowers goes unread for want of the literacy that the plaques are supposed to redress. Nowadays though, the literacy advertised on the plaques is that of ‘environmental education’, a literacy of ecosystem functions, of leaf litter recycling, of niche and adaptation, and not the mysterious medieval catalogue of trees. At the end of the walk, the effort of having passed all the interpretation stations and walked the allotted kilometres is consummated with coffee and cakes at the Canopy Café, light entertainment by a crooning grey thrush and a couple brush turkeys, and the satisfaction that 248

one’s leisure time has been purposefully spent. The whole experience may be had, as one of the rangers says ‘with your feet never touching the ground.’ It has not been easy for me to see it as nature, or at least not present-day nature and ever renewing nature. Like many a great work its intentions seem to have been foreclosed by traditional interpretation. I have felt a bit suffocated, like Isabelle Archer in Henry James’ Rome. Yet, again like a great work, it turns out to be alive to endless interpretation. Indeed as living naturehowever well this is concealedit is endlessly reinterpreting itself. I have had to read it closely though. I have had to get off the track, away from the program of designed visitor management, get bushed in it and sit down amidst lawyer vine on hunks of blown larva to see beyond the imposed order, to see the huge rosewood disappearing into a strangler fig or the tiny red mite lost on a thigh, and to look at it again and again, working out what is what, distinguishing shield ferns and blood vines and flagellarias from the background of venerable enamelled greens, watching ephemeral showers of booyong, rosewood and carabeen seeds litter the stage, noting the themes and variations of birds, the entrances and asides of animals, the parade of short-lived species germinating, growing, fruiting and dying as gaps where trees have fallen repair themselves. And then there is the slow procession of great time as millions of booyongs appear, endure, succumb, appear again, endure again, succumb again so that in 50 years one may become a small tree and in 150 one may join those selected to reach the canopy and flowerin the pageant that takes place only in certain late summers of their own concerted choosingall around the edge of the escarpment. As well as wandering at leisure over the last bit of the basalt shelf I have been able to walkmore purposefullyway down below it too, along the Rosewood River. I have visited the remote terrace of giant ringwoods, easily the largest and most monumental collection of a species that grows naturally only in the Bellinger and Nambucca valleys. I have crushed the leaves in my hands and smelled the fragrance of aniseed. I have felt the warm wind whistle out of one with a hollow trunk. I have walked up to and stood under that secret grove of old red cedars on McGrath’s Hump, on one occasion losing a local Bellingen historian and the oldest member of our party. While he temporarily suffered cramp, the rest of the party remained intent on its goal. Eventually he decided to walk back to the river by an old track he remembered from years before. To his discomfort he found it overgrown with prickly vines and lantana, almost impenetrable. But not so discomforting as meeting the State Emergency Services search party back where we had started out, and having to endure the chiyacking with his cup of tea. I have seen all the deep green holes along the bouldery Rosewood, each with its attendant 10 kilos of long-finned eel. And I have walked through the last uncleared alluvial flat of Lowland Bellinger rainforest where you can climb up 20 metres through the hollow centre of a strangler fig, like climbing a belltower of gothic filigree that leans out over the stream.

249

I have also been able to experience it all as ambient backdrop, for that too is proper to aesthetic experience, just as we have to experience architecture, as Walter Benjamin said, ‘in a state of distraction’, or as we may experience even the best music as background to everyday life, or as, in the morning I have seen the dolphins passing, bait darting, and terns eyeing and diving while I was surfing. Memorably, a talkative friend once spent the entire 6.6km of the Wonga Walk and a coffee and cake at the café telling me an astonishing, convoluted philosophical tale linking Ludwig Wittgenstein’s language philosophy and Mikhail Bakhtin’s theories of narrative, via the Russian Revolution, Bakhtin’s brother, the White Russian army, and a roundabout journey from the USSR to Britain via the Middle East. I still wonder how apocryphal it all was. So now the walk still evokes images of this seldom seen friend and his act of storytelling. It never calls to mind the wonga, the fat steelblue pigeon with the white necklace, whose loud, relentless call and ringing wing beats I have never actually heard there on the track that someone chose to name after it. It should be called The Turkey Track but, in describing both the primates and the avifauna, that was apparently rejected as too inappropriately appropriate. As is the case with works of art, even the most specific and contingent occasions of personal experience, even the most idle thoughts, can enrich the object, as if to testify that what seems utterly subjective is actually part of the objective character of aesthetic objects, and that it is the multitude of individual experiences, as well as self-persisting nature itself, that makes the aesthetics of nature more than merely subjective. Perhaps, in my experience of the museal Dorrigo rainforest, I was jaded right from the start. This rainforest is so accursedly natural it is unnatural. And people just gush so much about rainforest. It makes me want Humboldt’s rocky hillside without the trees, or some dry tufts of barbwire grass and bull ant nests under the hot sun, and not these venerable carabeens. I would just as soon poke about under the 10m high bat-shorn canopy of stinging trees down on the little remnant of lowland rainforest on Bellingen Island, or in the sad little bit of swamp heathJohn Birmingham calls it ‘swampy-looking pissed-out bushland’left beside the road at Coffs Harbour airport, or the long hot forest that lines the Pacific Highway from Urunga to Ku-ring-gai, full of plastic litter. I would certainly like others to see these placesespecially the litterers or the road makers or the air travellers. Just to see them. In fact the neglected halflandscape left in junked semi-ruin by the quick just-get-what-you-can culture of grab-grab, make-do-for-now-only pseudo-progress repristinated with a bit of exotic beautification is, despite what I said above, a most important object for the nature critic. It is an undiscovered continent of unredeemed beauties. Perhaps the thing that sounds naïve about Humboldt’s critique is not the wrong-headedness of judging nature’s givens but the particular genre of judgement. Like his brother, Humboldt was one of the most interesting thinkers of his time, but this particular judgement of the treeless landscape sounds a bit glib. It sounds too much like it is based on the all to common notion that aesthetic judgement, whether in matters of art or nature, should come down to a 250

knowing censure or the mere thumbs-up or thumbs-down of satisfaction. No doubt too much critique of art, literature and cinema is of the advertising blurb kindthe excessively adjectival kind that gets quoted to sell a book or an exhibition. Or it is the inevitably false kind demanded by circumstances when acquaintances in the cinema foyer want to engage us in the conversation genre of instant Judgement; although demanded under polite duress, such judgements come back to haunt us. A lot of the rest is of the know-all would–be editorial kind in which self-assured style arbiters parade the most contingent or passing judgements of taste as if they were unimpeachable aesthetic truths. Like a critic of the arts, the nature critic needs to be able to make more than glib or bantery one-line judgements. And the surprisingly uncommon ability to carefully observe and truthfully describe one’s own subjectivity and its response to objects should never be relinquished just for the sake of never appearing to reveal anything less than self-assured taste. Glib good taste is much easier than the trials of critical observation, self-observation and reflection, and the attendant risk of looking stupid. The nature critic needs to open up to the experience of the natural object— even to bad surf. Any critic needs to be open to the experience of the thing otherwise it is not allowed to show itself and be seen in the terms it demands. We should not censor the claims that things make and then judge them on the basis of such an inhibited experience of them. Almost anything deserving of harsh judgement will reveal its limitations according to the same terms it would like to claim as its own. This is why hypocrisy is a typical symptom of bad nature, as of bad art. However, opening up to nature, like opening up to art, does not merely mean exposing ones unformed sensibility in order to experience authentically natural responses. Walter Benjamin said somewhere that the better the theoretical understanding of art, the richer the appreciation. He argued by analogy, citing what for him seemed like the more obvious case, namely, the way that an understanding of natural science enhances the appreciation of nature. Benjamin’s argument needs to be made both ways. There is no better gloss or footnote to nature than science. Opening up to nature means asking of nature as many questions as one can, in order to elicit all the responses and suggestions that such a complex object may make. This means that opening up to nature is not something done in a kind of natural innocence unencumbered by the baggage of learning. The more you know about nature, the more you see, the more it reveals, and the more you realize you don’t know. The aesthetic experience of nature is something done by drawing on all of one’s experience and all of societyscientific, artistic, ethical, political. This is one reason why the loss of so much of the Gumbaynggirr culture is a loss twice over. Not only did colonial society clear away so much of the traditional nature but what was left was desolated of its meaning. This is why so much of the nature of Australia, insofar as it would seem pristine, risks hypocrisy. Nature may not be intrinsically meaningfulunless, that is, there is a bit of conscious, semiotic nature like us around to read a meaning. Then all that limits what it has to say is our ability to read it. It is a mistake to think aesthetics is 251

just something to do with the senses or with subjective perception. The aesthetics of nature is a matter of meanings, including scientific meaning and the meaning of the passion that it excites. It is with meaning, whether ambiguous or precise, conceptual or not, that nature responds to questions the way any object of wonder does. Questioning is another name for wonder, the way a child wonders how old the yellow carabeen is while hiding between the buttresses. What are buttresses for? Why are those mistletoe leaves like the leaves of the gum tree it’s growing on? Has anyone ever used a walking stick made from the stem of a walking stick palmthat miniature palm with the red fruits? Are they red because you can eat them, or because you can’t? What tree did these speckled flowers fall from? Why were they made to look so beautiful? What is the difference between beautiful and pretty? How did those lianas climb all the way up there? Where do the pademelons go during the day? How much do stinging trees sting? What must it have all been like a thousand years ago? Who walked through it then and what did it say to them? Was this rainforest always here? Why doesn’t the rainforest grow out again over the cleared plateau? And nature answers in many wayssometimes in the finest detail; sometimes neither speaking nor concealing, but indicating; sometimes as Heracleitus said the Sibyl did, ‘with raving mouth, unadorned, reaching out over a thousand years’; sometimes with more questions: that carabeen is as old as a giant yellow carabeena few hundred of years if you guess. Or do the science and carbon date it! Trees may use the buttresses bequeathed to them by evolution for many thingssupport, breathingbut what I find fascinating is this: I think an adaptation implies a function, yet I find no satisfaction in any of the speculated functions for this so common feature of rainforest trees. Again it seems there is scientific labour to be done here: Would such research identify functions? Or more profoundly, could it demonstrate that not all selected features have functions? Fascination with the wherefores of features and their functions, can lead thought as much towards profundity as myth: Until someone say found a function for mistletoes’ imitating their host’s leaves, who says that they are alike? The child or the tree or the mistletoe? Meanwhile, I would love to try a walking stick made from walking stick palm, but I could never cut one. The fruits were not made red for us, but they are red so that something like a bowerbird or us might see and eat them and spread their seed. Try them anyway because, like bowerbirds, we were made to see red. Don’t try the cyanic blue fruit of the little honeysuckle bush beside it though. No tree bears those creamy flowers flecked with purple; only the wonga vine. They were not made beautiful for us. They are pretty when we pick them for ourselves, and beautiful in their unconcern for us. Those cissus vines climbed up on the trees while the trees were growing up to fill a gap; those lawyer palms climbed up slowly out of the shade, hooking their way up on the trees that were already there. Pademelons and all the animals can disappear into the forest only revealing themselves to those with eyes to see, or those who can sit quietly and wait, or those who come at dawn or dusk. Brush your arm on the roughness of the 252

stinging tree leaf. It asks you to brush it with its look like a big pale green heart. Look closely at the roughness and see that it is made of small curved needles, syringes of sting. Feel nothing for a second and then feel the first sharp moment, and then the daylong lingering sting, and feel the memento of the sharpnesswhenever you wash your handswhere your body likes to keep it, deep in your armpit. What must the forest have been like a thousand years ago! It must have been something like this, but its old voices have become almost silent, and forever. And beyond that, even this forest was not always here. Meanwhile, now everything has changed again. It would take a thousand years and a thousand wills to get something like this forest to grow out over the plateau again. People are only just startingif all that a few have been doing could yet be called starting.

253

254

14 Natural Beauty The aesthetics of nature explained

I realized before long that the knowledge they had of nature was an entirely vulgar one that wholly failed to meet my requirements; that they were merely specialists of feeling and totally ignorant of its object. —Louis Aragon, Paysan de Paris The justification for pretense to disengagement derives from our Victorian habit of marginalizing the experience of art, of treating it as if it were somehow ‘special’—and, lately, as if it were curable. …I cannot imagine a reason for categorizing any part of our involuntary, ordinary experience as ‘unaesthetic,’ or for imagining that this quotidian aesthetic experience occludes any ‘real’ or ‘natural’ relationship between ourselves and the world that surrounds us. —Dave Hickey, Air Guitar: Essays on Art and Democracy

‘Philosophy of art usually lacks one of two things: either the philosophy or the art.’ So Friedrich Schlegel said. Something similar happens in the aesthetics of nature. It usually lacks two of two things: the philosophy and the nature. Quaint, dry or irrelevant, aesthetics is merely academic. Art mostly gets on without it, setting a cultural pace that leaves aesthetics way behind. In the case of nature, aesthetics gets acknowledged on occasion as a matter of inexplicit thrills, a bit of an embarrassment. It’s a word that makes some people say they want to reach for their guns. You see it listed as a value in bored intros to plans of ecological management, or as the last reason why a patch of bush should be preserved: biodiversity, tourism, recreation, biochemical or genetic resources, water catchment protection, carbon sequestration, ecosystem services, etc, etc…and, o yes, aesthetic values. There it is at the end, ad hoc so it’s not too embarrassing. It makes the list that bit longer. It might appeal to someone, maybe even the right someone. It’s a sign of the author’s cultural sensitivity

255

and a sign of the documents exhaustive consideration. Beyond that, aesthetic matters don’t matter. They are unexplained and deemed inexplicable. For all that, aesthetic motives are more prevalent than the culture of nature likes to admit. Most environmentalist arguments camouflage aesthetic intentions in functionalist rationalizations. This way they can survive and reproduce in political, and market environments that would otherwise be quite hostile. In 1864 in Man & Nature; or Physical Geography as Modified by Human action, the geographer G.P. Marsh argued that human production was destroying the fabric of nature on which humans ultimately rely. This is sometimes cited as the first explicit statement of such a sentiment. Modern environmentalism owes its genesis and success to this timely hybridization of aesthetic and functionalist judgement. And it is not just a camouflage or a subterfuge. Ecology makes valid claims that turn out to be consistent with norms in the aesthetics of nature: callous destruction of natural beauty does come back to haunt human natureit doesn’t just rob those nature-loving ecologists of their favourite subject matter. However, because aesthetic claims are regarded as suspect in the worlds of the market, politics and science, there is quite a bit of pressure for deception to be employed in environmentalist rhetoric. Repression of aesthetic motives and even self-deception about them turns out to be a good working strategy. Lest it should leave itself open to suspicion and rejoinder, environmental culture shuns aesthetic reflection, thereby diminishing the passion and intelligence of experience. In environmentalist polemic and ecological management, aesthetic experience is only the means to other ends. As emotive it is used to sell some arguments but deemed to jeopardize others. It bubbles along in unconscious, or furtive forms until the weekend where it might inspire the Landcare group, or, more likely, the picnic or bushwalk. At best, as recreation or lifestyle, it can be sold to make a tourist dollar from the well enough to do. Natural beauty is the inspiration of much artistic expression and many a traveller’s tale, but so seldom does it inspire philosophical reflection, critical judgement or attempted explanation that it has a reputation for defying all three. Nearly all disputes about nature are aesthetic, whether consciously or (mostly) not. The usual suspicions about such a claim are just hoodwinked by some prissy concept of aesthetic. When it comes to evaluating nature, the serious task of living a good life is allowed almost nothing to do with it. Natural beauty sounds too much like sheer luxury, an insult therefore to those who can’t afford it: if it’s only a luxury, nature deserves to be expendable. Those who argue this way—and it still insinuates itself deep into the common sense of the age—are the heirs of the old middle class trust that the worthwhile riches of the past and nature have been gathered and stored forever in the museums and theme parks of the present even if only for the pleasure of an elite elected by the happy accidents of a history whose fortuitous character dissolves political qualms and clears all conscience. By rights, the same should (and does) go for art and what’s called cultural heritage and any other form of wealth that has been spirited away from those whose experience of it is deemed 256

by the same argument to be expendable, and yet in whose name the argument is piously invoked. Science seems useful and might be exempted, and sport is inalienable and definitely exempted. Environmentalism, like someone trying too hard to look serious at a funeral—or useful—takes refuge in sober clichés like sustainability, ecosystem services and maintenance of biodiversity. And it takes comfort in a consoling naturalism where almost irreconcilable ends such as biodiversity, ecosystem functions, whole-of-landscape management, and contradictory aesthetic tastes are unquestioningly reconciled nevertheless. Ends and means get mixed up in a miasma of rationalizations. On the one hand, in a typical functionalist argument, predicted global warming portends gloomy social consequences and the bleaching of coral reefs is suggested as an indicator of the warming effect. Yet preserving coral reefs is a reason for avoiding global warming before it is a means to predicting it or confirming it: bleaching in itself is a bad end. On the other hand, in an affronted reaction to the technocratic calculations, ecocentric thinkers advocate nature as an end in itself, claiming that coral polyps have a right to exist for their own sake. We find that what’s called environmental philosophy ends up in a school debate over whether the malaria protist should exist for its own sake too. In the process, narrow-minded functionalist reason seldom gets exposed for what it is —i.e. not nearly functional enough. It is so clumsy and dysfunctional that it is incapable of ministering to the serious matter of aesthetic life and the pursuit of happiness. Coral polyps, while happily existing for their own sakes, deserve, even in their utter unconcern for us, to exist happily for ours. Why find functions for nature or art? It is like finding functions for living. As in the case of art, there are theories that explain and excuse nature as therapeutic, cathartic, spiritual, uplifting, universal, morally edifying, cultural heritage, good practice for real life, materially useful, profitable, or good for its own sake. Modern environmentalism is usually forced to use the excuse that what gets called the environment is either useful and profitable, or else venerable and vulnerable national heritage. Good for mumbling or intoning, depending on the context, the cliché high conservation value comes in all too handy. The task of arguing for nature or art reduces us to finding functions, for functions are the inflated currency of impoverished reason. Yet, as life, these things have no functions, not even for themselves. We make great social and intellectual efforts to distinguish art from life and aesthetic nature from life, forgetting in the process that this is just a manner of speaking and that the reason we are distinguishing art and aesthetic nature from life in the first place is precisely because they are such important parts of life—parts we live for— and not something other than life. It is received wisdom that if we abandon nature to aesthetics we abandon it to mere subjective taste, for which, as is well known, there is no accounting. However, for the functional necessities of ecosystem services, we assume that we can render accounts. Think tanks of ecosystem economists make careers out of pricing them and thus making them comparable and exchangeablemostly ignoring the fact that markets price things, not economists. Come to think of it, 257

price is as obscure and alien and arbitrary as taste. Only its numerical character makes it seem transparent and objective: you can readily know and compare the price of everything even if you know the value of nothing. Really, Karl Marx was right: price is a queer thing abounding in metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties. I am almost tempted to say it is subjective, but it is no more or less subjective than tasteeven if the taste of others may sometimes seem unaccountable. What is much more interesting about both price and taste is their peculiar character as objectively obscure or alien or arbitrary. It seems that aesthetic Judgement can hardly be reduced to anything like a precise and consistent science, and in naïve common sense it is simply assumed to be about ineffable matters that can only be felt. Feeling is the most vague and abstract sphere of experienceas Hegel rightly observed in his lectures on the philosophy of art. Certain categories of feeling may quickly come to mind. We can all sort of describe our own inner experiences such as pleasure, joy, anxiety, sadness, anger or whatever. Although they are hidden from the direct observation of others, and although they are often confused, the evolution of language has at least bequeathed us words to denote these obscure things that we all seem to share and understand. But few words for would-be aesthetic feelings come springing to one’s mind, and hardly in any natural, exhaustive or universally acknowledged taxonomy. Is aesthetics just too subjective? Too inward for speech to frame. Well no. People forget that when they see beauty in a flower, they have no trouble finding others who see it too. Aesthetics, whether in art and nature, is also about, must be about and is primarily about what is concrete and objective. Apart from the objective human nature that all those subjects share and share words for, there are the objects themselves of aesthetic experience, the objects in which, as our language tells us, beauty inheres: this is why the aesthetics of nature can’t lack nature. People seldom think about this when they hear the word aesthetics. They think vague feeling rather than detail and meaning, and mere vagary enlists a vocabulary too impoverished for people to engage properly in everyday talk about the aesthetics of nature. It is an embarrassment really. One of the few words that has any sort of aesthetic credentials is beauty, but it is not enough. It is called upon to do too much, and to many it sounds too precious, too limited, too old fashioned, too quaint, too subjective. Serious art, for instance, does not like to let itself be seen being too much interested in beauty any more. Sublime is another word that comes to mind, but it is even quainteran epithet for advertising lookouts, mountain resorts and the tourist attractions of a bygone age. Even while Wordsworth was describing sublime views and banking their memory for his geriatric consolation, August Wilhelm Schlegel was already calling the sublime a laxative for intellectual constipation (Luhmann, 89). The sublime at least has a long and interesting history, but its meaning has been unstable and its references always vaguely hyperbolic and, like everything in aesthetics, vaguely ineffable. During the 18th century though, the two terms—beauty and sublime—were selected by philosophical culture to meet the demand for a technical division of the firmament of aesthetic 258

experience. By the late 20th century the pair had become an exemplary binary opposition for students to practice their deconstruction on. In Molière’s La Malade imaginaire, in the burlesque of a student’s admission to his doctorate, the student opines that opium induces sleep by means of a vertus dormitiva or a sleep inducing principle. Beauty and the sublime are a bit like this. They are used to render whatever induces aesthetic experience thinglike and therefore conceivable. Commitment to the existence of such things should be made with an appropriate ontological levity. Theorising in terms of such things is not so much wrong as inadequate. They wield so little explanatory power. Still, at some stage in the historical evolution of aesthetics, positing a vertus dormitiva or two was an important theoretical move. In western philosophy the two ideas go back to the ancient Greeks, but in 1757 Edmund Burke wrote his Philosophical Inquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful: with an Introductory discourse concerning Tastein response, it is said, to some passing remarks of Joseph Addison. Eventually, after Kant had offered the world his Critique of Judgement, the two terms seemed to stand with as much authority as the same philosopher’s division of reason into pure and practical, of knowledge into transcendental and empirical, of propositions into analytic and synthetic and of the action of thought into subject and object. When Kant proposed categories people took notice, so that, even in the late twentieth century, postmodern theorists who had deconstructed most things, were still trying to describe aesthetic phenomena by resorting to re-jigged versions of the concept of the sublime. Admittedly, ever since Modernism, theorists have been reticent about beauty and ironic about the sublimealthough this was partly to protect the concepts against inflation and devaluation. The sublime and the beautiful, a pair that epitomizes a kind of make-do ideology, have lived on to give aesthetics at least the starting point of a tradition. The sublime was experienced in the presence of the overwhelming might of naturebut only at a safe distance. Nietzsche said we only liked mighty nature because great human beings were lacking. Grand views, wilderness, wildfires and waterfalls would all fall under the label sublime. Beautyin a kind of oppositional reflexwas often associated with the detail. If sublime was grand and limitless, beauty was otherwise. Kant’s Critique is the definitive work, so in his words: The beautiful in nature is a question of the form of an object, and this consists in limitation, whereas the sublime is to be found in an object even devoid of form, so far as it immediately involves, or else by its presence provokes a representation of limitlessness. (§23) The oldest and most persistent theory of beauty—Pythagoras’s—says beauty consists in harmonious proportion. Which either makes beauty sound very simple and dull or doesn’t get us far and doesn’t answer much. It doesn’t explain the appeal of dissonance for instance. Kant has at least got more to say. 259

He saw the limitation in which he said beauty consisted, as a matter of apparent design, as a matter of beautiful objects seeming to be so formed as if for some inscrutable end. Self-subsisting natural beauty reveals to us a technic of nature which shows it in the light of a system ordered in accordance with laws the principle of which is not to be found within the range of our entire faculty of understanding. (§23) From this Kant drew a more detailed distinction between the two categories: …that if, as is allowable, we here confine our attention in the first instance to the sublime in objects of nature (that of art being always restricted by the conditions of an agreement with nature), we observe that whereas natural beauty (such as is self-subsisting) conveys a finality in its form making the object appear, as it were, preadapted to our power of judgement, so that it thus forms of itself an object of our delight, that which, without our indulging in any refinements of thought, but, simply in our apprehension of it, excites the feeling of the sublime, may appear, indeed, in point of form to contravene the ends of our power of judgement, to be ill-adapted to our faculty of presentation, and to be, as it were, an outrage on the imagination, and yet it is judged all the more sublime on that account. (§23, my italics) It is in this quality of the sublime’s being an outrage to the imagination that the sublime has descended into modern aesthetics, because so much of the revolution of sensibility in modern aestheticsespecially in arthas consisted in outraging taste and calling on a kind of the sublime sensibility to transcend and to redeem this outrage. The unstable meaning and vaguely hyperbolic reference of the term sublime is apparently the result of sublime apprehension turning on itself and subliming itself. A striking feature of Kant’s aesthetic theory is that it was primarily an aesthetic of nature rather than art. Aesthetic theory has mostly had it the other way round ever since. You get the feeling that Kant wasn’t someone with a compelling interest in or knowledge of art. He never discusses a particular artwork the way he might the song of a nightingale. This may just be because of the persistence of his habit of philosophical abstraction, but if so, it is a habit that allows the experience of unadulterated beauty only after having made abstraction of the dark subject matter that could haunt, say, a human song. ‘The bird's song tells of joyousness and contentment with its existence. At least so we interpret nature—whether such be its purpose or not' (§42). Without abstraction of the sense, Kant could hardly have listened to say Don Giovanni with the same disinterest. Both a natural philosopher with an early interest in cosmology and a man attracted to the thought of Rousseau, it is perhaps not surprising that he thought an interest in natural beauty was ‘the mark of a good 260

soul (§42)’, whereas, he thought this was not necessarily so in the case of an interest in artistic beauty. There is a sense in Kant that art was all too subject to the corrupting possibilities attendant upon human freedom. Freedom lay at the heart of his differentiation of art from nature. It lent the ancient distinction its peculiar poignancy for the 18th century and for the subsequent romanticism of nature. Willful artifice could only beget artificiality. Art is distinguished from nature as making (facere) is from acting or operating in general (agere), and the product or the result of the former is distinguished from that of the latter as work (opus) from operation (effectus). (§43) ~ What have these far away 18th century European thoughts to do with the bush? Firstly, shouldn’t I be writing about the nature of Australia as an Australian reflecting on Australian sources? It’s a problem—this expectation to be always being Australian. It gets in the way of seeing the bush. Like Europe, Australia is mainly somewhere else. There are some words written by Umberto Eco that have been struck on a brass plate and set in the paving of the forecourt of the Sydney Opera House: Australia is not only the Antipodes. She is far away from everything, even herself. What epitomizes this is the old pop literary myth in which Australian nature is prepackaged as daunting, hard to like, something that requires us to sublimely overcome our fears, something that only the rugged bush legend or the artist as hero can come to terms with it. This bit of pseudo-heroic blather obfuscates the aesthetics of nature, insists on alienation where there is mostly affection. It is in fact a descendent of European tradition, yet it is an adaptation corrupted by heedless rehearsal and role-play, and it is thus more estranged from the bush than its aesthetic ancestors. Theirs is a promise of the intimacy of experience that we find constantly giving the lie to the myth. It is even in the experience of those most new to the bush. We read of it in Watkin Tench’s descriptions of the bush or see it in John Glover’s paintings. The dangers of the bush demand no more respect than the city’s. It will kill you but it’s decent says a character in Les Murray. What I am reflecting on is the aesthetic experience of the bush. Although I don’t want to sacrifice its particularity, I do want some explanations—and not just national myths that simply demand more explanation—so I need general explanatory terms. Everyone has some of these terms—beautiful, sublime—lying around in the shed of ideas, like tools losing their edge. When it comes to nature, Kant as much as anyone described and calibrated the way we use them. Only they are not as useful as they might once have been. They need sharpening with better explanations, and they need to be supplemented with other concepts. Second, what I like about nature is in the particulars, in the inexhaustible detail and design. I find myself wanting to comb the foliage of a herb through my fingers and wonder what it is and why its flowers might have five petals and 261

not four. Is it for lovers? She loves you, she loves you not? The detail that I especially like is the narrative detail—what happens in what sequence and when and how and why and with whom or what: the daily goings on and the annual departure and return of certain birds; the surprise of a new arrival; the succession of herbs and flowers and ferns and vines and trees, sometimes as expected, sometimes against expectation and yet revealing a curious new consequentiality. It is not just the unfolding observation of these things but the unfolding relation to them (and to others through them) like the gradual acquaintance of a shy swamp wallaby, or the tending of flowers or lizards at our fingertips. Although Kant appreciated nature’s details and designs, he too tended to make it vague and abstract, perhaps for the sake of philosophical generalization, perhaps so his experience of natural beauty was not adulterated with the darker purposes of nature. Flowers are free beauties of nature. Hardly anyone but a botanist knows the true nature of a flower, and even he, while recognizing in the flower the reproductive organ of the plant, pays no attention to this natural end when using his taste to judge of its beauty. (§16) This habit of thought turned out to be well adapted to the pop aesthetics of the bush. Repeated more for its adaptation to specialization and the division of labour, or to habitual thoughtlessness, it has lived on to alienate aesthetic reflection and therefore aesthetic experience from the bush. Nature as the object of aesthetic experience is supposed to be non-conceptual and non-intentional— a view not so far removed from the notion that aesthetic experience is ineffable. It misjudges aesthetic experience of nature, ignoring the other side, namely that like art, and for semiotic animals like us, nature speaks. Nevertheless it became the popular prescription for the aesthetic experience of nature. Beauty and the sublime remained too abstract and therefore, as modern art suspected, too vague and superannuated, to explain the aesthetics of anything much anymore. They are nouns coined to give a false sense of definition to intangible abstractions drawn from innumerable instances of experience, to give certain vague feelings a certain certainty. Sure we know what it is to experience them, but to name them explains nothing. They demand explanation and so does all the other aesthetic stuff, the content of aesthetic experience that exceeds them. We best appreciate nature when we know something about it, when we know enough about it to actually see it, when we are not merely experts in feeling. I appreciate this when I walk with someone who knows and notices things that I don’t, who spots bird’s nests, animal traces, mushrooms, and insects, who hears and knows frog calls and bird alarms, who reads the history of a place from the rocks and plants, who dawdles and peers and takes ages just to walk a kilometre of track, who is the first to set off up a creek or a hill and the last to get back and who doesn’t bother to reach the top. Even a child can sometimes instruct a field ecologist or an indigenous expert in some of these things. There is too much to see, and maybe that is why so much aesthetic reflection cannot help 262

but abstract too much detail. Or maybe it because, as a stylist, nature is unsurpassed. Like a supreme artist it seems to understand that those things are best that best withhold meaning, an eloquence that demands confidence in the wealth of one’s meaning and very great technique. Yet as a result nature seems mostly to just go over people’s heads. Its eloquence may be sensed but it escapes articulate consciousness or analysis. Most people are more familiar with the kind of curious contemplation demanded by nature—at once fascinated by detail yet blissed into abstraction—when walking through the mall and browsing through the supermarketthe blissful urban analogue of the bushwalk. Vague aesthetic feelings about nature go with the vision of nature as a vague blur of green, a backdrop to lifestyle. The unreflective aesthetics of nature ‘annihilates all that’s made to a green thought in a green shade;’ but even in Marvel’s poem this annihilation is only one intoxicated moment among the many pleasures and the sharper stings of his garden. Third, modern artistic culture has used a cultural descendent of the sublime sensibility in its ongoing revolution of sentiment. This has now to be adapted to the poetics of nature. The old sublime view of nature seems like an escape from nature, and when nature is so badly done by, the idea of sublime safety from nature looks a bit domineering, and a bit ridiculous. It lives on in the thrill of the wilderness experience, and of course in lookouts, cable suspension cars, and those raised walkways through or over rainforest canopyway above the ticks, leeches, and stinging trees. It’s pop nature culture. Part of sublimely transcending the old experience of nature is to supersede the old vague, abstract feelings of sublime views, the frisson of the so called wilderness experience, not to mention the customs of the pretty chocolate box lake, the view at sunset or the gum tree framed view. One thing I like about the Dorrigo Skywalk—the walkway that runs off the escarpment and looks down over the rainforest and the Bellinger Valley—is the way it gets you up to the beautiful detail that you seldom see: coachwood flowers turning into galaxies of red stars over the foliage, black apples ripening within reach, feathery sassafras seeds blowing away in the wind, and wonga, cissus and staff vines like a net all over the top of the canopy for carpet pythons to stalk ringtail possums through. Of course I still walk out to the end and revive the old 18th sensibility, gratified and elated, looking way down on the big bend of the Rosewood River with its various types of forest mapped in their allotted hues over the ridges, and then to the Bellinger Valley, beyond McGrath’s Hump, with its little patches of pasture cut out of the dark cloth of the bush, and way off in the east, the sea, the sea. In Australia it is a common experience that a taste for the bush has superseded an earlier taste for less sophisticated, less demanding, less satisfying forms of nature. The role of unsophisticated nature has usually been played by the infantile fare of Northern Hemisphere greenery and scenery. Europe seems uncultured when it comes to nature. In Australia nature could seem Modernist or avant-garde or difficult, while in Europe it cannot help but seem a little naïve or primitive. Kitsch even. Perhaps this accounts for some of the distaste for the bush and for the eternal recurrence of real estate subdividers equating 263

development with bulldozing it. Also in Australia, personal ontogeny has recapitulated national phylogeny. The country was colonized by a sublime sensibility that acquired a taste for the gum tree picture, a sensibility which replaced, and thereby rendered more infantile, the taste for the easy aesthetic comforts of green and pleasant land. The great theme of Australian landscape painting, the central tradition of Australian graphic art for 200 years, was the development of techniques and a sensibility for capturing the nature of Australia. According to official interpretations, if not those of the artists, this has been how the project of artistic modernity has understood itself, transplanted to the shores of Terra Nullius. Let me announce, in order to anticipate with due irony, a critique of the sublime colonial gaze that must surely suggest itself to habituated cultural criticism: The continent was colonized by an inherently violent and aesthetic sensibility of power, a way that western sublime sensibility had of capturing landscape. From Lewin to Glover to von Guérard to Heidelberg to Heysen to Nolan to Williams to Robertsonin this sequence lies the progress of an invasion; call it the mental fight that accompanied European invasion from the First Fleet to the Wik legislation, the image of nature that realized itself in the new culture of nature. The Darkies Point massacre has its spiritual analogues on revered display in the galleries of Sydney and Melbourne. This driver of the development of an aesthetic of nature is not so far removed from the wild human nature of domination. But it is just another detail in the sublime and beautiful aesthetics of nature, just more matter for aesthetic sensibility and practice, just another thing for nature to show us and another reason why we need judgement and critique of the historical detail. It is time for a culture of nature in which nature is not only beautiful or sublime or ineffable, but outrageous, astonishing, imaginative, original, ironic, parodic, comic, prosaic, political, theorized, disputed, riddled with isms, unorthodox, eloquent or self-critical, and full of details and stories and meanings and nuances. This is an all too adjectival way of putting it, like a book cover blurb. What matters is what is in the book of nature. What’s in the book of nature is just as all these adjectives would have it. Only custom seems to inhibit our experience. Now that we cannot avoid a poetics of nature, it is time to sublime our experience of nature. So what interests me most about that Skywalk with its bit of rainforest is that it is an historically specific bit of our nature culture and that, like a lot of popular culture, it naively expresses awkward unreconciled passions that have been laid down in the geological strata of social history and then faulted and folded into the arbitrary and anachronistic juxtapositions of contemporary experience. It is a symptom of the unconscious of our nature culture. And this supplies the opportunity for the culture of nature to reflect upon both nature and its own nature. We boast that even children are sophisticated readers of our popular culture, but show me the child wise to the culture of nature. That skywalk is a kind of folly and fantasy object. If only it were more articulate and expressed as a beautiful joke played by nature, including our own nature, on ourselves. If only we were as much connoisseurs of nature as of art—let alone of sport. 264

Fourth, we can no longer quite distinguish art from nature in the way Kant didnot when we are working on restoring and managing and protecting nature. Since we are busy making nature in accordance with a certain image, we need to talk about a poetics of nature, a matter not just of contemplation but also of design and works. ~ Yesterday I searched all afternoon for two lines of poetry, vaguely remembered. Nature is fond, I sometimes think Of Trinkets, as a Girl To find that particular sentence amongst all the little poems in Emily Dickinson’s collection (this was poem number 833) was like finding a particular leafthat half eaten one with the waving row of sawfly larvaeon a big tree. The pleasure of such a search lies in the distractions along the way. They are like the little grey fantail that lands, looks, talks and flies on; the brown thornbill on its little bird-legs tugging a tuft of hair on your arm; the striated thornbills in a bevy at the birdbath—little as bees Judith Wright called them, the scrub wrens gleaning insects from the leaves, exemplars of the happiness of preoccupation; the hapless blossom spider brought home on a picked flower; the tiddler skink on the sill; the cricket tinkling somewhere in the summer night; the mosquito orchid; the toadstool growing from the basal bark, the fig seedling in a fork; the insect lost in the vast world and its own precious business; the nanotechnology of the ant; the one midge in the constellation before my eyes; the tick in your eyelid; the butterfly blown out beyond the surf; the little tern slicing into a big wind and dodging breaking swells. Even imperial poetsVirgil, Oviddeclared it permissible to compare small things to great. The day before yesterday I was walking through a big rainforest with some students. We were all looking up, marvelling at the size of the trees. When we looked down it was to admire the base of a yellow carabeen 4m across with its flying buttresses. One student put his hand on a buttress, like a dancer putting his hand on a partner’s waist, taking the size and balance of the tree. In this big rainforest I am reassured by a dense brake of shield ferns, knee high, a profligacy of seedlings, and a scattering of flame tree flowers or rosewood seeds. In a damaged remnant or a replanted forest I would not see this. Happily, a little further on, in a tallowwood and blackbutt forest growing on a different soil, there was a sward of little seeding grassesbasket grasses and dwarf panic; little flowersblue lobelia, violets white and blue, mauve pastel flowers, white pratias; tufts of lomandra with orange scented flowers and lemon scented barbwire grass; orange one-petal flowers; fruiting banana bush, its regular form like a perfect miniature of a tree. In other places there are 265

brakes of rasp and gristle ferns. Under forest casuarinas there is a fine thatch of shed branchlets. All these small beauties I take as signs of well-being; they seem like intimations of cosmological order. Ecological managers search for focal species and indicators that signify healthy ecosystem function. They might prefer to drop the health metaphor and say something like assess ecosystem condition. A range of ants, for example, or frogs, fish, or mites, are said to be useful as indicators of ecosystem condition, and research is done demonstrating a correlation between, say, ant populations and vegetation condition. So far so good. Yet then, with a displacement of desire as ruthless as any fetish, ants are promoted as useful—that is as a useful indicator of the condition of vegetationeven though, to anyone but a skilled entomologist, the general vegetation condition is easier to assess than that of the ant populations. The wonderful ants are demoted to functionaries, to indicators rather than the thing indicated, when in practice they are not such useful indicators anyway—other than of themselves if you can find them. Yet at last they sound useful. Something similar happens when people commend the value of biodiversity. Biodiversity is a bean counter’s word for natural beauty. It pairs down nature’s excess of beauty and design to something with quasiscientific, bureaucratic respectability. It sounds useful for something else and gets beauty past the superegos of ecotechnocrats, environmentalists and scientists without them feeling guilty, and past the state and federal ministers as well. Ah, the charming neurosis of envirocratic management: It diverts its desire to respectable parts, revealing its passion only by a certain furtiveness that is almost touching. It busies itself with the trouble of appearing to make things work by parts, rather than finding the parts there already blissfully making themselves, delighting and surprising us. Kant, like many others, felt bound to preserve something of the irrationalist mystique of beauty (§39). Despite the prejudice that the rational takes precedence over whatever might claim to exceed rational conception, even the so-called West has, in its central tradition, asserted otherwise. At the very least it has drawn endless inspiration from the antagonism of reason and the intuition of unreason, savouring them as irreconcilable. Diagnoses that the West is pathologically hyper-rational are in fact internal to the Western tradition and merely of one party. The bourgeois himself, that parodic figure of the West whose antipodean heirs live on in both the aspirational suburbs and café society, liked to have his art irrational and life rational—or so Theodor Adorno said somewhere. Just saying that beauty exceeds rational conception implies the limitations of concepts and the importance of some supplementary aesthetic intuition—and vice versa. Kant held that we do not need a conceptual understanding of something to grasp its beauty, but I would say that concepts instruct us in our aesthetic intuitions and that such conceptual understanding as we have raises the bar that beauty exceeds. Hence our wonder and admiration of it. One need only walk in the bush with someone who knows it and someone who doesn’t to realize that the former sees while the latter is blind. Perception is not just some sensory window through which we all get bathed in the same 266

sunlight of unprocessed information. Information is not out there; it is what is perceived—a phrase that translates the Greek αι’σθητικός or aesthetic. Understanding is a condition of perception too, and of the quality of intuition. Without understanding and experience people simply would not see all those species of ants; the bush would be just a pastiche of greens. Even landscape art makes a virtue of its constitutional blindness to the beauty of nature: painters blur their eyes and look for form and colour; art photographers don’t want to be confused with wildlife photographers or botanical illustrators. As Schönberg said, painters paint pictures, not things. Their works, as essays on seeing seeing, presume they may or must suspend understanding of the things they paint or photograph. Most of the understanding they show is understanding of the landscape tradition. Meanwhile, faintly praising those ants for their role as indicators is just a hamfisted way of acknowledging the beauty of them and of the vegetation, a beauty that exceeds even the entomologist’s concepts, including now, this new conception of how certain species tell us specific things about the bush they live in. The effortless abundance and intricacy of its beauty demonstrates the genius of bush and the vanity of our contrivances. Recently after visiting some gardens in the Blue Mountains I found myself having tea at a café in a national park. I had seen one quite beautiful garden with rhododendrons, azaleas, peony roses, clematis, bay laurels, maples, the works; and another that, more by necessity than virtue, juxtaposed rhododendrons with the bush they’d been plonked into. The former was all labour, artifice, passion and magnificent tizz, a traditional Blue Mountains garden, a beautiful Eurasian-Himalayan fantasia 1000m above sea-level and a world away from Australia. The latter carved and inculcated itself into the bush as gracelessly as a highwayor a suburb. It was an emblem of the way Australia has half plonked itself onto this continent. It is repeated everywhere as towns and suburbs eat, dribble and plonk their way into the bush, evenor perhaps especiallywhere natives are planted. I have never seen a garden though that came close to the perfection of the bush. Never. Planted forests are the same. Gardens of Australian natives are too. Or they’re worse. Beautiful gardens are too simple or too cluttered, arch or contrived, gaudy or drab, too neat or, fraying. Always, they demand that we look away from little flaws, from their wearying mutability, or that we blur our eyes. Time eats away at them, dissolving the intentions of makers and caretakers who can never quite anticipate just how it will fall from grace and never quite keep up with the maintenance. A lawn thins under growing trees, broad-leaved weeds creep over the shaded ground, and a planted forest is bare underneath. A pruned shrub or a trained vine needs to grow back a bit. At the same time though it portends tomorrow’s cares. Of course garden lovers make a virtue of this: the beauty of a garden is always a passing beauty, the passing beauty of repose and admiration after labour, or of things decorously decaying before they fall into abject neglect. True garden lovers love the narrative and sweat of their labour and the contemplation of its being succeeded by nature’s labour. Yet this beauty is in the bush too, and the fruits of labour in the 267

bushof nature’s and of oursstill always outdo the contrivances of the garden. Always. The bush as bush never has flaws. It only develops them when it shows the traces of the imposition of garden culturein weeds or strange plantings or jerry buildings or roads or litter. Free of such imposition, and utterly confident of its gifts, the bush showsshows offmortality and uncertainty and the passing of time in its narrative spectacle as natural beauty. Sure there is an ideology here, one that can be merely prisoner to impoverished ideas of naturalness and natural order or the tyranny of natives only. But what is in this sentiment that is worthy of good aesthetic judgement? What I love about Kant’s concept of natural beauty is that o-so-Kantian line, about the form of natural objects appearing ‘as it were, preadapted to our judgement (§23)’. Kant has a reputation for writing dry, difficult, unreadable philosophy, philosophy that has been ground out with immense effort to obtain a rarefied systemic consistency. If anyone could, Kant could contrive an argument. For people who have a little knowledge of philosophy he probably epitomizes a parodic view of philosophy as something abstruse, ponderous, German, irrelevant, futile, quibbling and outdated. But really he is full of fascinating, and sometimes unreconciled ideas. Despite the importance he placed on consistency, his writing contains many acknowledged shortcomings, many concessions of impasse, many claims proposed as as it weres. These often contain the germs of thoughts that later science and philosophy have revealed as creative or prescient. The best philosophy can be most wonderful in its shortcomings. In that as it were Kant acknowledges the metaphorical character of his idea of preadaptation, and the inexplicability (for him) of such a preadaptation were the term to be taken literally. To describe Kant as dry, difficult and unreadable reminds me of a description of the kind of bush that people don’t spend enough time in. By finality in the form of natural objects—the finality that made the objects appear to be pre-adapted to our aesthetic judgement—Kant meant something like teleological design. Ever since Aristotle, western science had distinguished between the causality of cause and effect (so-called effective cause) and that of goal oriented or teleological processes whose intended or shaping end is described as the final cause of the process. When post-Newtonian, 18th century science was preoccupied by the prospect of powerful mechanistic cause-andeffect descriptions of nature, and many teleological descriptions were looking like the quaint ruins of Aristotelianism, Kantno mean scientist himselfpersisted in asserting their significance. Kant, however, was not concerned with teleology in the theological sense, that is, in the sense of the world being designed by a god for some final theological end. As in his moral writings, he philosophizes like a child of the Enlightenment, without need of a god. Nor however was he satisfied simply with teleology in the sense in which it persisted for Enlightenment thought—the sense of either nature as a whole or of organisms themselves being organized according to particular conceivable ends. Suspicious of any notion that accounted for aesthetic Judgement as mere functionary of other purposes, and concerned with how subjective judgements 268

of taste could also be universal, he insisted that the aesthetic experience of nature could not be explained by our less than universal conception and appreciation of nature’s design for particular purposes. Self-subsisting natural beauty reveals to us a technic of nature which shows it in the light of a system ordered in accordance with laws the principle of which is not to be found within the range of our entire faculty of understanding. Against the common sense of Enlightenment thought, Kant held on to a Romantic impulse, and assumed the shortcoming of scientific description. As some 20th century critics of science might have said, it seemed too reductionist. For Kant, aesthetic judgement was a kind of necessary supplement to scientific understanding. As such, beauty is a non-conceptual intimation of truth—a point suspected, often rightly, of naïvety, of intellectual defeatism or of resorting to the irrational and mystification. It has a strong appeal in aesthetics though, whether of art or nature. Kant felt bound to assert the legitimacy of his theory of aesthetic Judgement, not for the sake of justifying irrationalism but because he could not reconcile two assumptions: first, that the actual existence of beauties of nature is patent to experience; and second, that nature’s objective design can hardly be expected to explain why natural objects should exhibit the natural beauty of their forms to us (§39). Defying teleology as Kant and the Enlightenment conceived it, this exhibition of preadaptation had to remain an as it were and beyond understanding. The evidence of beauty disconfirmed the theory of teleology, which had to await the account of its own natural history. What more can one say then other than I don’t know much about nature but I know what I like. Frederick Turner, tried to go a little further by saying that ‘the sense of beauty tells us what is relevant, what is likely, what is proper, what is fruitful' (49). Yet saying that aesthetic judgement of nature is our seatof-the-pants way of knowing what is good and natural is not going all that much further. Again it is a version of the old idea: that the experience of natural beauty is a non-scientific intuition of nature’s purpose. Just for whom or what it is purposeful? Us? Nature itself? That’s another question and one that is often dodged on the assumption of the supposed licensed vagaries of aesthetic contexts. While these ideas could persist as placeholders in explanations in the aesthetics of nature and for uses other than explanation—like the critique of science—whatever explanatory power they might have had became superannuated. The theory of nature’s aesthetics demanded explanations of the ideas it had been using as explanations. Why did the idea of beauty as an intuition of what is good or designed or purposeful about nature keep cropping up? Is there really such a thing as this intuition? If so, why is there such a thing? And when it comes to the aesthetics of nature, is that all there is to it? The idea of forms as it were, preadapted to our judgement refused to sacrifice an insight that was later vindicatedin this caseby post-Darwinian science. Natural selection is a machine for generating teleology nonteleologically. And it is always, as it were, discovering preadaptations; it is like 269

art, always revealing functions and meanings that its sources never dreamed of. Like the peculiarities in Kant’s theory of knowledge, those in his theory of aesthetics turn out to be consistent with evolutionary accounts of human psychology. In Kant’s metaphor there lies an explanation of natural beauty as something apprehended in things not designed for us, unconcerned with us. In it there also lies an intimation of our own evolved biological design for appreciating design notwithstanding any inability to grasp its purpose. There is even an invitation to apprehend nature not as the embodiment of an abstract ideal of beauty, but to read it in all its variety of design. We are signifying, designing and communicating animals to whom nature cannot help but be like something or someone saying something to us, and for whom such design had better be an object that promises to reward our attention. Aesthetics is in the signifying detail and the happiness of aesthetics lies the felicity of that promise. In turn, if we learn anything from studying design and its evolution in natural history it is that such ideals as perfection, symmetry, harmony or unity, are being ceaselessly superseded, precisely because nature’s design is historically evolved and it must always work with the means at hand. This is one reason why we need a culture of judgement and critique of nature that is more than travel journalism, science journalism, nature documentaries or information pamphlets, which is about all we get. Nature, like art, is prosaic as well as poetic; it is dissonant, makeshift, contrived, asymmetrical, cunning and perverse. Above all its beauty is historical not eternal. There is a natural history of beauty. Yet, among the least satisfying results of thinking about the aesthetics of nature have been those attempts to describe aesthetic experience using statistical surveys of personal preferences and to explain natural beauty by invoking evolutionary psychology. The idea is that humans have evolved to appreciate those landscapes that, in the Pleistocene, appeared safe, and productiveplaces that provided shelter, a vantage point, food and water for evolving populations of the genus Homo (Orians & Heerwagen). Research is typically done using photographs to survey landscape preferences (Williams & Carey). And it appears that we humans have a preference for a picturesque landscape with trees to protect us and a prospect of savannah-like grassland before us—just like the ones we are supposed to have evolved in. I admit, my putting it this way makes it sound a bit too much like apes emerging from the jungle out onto some Pleistocene grassland—or like Capability Brown. The trouble with most natural historical explanation is that it is neither natural enough nor historical enough. It ignores the natural history of culture and simplifies aesthetic responses according to some very time-bound notionslandscape preference for one, landscape photographs for another. At its best, this kind of research acknowledges the problems, allows that they are outside the present brief, and makes do with scare quotes around words like ‘unnatural’. Evolutionary explanations are only as good as the description of the present state of things—in this case the state of human minds and society. These are, 270

after all, the most accessible empirical data, yet they are also very difficult to observe without interfering with what is being observed and therefore they are difficult to describe objectively. An explanation has to avoid projecting unreflected, cultural data into the description; otherwise, in the conclusion of its argument, it will draw it back out like a rabbit out of a rigged hat. Landscape preferences are as bound to the history of aesthetics as are gum tree pictures, the fashion for rainforest, the sublime thrill at waterfalls, the love of a fresh fall of powder snow, or, for that matter, Hollywood blockbusters, Barbie Dolls, or the lines of the latest car. In fact, showing subjects landscape photos has very little to do with the aesthetic experience of nature. There may well be some persistent preferences but the way they are labelled and opinion polled can say more about the aesthetic limitations of the researchers than about the nature of aesthetics. Primarily, they say something about the aesthetics of photography. If we surveyed food preferences or story preferences, we might suppose that our culinary aesthetic is conditioned by a Pleistocene partiality for frozen pizza and sliced white bread, and our narrative aesthetic by a Pleistocene predilection for action flicks or reality TV, but we would only be doing so because we had not bothered to adequately observe contemporary aesthetic culture—something that seems quite difficult for habitually non-reflexive, empirical researchers. If the description of their present is so questionable, then what of the description of those empirically remote Pleistocene places? I think evolutionary theory, whether in the natural selection of human psychology or in the social selection of culture, can do better than this. We can explain beauty or other aesthetic experience or practice and say why humans like this or that and why we are aesthetic or poetic animals, but such an explanation demands a good description of aesthetic culture and a good account of how it got to be that way. Then, for all that, the explanation will be merely an historical one, the empirical historical details and the evolutionary mechanisms will be subject to doubt, and then, because of the nature of taste, the description of the aesthetic culture it explains will almost certainly be disputed by almost anyone capable of reflections on aesthetic culture, whether brilliant or dull, because one thing that is universal in aesthetic culture is the matter of differences of taste. To attempt a brief and corrective description of the present state of aesthetics anyway, I would say that the subject matter of aesthetic experience has always been socially selected according to whether it is adapted to naturally selected human emotional and cognitive capacity and predilection, including among other things the capacity to interpret what we moderns call landscape as well as innumerable other details of nature, to appreciate design regardless or otherwise of its purpose, and to intuit, up to a point, what might be good for us or relevant to us. More than that, I would say that nature’s aesthetic, like art’s, has long objectified emotion and feeling, and given us feelings about feeling. This recursion enlightens us about our feeling, especially our feelings for social relations and for our relation to nature. We might still be saddled with the burden of the brain and body of a hunter-gatherer adapted to Pleistocene 271

circumstances, but we use the equipment at hand to muddle along. Kant’s insistence on the universality of the judgement of taste, his insistence in the face of differing judgements that it is not an objective but a subjective universality—i.e. that it is universal to human subjects—is a claim that we are all more or the less the same aesthetic creatures. I would only add that this is because human subjects are astonishing natural historical objects and that this is how natural history made us. However there is also the social history of aesthetics too. Aesthetic sensibility is not only some naturally selected system of intuition. What we deem to be aesthetic is an autonomous sphere of society, and that system of intuition is its primary mental environment. Humans are such social animals that it is very difficult to separate their supposedly pristine, unsocialized yet naturally social psychology from the culture that insinuates itself into individual development. Any successful separation must confront or circumvent the problem of there being at least three confounded historical processes: natural selection, social evolution and individual development. Naïve historical unravelling, and confusion of ontogeny and phylogeny are traps waiting for the unwary. More importantly, the autonomous social evolution of aesthetic forms extends aesthetic experience beyond whatever any historical unravelling might derive as the pristine, primary psychological environment of proto-aesthetic experience. The most immediately gratifying emotional response to nature (or art) is, in aesthetic culture, neither the most enlightened nor the most gratifying. By this, I do not only mean that aesthetic experience develops in its sophistication throughout the course of a life. It has its social development as well. Aesthetic experience and aesthetic culture have been about greater understanding, and greater happiness. And—since admiration rather than pleasure is the most important aesthetic response—it has been about creating aesthetic objects worthy of the greatest admiration. As the last specification implies, aesthetic culture has certainly not proceeded by the inhibited, puritanical means of the first or most immediate gratification. A survey of the landscape preferences of a sample population says as much about human aesthetic nature as a survey of scientific or artistic skills of a sample population says about scientific or artistic culture. Average punters are not humans in a state of natureor at least not in some authentic pristine state of Pleistocene nature. Such a survey of landscape preferences reveals more about historically specific popular landscape culture than it does about the natural selection of aesthetic sensibility. Of course, contemporary popular landscape culturewhich is itself socially adapted to (among other things) human emotional biologymay be used to make certain hypotheses about human emotional biology, but human emotional biology is a rich vein for research, and time-bound, popular landscape preferences amount to a pretty small part of the available data. No aesthetics of nature can ignore the historical transformations of aesthetic society. Sure, the critique of progress is irresistible. Although the harshest critics of the ideology of progress often betray, by their political actions, some 272

belief in the fact that things could be better, almost all draw the line at aesthetic progress, especially when it comes to nature. Since it is supposed to be the same as everor at least it would be if we were not relentlessly diminishing itthe aesthetics of nature is assumed not to participate in progress. Its sensibility is epitomized by a melancholia for a secular paradise lost. Yet apprehension of the diminution of nature must itself be recognised as one of the most powerful pressures driving the evolution of the modern aesthetics of nature. And in accordance with the self-imagination of modernity, and therefore in its dedication to innovation, aesthetic culture has emulated scientific society. As Anthony Giddens has said, this innovative bent follows from modernity’s being so characterised by self-descriptionand self-prescription. Aesthetic innovation, in art or nature, might not necessarily be progress, but it emulates science in its being made under the sign of progress. Even though that progress is not continuous or consistent or even if it is not a fact, it is a norm that keeps on seeing its self-realisation in the relentless change of aesthetic culture and sensibility. One of the most familiar forms of aesthetic progress is acquired taste. Its great drivers are social and individual self-construction by means of selfdifferentiation from the past. Both of these were at work in sublime contemplation. Formerly ugly or frightening objects became objects of beauty. Initially it may just have been, as Kant said or as ancient cave painters may have noticed, a matter of feeling our power to frame and thereby transcend these things. In turn, such is human desire that the beautiful power of transcendence was transferred onto the transcended object. It was transfigured into an object of beauty and that experience was communicated in beautiful images. Although the sublime belonged to nature’s aestheticsespecially in Kantthis process is now utterly familiar in the history of art, in things such as dissonance, atonal melody, graphic abstraction and narrative innovation. In each of these the negation of, respectively, harmony, tonality, figuration and generic narrative is transfigured as more harmonic, more melodic, more figurative, and more narrative. The same has happened in the aesthetics of both art and nature. This process is practically pop culture now. In his essay ‘What is Enlightenment’, Kant could see that it was not just a personal thing but a social thing; and not just the developed maturity of society as modelled on individual development but the developed maturity of each (individual and society) depending upon and being reflected in the other. Kant thought that the love of nature was a sign of Enlightenment, and an ethical thingpart of living the good life. We moderns often use the phrase the good life to refer to a hedonistic one. It comes from Aristotle’s Ethics, where how to live the good life was formulated as the most important problem of philosophy. I was sitting with a friend on a deck in a café overlooking mangrove swamp on Coffs Creek. We usually take our binoculars and bird book when we go there, drink coffee, eat cake and spot plumed egrets or sacred kingfishers. Mullet mill in the water waiting for crumbs, wily silver bream flash their flanks beneath them. Pelicans rest on the flats like planes on a tarmac, silver gulls face north 273

east into the breeze and wait, White-faced Herons imitate the inclination of the sea rushes, a striated heron lurks in grey mangroves, crested terns fly by and check things out, pied cormorants swim and fish like aquatic dinosaurs and dry their wings between stints. I once wrote a submission to Coffs City Council objecting to the construction of this particular bit of commercial architecture in this particular place. Usually the waiters, like the birds, pretty much ignore our bird-watching paraphernalia. This day the place was crowded. We did not have a waterside table. We did not have the binoculars on the table. We had to watch the clientele. Suddenly two women at another table started laughing. The third woman at the table was looking down to her side at the edge of the deck, a bit disconcerted. A water dragon was looking back up at her. Another dragon started gleaning crumbs from beneath a newly vacated table behind her. Eastern water dragons grow to nearly a meter and they are more archly reptilian than say, skinks. As their name suggests, they can put on a bit of frightening display, arching their heads up and flaring their necks out as if about to breathe fire or rip flesh. It’s all floorshow. They also like what humans eat, and although shy in the wild (you notice them mostly by the splash they make when they drop from the bank into the water at your approach) they get very used to people and can become as familiar as dogs. The waiters knew this pair. They were like somewhere between regulars and staff. Buskers maybe. The three women were not quite comfortable with reptiles, but they knew what Enlightenment was or what it used to be in Kant’s day. We all did in this popular, café society sort of way—including me who had written that submission. They sipped their coffees, and talked and smiled. The smiles of the one in the dragon seat were a little edgy, but she probably liked the fact that there was wilderness out there somewhere, and you could see that, like Kant, she would have liked a little bird singing at her window. ~ It is a commonplace that the beauty of art can appeal to those lacking in moral sentiment. We all know those tales about death camp commandants listening to Mozart. Not the beauty of nature though, according to Kant (§42). Since the beauty of nature has no end in and for itself, its beauty for us may be sensed only as a hint to us of our properly ethical destiny. Therefore it is only to someone already given to moral feeling that such beauty could be apparent. Kant argued that reason itself, abstracted from all human self-interest, could derive the moral imperative of doing to others only what you would have them do to you. It is not just a principle given by a god or religion or culture, it is a categorical imperative, Kant claimed, universally true for any reasoning being. Thus nature, innocent of humans and their failings—and, like Kant’s austere moral reason, uninfluenced by mere human purposes—is able to intimate to us our moral destiny and its imperatives in a way that art, tarnished with human purposes and failings, can’t. In the beauty of nature we see the image of moral good. In this one stroke Kant contrived to solve the problem of nature’s sensed 274

lack of human spirit and to assign nature aesthetic pre-eminence of over art. It looks like a contrived argument, as Kant himself admits. He concedes that his ‘interpretation of aesthetic judgements on the basis of kinship with our moral feeling has far too studied an appearance to be accepted as the true construction of the cypher in which nature speaks to us figuratively in its beautiful forms' (§42). Nature is so accursedly natural, particularly when it is presumed to be just naturally appealing to our better natures. Its sometimes-terrible beauty is hardly a clear hint of our own moral good. It’s more like our moral ambiguity. Many have differed from Kant, claiming that natural beauty is subordinate to artistic beauty. They take their parts in a contest of sensibility—sometimes conscious, sometimes unconscious—that has run through both popular and intellectual modernity. Art and nature each had poets to advertise them long before anyone was writing jingles for the Romantic nature that has so enchanted modernity. Philip Sidney’s Elizabethan Defence of Poesy is as good a statement of art’s superiority as any: Nature never set forth the earth in so rich Tapistry as diverse poets have done, neither with so pleasaunt rivers, fruitfull trees, sweete smelling flowers, nor whatsoever els, may make the too much loved earth more lovely: her world is brazen, the Poets only deliver a golden. It also is worth quoting Hegel, to epitomise philosophy’s response to Kant and to look into the rationale of this kind of thinkinga rationale that so often seems to imply that the love of natural beauty is not quite as sophisticated as that of art. It is just a little bit too natural or a bit too unhuman or a bit too easy. Writing about the immediately apprehended beauty of life in nature he said: Yet, because of this purely sensuous immediacy, the living beauty of nature is produced neither for nor out of itself as beautiful, nor for the sake of a beautiful appearance. The beauty of nature is beautiful only for another, i.e. for us, for the mind, which apprehends beauty. (123) For Hegel it was the calling of human spirit to surpass, in the beauty of its artworks, nature’s merely fortuitous kind of beauty. Mere nature cannot make the already too much loved earth any more lovely. Nature, lacking the freedom to surpass itself, is therefore restricted in its power to excite the greatest admiration. Only something made can excite such admiration—something invested with its portion of spirit—because what we admire in the work is free consciousness displaying its power as a maker, its power to at once negate, yet preserve and supersede nature. Or so Hegel thought. If admiration is more crucial or critical to aesthetic response than pleasure, then I admire the best artworks for the astonishing aesthetic nous that they display. That is the source of their pleasure. They display their art. I cannot do this with completely extrahuman nature. Instead I admire design that is the seemingly miraculous 275

consequence of no aesthetic nous at all, and the nous in this case, as Hegel says, is all in the beholder. Yet while we admire artworks for their having been made, they impress us by their seeming to have freed themselves from their origins in individual human intentions. What we admire in their making is that they manage to make themselves look like nature, exceeding human design. As many have said, works of art behave, and would have us take them, as natural objects. Their art consists in concealing their art. If they are beautiful they seem to communicate to us perfectly in our feeling of their beauty. It as if their inspiration is already in us as much as in the artist, and as if we share it because it is in nature itself. ‘Both the artists and their audience,’ said Niklas Luhmann (1995, 78) ‘participate in communication only as observers.’ On the other side, natural objects, because of their apparent, sophisticated design—a design that in the case of living things epitomises inimitability and unmakeability—seem to be quite intended. Art displays nature and conceals art. Nature conceals nature and reveals art. All aesthetic objects participate in this dialectic of admirability. Hegel rationalises a personal preference, explaining it and justifying it by citing the objective subordination of nature to art. While comparison is always implicit in aesthetic judgement, while aesthetic objects vie for our affections, to the exclusion—momentarily at least—of all others and we assert our preferences with utter wilfulness, and while whole classes of aesthetic objects— the natural vs the artistic—may vie for pre-eminence, comparison is always modelled on some kind of abstraction as violent as that of pricing, an abstraction that is always ready to sacrifice something about the particular object. What’s objective is not the subordination of one of nature or art to the other, but the invitation to comparison. Objectively, each emulates the other, inviting comparison against the other. Comparison is odious if it asserts objective subordination simply as a post hoc rationalisation of personal preference. To generate an objective aesthetic theory from individual experience without sacrificing the one to the other—that is the predicament of aesthetics. If it is not impossible, then it must surely demand a kind of tact. Precisely because comparison is immanent in the objects of aesthetic experience, comparative judgement of art and nature should be treated with a certain lightness. Watching a sunset, the art critic Dave Hickey (52) turns the tables against complacent advocates of natural beauty. Compared to the lights of the Las Vegas Strip, the sunset that smoulders out above the mountains beyond ‘looks bogus as hell’ to Hickey. Metropolitans have been playing this gambit since Socrates, implying that simple unintended natural beauty lacks the sophistication of art. It says as much about the aesthetics of suburban wit as it does about nature, but its persistence in modern sensibility from Baudelaire to Nietzsche to postmodern chic suggests it is not a critique to be dismissed lightly. Rather, it is something, to be taken on lightly. Like nature, we all have something to learn from Las Vegas. Apart from nature’s naturalness, nothing afflicts it as much as its ponderous authenticity. Only a dead hand would bestow the praises of naturalness or authenticity on anything anymore. Those 276

nature-loving friends of Hickey’s who prefer the sunset to The Strip ‘are responding to nature’s ability to mimic the sincerity of a painting.’ ‘One either prefers the honest fakery of the neon,’ he says, ‘or the fake honesty of the sunsetthe undisguised artifice of culture or the cultural construction of “authenticity”.’ Just as there is nothing so lacking in spirit as spirituality, there is nothing so inauthentic as authenticity, or so unnatural as naturalness. We can of course, if we like, turn Hickey’s tables again though, and point out that nature’s ability to mimic painting is honest fakery too. It has just been doing it longer. I like what Edward Abee says at the start of Desert Solitaire, his book on the Utah desert: ‘This must be the most beautiful place on earth. There are many such places.’ And he proceeds to list his beautiful places, natural and metropolitan. I would say that Kant's moralism, Hegel’s deliberation and Hickey’s wit mistake both natural and artistic beauty. I suspect that each kind of beauty is apprehended in objects just insofar as those objects seem unintended for or unconcerned about our particular regard for them, and that beauty in art is a kind of reply to the beauty of natureone that seeks to be worthy of complementing nature’s priority, primarily by not merely being its slavish imitator. And, indeed, nature seems to reply to art in almost the same way. Art and nature may imitate one another as much or as little they like, but the end is emulation. Art emulates nature. It seems to do so because, as Shakespeare said, art itself is nature. Especially now when nature is a bit of an art. Nature, nowadays, need no longer be thought of as something lacking the capacity to make an admirable display simply because it is merely a thing perceived and not something made by and for consciousness. Perhaps this is only starting to dawn on us because we can no longer, like those philosophers fresh out of the eighteenth century, deny our part in so many of the works of nature. This is the case whether nature is restored, managed or even conserved as absolutely extrahuman nature. In natural objects consciousness now apprehends the image of its own power to excite admiration by its works. It apprehends this precisely in those objects having been spared the violence of human domination, and in their having been no more than touched—whether in labour or in contemplation—lightly, as if by sympathetic consciousness alone. It need not have been forever so. Aesthetic experience and its objects are always part of history and always evolving. Even so, the aesthetic apprehension of meanings and images in clouds and mountains and stars was long ago an intimation that freedom and human mind—both also children of their times, and I might add, of nature—might one day find the most remote, inhuman objects showing themselves to us like artworks. Hegel, the philosopher of spirit and reflective consciousness was, like Kant, not quite ready to recognize spirit’s recognition of its image and labour in natural things, because Hegel, the philosopher of history, was, like all of us, of his times, and his understanding of aesthetics is no longer quite historical enough for the natural beauty of these times

277

~ The sublime and beautiful, barely developed beyond their 18th century forms, still linger in the popular aesthetics of nature, limiting experience in the process. They limit the image of nature and nature itself, which is seen and made in that image. Nature is more than an appearance framed by tradition for our delectation, more than just something to look at, an object of contemplation, a tourist attraction, more than just sublime or beautiful. Because of the habits of philosophical abstraction, beauty and the sublime were modeled on a limited conception of the aesthetic object. Even in art—in its commonly narrow sense of visual art—there is more to art than just something to look at. Perhaps, instead of to Kant, I should have returned to the first great aesthetic work in western philosophy: Aristotle’s Poetics. This work was not simply an aesthetics but a poetics of narrative. Nature is historical, it’s full of stories, its image is a narrative. It moves, it changes, it happens, it travels, it grows, it lives, it dies. It acts, it makes. It tells as well as shows. We work on it too, changing it, doing it, as part of it, and sometimes making a virtue of it. As narrative art is to history, a poetics of nature is to natural history. Of course, as is so often the case with aesthetic claims, this might only be a prediction, not a fact. Or it might be no more than a manifesto.

278

15 Works of Nature A proposal for an art and a poetics of ecological management

… this is an art Which does mend nature, change it rather, but The art itself is nature. —William Shakespeare, The Winter’s Tale (IV, iii, 94-96)

One way or another, humans now make what they like to think of as wild nature, but not like gods creating beings out of dust, and nowhere near so deftly and miraculously as to put life and limb back into a crushed ant, nor anything like a universe fraught with immense time slowly building life and consciousness up out of endless tinkering on the smithereens of stars. Even the utterly artificial golf green takes the inscrutable natural wonder of grass as a given. Humans still make nature now in much the same sort of way that they used to construct the nature of European pastoral culture or the nature of the traditional Aboriginal country, and they make it from the uncanny materials already given to them by natural history. Making nature is a mark of modern societyconscious or unconsciousinherited from the past for sure, but with its own modern features Nature could once unambiguously refer to what was beyond human artifice, but when humans bring anything under their powerif only under their power to destroy itit becomes a different kind of thing. Now all of the earth’s living nature falls under this fate. Now the most remote wild places and the things that live there are beholden to human freedom or to its social complement, the arbitrary unfreedom of wild social forces. Even a National Park up in the wild ranges of the Great Divide, days walk from anywhere, is mapped and managed by and for the modern culture of nature. The never seen fur fly biting the never seen wallaby browsing in the shadows of some never seen thicket is managed precisely as such. Closer at hand, every bit of wild nature bears some trace of human labour, deliberate or inadvertent: the road that divides it, the birds that fly seed in from the fragmented and weedy farmscape, the fact that it is in a

279

place socially designated and managed for its function as nature, the fact that it is this bit and not that bit that used to be over there where the farm or the town is now, the fact that it is just a leftover deemed to be nature by the wild selections of modern functional colonization. In its most active and deliberate sense this labour on nature restores it from damaged remainsusually by forms of designed disturbance such as weed removal, burning or floodingor reconstructs it from the ground up using the techniques inherited from civil engineering, agriculture, silviculture and horticulture. Call it a postmodern, postcolonial genre of landscape architecture; or call it ecological restoration and management. It may not be like this everywhere in the world but that is what it’s like here, now, in catchments east of The Great Dividing Range, like the Bellinger valley. From the remote wilderness in which wildfires must be left to burn themselves out, to the municipal micro-wilderness busily bush-regenerated behind bollards, what we think of as nature, what the children of technocratic society call the natural environment, is all part of the modern society’s culturescape. Sure, there is such a thing as wild nature, but not in an absolutely extrahuman sense. Therefore we have to make it up according to its image. What we identify as nature preserved or restored is now a kind of image or index of what we wish it to be. By image I mean that it is a likeness of what we wish it to be, an image, say, of the pristine. By index I mean that it is physically connected to it: we make wild nature out of the biological and geophysical materials inherited from the past, the same animal and plant species that lived in the pristine bush, the same rivers (inasmuch as a river can be the same twice) that flowed through it. Like its ancestors in traditional Aboriginal or pastoral nature, modern nature has its system of practices and norms, and, since we so confuse norms and facts, its appearance is easily delusive. Such is the ambiguous power of images. Such is the virtuality of reality. Insofar as we believe in untouched natureeven though we must now cradle this great powerful thing in our hands like a trembling birdthese standards are little self-deceptions that we transform from mistakes into norms and norms into facts. Should we worry about such a thing as belief in wild nature? What is mere belief worth anyway? Nature is quite wild and beautiful enough not to care what we believe. Belief is little better than a cherished delusioninto which it is prone to degenerate as one-time truths are turned over by time. Crisis of belief is just the growing pain of enlightenment. Science dissolved the burden of belief into ontological relativism: It is merely a matter of the ontological commitment required by an adequate theory. And fiction, to correct Coleridge, is willing suspension of belief. Science and fiction gave up on belief long ago. So should nature culture. However, there is nothing mere about appearance. All great art and philosophy demonstrates this. Art makes a virtue of the ambiguity of norms and facts, image and object, the virtual and the real, even art and life, enlightening us with sheer appearance. And so does nature. Or (to introduce a norm to confuse a fact) so it should.

280

All this transforms the aesthetics of nature. Since we make up nature according to our image, what was once a concern of passive aesthetic contemplation is now a matter of poetic practice. An art. The experience of nature includes working on nature, and its appearance is one of something worked on. To refer to a poetics of nature is to refer to the making up of nature, and to the making good of this situation where we have to restore and manage it. The aesthetic experience of nature is not simply of what is beautiful (or whatever else contemplative aesthetics is concerned with). The question is: In what does the poetics of nature consist? And the answer is not simply supplied by ecological scienceany more than the sciences of psychology or sociology supply answers to artistic practice (e.g. in fiction) or ethical practice. Indeed disciplines with crude technocratic names like ecological restoration and ecological management must in some way redress the limitations imposed on ecological knowledge by its epistemic limitations as a sciencejust as narrative art, ethical actions and philosophy, redress the limitations of psychological and sociological sciences. Any attempt to redress such limitations imposes the most difficult of standards. A poetics cannot slacken its efforts and adopt a degenerate, mystificatory or lazy folk-scientific attitude to its subject matter. A poetics of nature that ignores ecology is not a poetics at all. It is a kind of kitsch. More than any other society, modernity tells itself to itself and constructs itself in its own self-image. Modern society has been an ever more frenetic orgy of self-explanation, and with that, self-delusion. And, in turn self-construction in the image of this explanation or delusion. It has also been a process of ceaseless self-differentiation from its immediate past self-imagesespecially from what it has come to recognize as delusory. For a time, modernity has wanted its nature to epitomize what is absolutely extra-human. No wonder, given the ugly havoc wreaked on nature by wild industrial society, and the admiration evoked by the beautiful unmakeability even of the worm. The norms of nature as extra-human, including such technocratic standards as those of wilderness, may be seen as an instance of self-construction by self-differentiationin this case differentiation from the destructive havoc of modern industry and agriculture and its exploitation of nature. This was the way modern society constructed its image of wild natureespecially where it ran over the traditional nature of indigenous societies, constructing wilderness as it went, ahead of its frontiers. It was constructing itself, but it conveniently managed to elude itself when it came to the observation of its culture of nature. It has not only been Aboriginal land that it pretended was terra nullius. At first it might seem strange that modernity, renowned since Hegel for its being history’s epitome of a self conscious society, should construct such an elaborate unconscious for itself. Yet really, it is just the effect one should expect from such an effort at self-construction. In this, society is like the psyche. In order to run itself in all its complexity a lot just works and has to work unattended. So now, given such a contradiction, it is

281

hardly surprising that the ground should have shifted again beneath society and its culture of nature. All this is the condition of the poignancy of enlightened modernity’s understanding of its relation to nature. In order to have its nature as it desired, it has had to end up deluding itself about the naturalness of this nature. In the society of the spectacleas Guy Debord labelled it many years ago nownature as natural is the most unnatural spectacle of all. Initially, as industrial society put individuals in a position to safely observe mighty and remote nature and so render it subject to sublime contemplation, this idea of extra-human nature could be maintained. But such sublime contemplation was itself an historically specific condition, a breathtaking moment, which unconsciously registered the passing of mighty and invincible extra-human terrestrial nature. It was the same industrial power that ushered in the sublime moment that in turn made once mighty extra-human nature somehow abject and beholden to the wild might of modern market society. It was the same moment, at modernity’s colonial frontiers, in which traditional nature was taken to be a terra nulliusthat most brutal Australian instance of the confusion of norm and fact. So much of the modern culture of nature—bushwalking and rafting, surfing, climbing, adventure ecotourism—is staged to preserve this sad, blissful moment. Modern society has had to sustain its image of wild extra-human nature by means of self descriptions of its relation to nature that have been rendered increasingly paradoxical by the passing of time. So now its continuing self-construction looks like being a matter of a new self-differentiation from its past. Aesthetic theoriesthemselves created on historically shifting ground and at the front between facts and normsare also manifestos. Their truth and their promise depend upon their historical context. With that caveat, I would say, a modern poetics of nature may disabuse itself or redeem modern society’s poignant self-delusion in a way that is both modern and historically specific, and yet in a way that is also quite familiar to art. Its most familiar form is expressed by Horace’s dictum: ars est celare artemthe art is to conceal art. This saying was always meant to be ambiguous, for art also consists in revealing its art. If its purpose is brilliant appearance then its brilliance as art must also be apparent. That is what excites admiration. The aesthetics of nature is an aesthetic of appearance demanding the same kind of revelation. The condition of a self-elusive society observing the increasingly paradoxical, selfelusive construction of nature is natural habitat for poetic practicespoetics having always been a sphere of action which makes a virtue out of knowing self-elusion. Still, the society of nature remains an unconscious societyunconscious that its most cherished object is social, unconscious that this poetic condition and aesthetic problems exist, unconscious that it is or need be anything but technocratic management. It is easy to disregard any such claim. Crawling through never-seen vines along a never-followed spur above the banks of the Never Never River, it sounds so scandalous, indeed ridiculous, to suggest that 282

even what is most natural is somehow artificial. And after all, since the 18th century and the likes of Rousseau and Kant, the artificial has been derided as a kind of fall from grace. But I have got to say, it is the predicament of action, of actually taking up tools and having to do something to restore a rainforest or conserve a eucalypt forest that drives home the fact of the social nature of nature and of its poetic predicament. I am not contriving postmodern theory here. This comes from experience. It is about doing things and working with nature, being up to my arms in it, wrestling with it. Faced with the choice of tools or means or co-workers or ends, it becomes a lie to assert that all the answers are given by an unambiguous science that simply reads them from the book of nature, or that we can restore or manage nature and exit the scene, leaving no trace of our work or our tools. Our work is being written on the bush and it bears the traces of our intentions—free or unfree. Unwillingness and inability to reflect on a poetics of nature, means that aesthetic baggage simply enters disciplines like ecological restoration and management by the back door. This happens overtly in what is promoted as showcasing or presentation: in packaging and selling a site as an attraction to people who aren't very interested anyway; in conforming to superseded standards of neatness, the picturesque and other old habits of landscaping; in rehashing conventional spectacles of clearing and plantingand mistaking the tree as the symbol of nature for nature itself; in making places popular, accessible and entertaining with structural follies such as raised walkways and theme park diversions to relieve the tedium of a nature that itself remains undiscovered. Raising awareness is a fetish that is always replacing the proper ends of ecological restoration in that worthy form of official Australian nature culture, Landcare, and of ecological management in national parks. These diversions into advertising usually result in kitsch and cliché. So does technocratic ecosystem management busying itself with landscapes of ecosystem functions and services, corridors and connectivity, fragment size and focal species. It cannot countenance any higher value than that of efficiency. It always bases its actions on getting a job done quickly and cheaply. It wants fast growing trees not straggling vines or pissy herbs, low maintenance ecology not difficult beauty. It believes in the tedium of work and makes it fact, afraid of the pleasures of effort. The great failure of environmental management is a failure of tasteof a taste for the act of work, and of taste for the works of nature. Instead of all this, in a poetics of nature the primary aesthetic concern should be with the true expressive materialsthe plants, animals, soil, water, topography, the tools of management, and the flesh and blood of the workersall the materials of representation replete with their particular nuances of historical meaning. They are circumstances directly found, given and transmitted from the past. And they are expressive. They can talk over you but you can’t talk over them. You have to listen and collaborate. It is in the failure to reflect on them, other than according to technocratic platitudes, that they burden us, largely as unconscious, unless or until they erupt as the nightmare of history. Like technocratic spirit, aesthetic baggage enters 283

restoration and management surreptitiously and insidiously. It leads to the deformations of these expressive materials of nature according to merely contingent ecological theories and the abstractions of the bottom line. Works purporting to be repristination or restoration of ecological function can be more like the timebound fantasies of contemporary capitalism than most are willing to admit or capable of recognizing. We see it in biological communities reconstructed according abstract schemata of structure and succession, in management for particular species or structures rather than others, in management for efficiency or orthodoxy of method or compatibility with other extraneous goals. It is precisely when working on nature that choices about these things, and the limitations on making any strictly scientific determination, confront workers. As a consequence, so does the fact that the choices are social, political, and ethical and therefore matters of which a poetics makes a virtue. Ecological management needs to be saved from the deformations of a surreptitious aesthetic disguised by an anaesthesia so thorough that it is able to solve practical problems simply by means of unconsciously aesthetic declarations. On many occasions, such declarations have posed as expert scientific advice, but it is precisely the expert’s normative limitation to a certain system of facts, that allows judgements that are utterly unconscious of those aesthetic facts that are normatively repressed. What would be good would be some isms. One ism—that of the Canadian Eric Higgs in Nature By Design (2003)— could hardly be said to think of itself in the context of aesthetic culture. Aesthetic experience is just one of the inventory of cultural values in the practice that Higgs labels focal restoration. Higgs program acknowledges the need to work on and with nature in the North American context. Like the Australian context, there is that unresolved postcolonial problem of registering the social nature of nature, both modern and traditional, against the old and cherished national environmental myth of wilderness. To address a customary schedule of contemporary social justice and environmental issues, Higgs combines ecological with cultural restoration, arguing (as it were) that you have to kill one bird to kill the other. High among the issues, is the need to free restoration from the depredations of technocratic functionalism and its mean attitude to life and nature, a need met by focal restoration’s communitarian ethic. Although written as a kind of soft academic treatise, this is out-there-inthe-community ecology in such a positive sense that it seems churlish to be negative. It would seem like a matter of mere taste. Yet that which is serious in the matter of taste is mostly what isms are about. Leaving aside the works themselves, Higgs theoretical response to technocratic restoration is in some sense a revolution within the confined spirit of managerialism. It inherits the burden of technocratic and managerial categories via academic custom and the upbeat labels of a social justice agenda. Just as someone like David Curtis (2004) advocates using the arts to promote the restoration of ecological health, Higgs wants to use the restoration of 284

ecological health as a focus for social restoration and vice versa. In each case one or other of art or nature is summoned as a means to something else—a habit of justification that invokes the functionalist principle. And in order to invoke the principle—or more accurately be invoked by it—some standard goal has to be passionlessly assumed, be it health, diversity, community or whatever. Perhaps since it isn’t self-consciously so, one cannot cite focal restoration as an ism. However unselfconsciousness is just the opportunity for the smuggling in of aesthetic and other unwanted baggage. The poetic energy of focal restoration is diverted into the metaphorical unification of several social justice issues. Health (or for that matter diversity or community) is equated with a kind of wholeness that prematurely reconciles the very social antagonisms that an art of nature would hardly be able to conceal. The challenge for works of nature, however, is to make a virtue of them. The works Higg’s describes, in particular Jaspar National Park in Alberta, sound as though they actually do this, so there might be some justification here in trusting the tale and not the teller, i.e. the works themselves rather than one of the workers and theorists. I doubt that the works lack the kind of passion that excites admiration. In Australia isms are embryonic in things like the differences between burners and non-burners, herbicide users and non-users; between the taste for trees or grass, swamp forests or sedgelands, animals or plants; over what is or isn’t Aboriginal management or scientific management; and in general between asserting different historical, cultural or functional descriptions as norms. The differences are over both ends and means. For the most part they are regarded as ideological differences. For those who take the high ground of technocratic efficiency or scientific rectitude, they are merely ideological. Across the fronts of controversy opponents charge one another or identify themselves as more or less green, scientific, rational, culturally sensitive, romantic, idealistic, holistic, purist, impractical or pragmatic, unrealistic or realistic. There is no holistic reconciliation of these differences in either a right way or in some happy compromise. Were there articulated isms, they would reflect these differences between and within works. Works might be able to quote or parody other works. An art of nature rescues the idea of a diversity of approaches from both the relativism of one method is a good as any other, and from the pseudoscientific narrow-mindedness and social impracticality of the one true method. It avoids both of these descents into irrationalism, and from the diversity of isms creates a diversity of ecosystems. It does not blur or trivialize environmental politics or scientific inquiry by precious aestheticism. Rather, aesthetic awareness lifts otherwise unconscious motives and cultural forms into the expressive material of the work of nature. It may not be entirely unconscious, but it is seldom articulated that the aesthetic of ecological management has been one of realistic representation: few would want to produce something as artificial as an exotic garden. Realism, of course, is not unknown in the history of landscaping, which has many traditions of wanting to make things look natural. But realism has not beencannot bean unchanging thing, and historically, realist art has not 285

rested long on any fixed concept of what was ‘real’nor how to represent it. Many ecological concepts that are important for bush regeneration change: like any science, ecology declares new definitions, more often than not, in order to solve otherwise intractable problems by convention. Concepts such as balance, stability, disturbance, maturity, succession, resilience, representativeness, regeneration, and biodiversity are all abstract, and all to some degree subject to reformulation. In addition, values insinuate themselves into orthodox ecological description, especially rarity, integrity or scientific value, and diversity. All are contingent and worthy of critical understanding. Bush regeneration stands in relation to ecological theory as art stands to theory generally: it does not simply reproduce theory but speculates on it and sets up itself as something autonomous in a critical dialogue with theory. That is reason enough that bush regeneration must not be ignorant of ecological science, but it can’t be in the thrall of supposedly eternal ecological facts either. Bush regeneration that simply reproduced scientifically temporary ecological models would be like drama that reproduced psychological or sociological theory: dull and untrue. Throughout the history of the arts, mimesis has implied a critique of concepts, either in the claim to provide an intuition of what concepts fall short of conceiving, or more modestly, in signifying the negation of concepts, in the way that objects themselves eventually negate our concepts of them. Like art, the art of nature cannot just imitate natural beauty. Like all great historical events so-called wild nature occurs, as it were, twice, the first time as tragedy, the second as farce. Now when we work on the genre of reconstructing or restoring nature, or even the genre of conserving it, we do so bearing in mind the image of the pristine. If that pristine nature was fated to occur as tragedy then its repristinated form is imperilled by the likelihood of occurring as farce. As delusion rather than appearance it can be farce. I have looked at restored rainforest and at works in progress and sensed this. The orthodox municipal or provincial mini-wilderness displays its defeat despite itself in the pathos of a mocked up sublime which disguises its damaged form: in longing to salvage and present a bit of the sublime past again, it pretends it is not just the icon and symbol of it remade from the index of its ruins. Probably some of the best restoration works will recognize their character as farce, happily elaborating the law of historical repetitions. The romance of repristination might do well to undergo a similar aesthetic transformation to that which narrative romance underwent when it evolved into the modern novelthat is, into what appeared to Samuel Johnson to be ‘the comedy of romance’. Still what weighs on the brains of the livingthe tradition of all the dead generationsare these things: the vastness of the landscape of damaged, degenerating nature wildly going its ownthat is naturalway; the unthinkable remoteness of restoration compared to the easy proximity of other gratifications; the abject tedium of any labour of restoration; and, especially, the nightmare that there is no conscious tradition of a poetics of nature. There is the heap of rubble and the fact that everyone is an expert in planning or wishing but 286

hardly anyone is an expert in just doing something, anything. Like art, actually making nature is not easy. There is so much passion about it, but so little passion for doing it. I can’t pretend to have an answer to this, but the conception of poetics at least offers a way of unclouding the issue. Like any poetics, the poetics of nature is a poetics of works. It is not all one great impossible second coming of nature as environmental millenarianism is accustomed to envision itdreamed, planned, delayed until better planned, delayed until the execution may be more perfectly undertaken, planned again, and then delayed again because nature has been working away and so made the initial assessment outdated. ‘Had we but world enough and time!’ In a functionally differentiated societysome might say dysfunctionallya society of landscape dissociated among discordant desires and practices, a society in which nature is just one department of land usejust as art and science are departments of endeavour, or work and leisure are departments of lifethere is no doing it all, let alone all at once. In the poetics of nature one works on the materials at hand, stopping the destruction of the past, making this bit good, making something better on the next work, and so onbuilding an oeuvre, a school, an ‘ism’, a tradition, a culture of nature. Such ad-hocery may be scandalous to the ‘landscape scale’ dream of technocratic ecosystem management. Yet even accepting the landscape scale, what other way would there be to undo the tyranny of small decisions other than by knitting back nature stitch by stitch, and what other way when the notion of a landscape unified under a systemic imperative of nature conservation rather than one divided according to the imperatives of self differentiating systems of society is a distant dream. ~ Once there is an art of nature, and we experience works of nature, then both nature and its experience are changed—but not in a way that lacks a cultural ancestry. Since Montaigne’s essay on experience, modernity has been distinguished by the development both of the concept of experience and of the quality of experience itself. Hans-Georg Gadamer (69-71) thought that, in the 18th and 19th centuries, aesthetic experience came to epitomize experience. Lived experiences were conceived as the objects of kind of aesthetic adventurelike artworksat once marked out from the rest of life yet integrated back into the whole of life, filling it with meaning. When Goethe echoes Kant and says ‘Every good or bad work of art belongs to nature as soon as it has been produced (140),’ he is registering this change in aesthetics and experience: all objects, acts and events were now open to the newly forged concept and action of aesthetically understood experience. At the first hint of light the yellow robin begins its double pulse: click click;…click click;…This becomes the rhythm of the first movement of the dawn symphony. Incredible that such a sound could come from such a small confiding bird, that it could fill the columns of the forest and awaken the whole 287

great thing. A Black-faced Monarch begins its theme and variations. A Lewin’s honeyeater sounds at odd times. Small brown birds twitter and warble here and there and then everywhere. It all grows richer and richer as new voices and themes enter. Rhythms hesitate and surprise, themes return when we don’t expect them but as if (so it seems to us afterwards) their reappearance had been ordained. It is all utterly original, never the same twice in performance, yet always satisfying our expectations as if to intimate some greater but ineffable pattern of returns to us. It is not just an analogy to describe it as music. Both music and the dawn chorus are music and nature. Both primarily experience and aesthetic. Under such conditions, differences between art, nature and life, could be relative, not absolute. Artworks old and new and nature too were not to be foreclosed in their experience by any burden of original intentions or, in nature’s case, the lack thereof. They were all given to experience as if they were objects of nature. Yet, conversely, once the differences between art and nature became relative it also became possible for artworks and the works of nature to be given to experience as objects fraught with intention. The historical shift that constructed experience as an aesthetic adventure might have been expected to aestheticize the practice out of life—but only to the extent that aesthetics emphasized its character as passive reception and not adventure. Now this notion of experience applies to the active poetics of nature, whether that nature is the work of humans or the birds. Now that nature has become like art and consists of works, nature is not only able to have meaning, it can be meant. Of course the ideal of disinterested aesthetic experience had made art and nature of a kind, but only by a process of abstraction. To experience them aesthetically was to experience them as appearancean abstraction that is still registered, and stubbornly, in the concepts of beauty and sublime. Sheer appearance though was by habit conceived as mere appearance. So it became customary that both art, and even nature, as the objects of aesthetic experience, were to be released from the gravity of substance, reality, subjective interests, intersubjective collusion, communicative intentions, truth and even meaning. They were just to wash over one as pure, abstract sensation. Or illusion. Arts where meaning at least persistedthe arts that use pictorial and linguistic propositionsor maybe all art, including even music, drifted towards the condition of fiction, and, again by custom, mere fiction stood in the same relation to truth as appearance did to reality. What these tenacious and scarcely conscious metaphysical habits abstracted from aesthetic experience though was not merely ontology’s most trumpeted categorysubstancebut also what metaphysics had always abstracted: the stubbornly intersubjective and therefore ethical nature of human experience. For such intersubjective, linguistic animals as us, perception and appearance are not just the way in which the world of things is given; they are the only ways in which the world of others is given. Artworks may want us to be dazzled by their appearance, but it is another thing for the theory of art to let itself be duped by art’s games. Forgetting that art was collusion, the theory of art deluded itself into thinking that art was primarily illusion. Even fiction, especially fiction, cannot be understood as simply 288

illusion, let alone falsehood or lie. Whatever is false in fiction is, as Adorno said, frankly false, and therefore truth. If art therefore is at the very least utterly astonishing substance, so lively and astonishing it has fooled ponderous aesthetic theory, and if, in fiction, art emulates self-creating nature itself, it is no insult to nature to assert it’s fictive status. It would be a lie to deny its fictive status in an age when natural history has become the fictile object of our designs and works. We have to make it up; and in making up nature the works of nature at once imitate, rival and embody the arch maker: nature itself. Yet nature is not admired for being made up by us. It is admired for being made by itself. For this reason landscape architecture and horticulture are arts from which restoration ecology has deliberately distinguished itself, even if in doing so it has revealed at once just how closely they are related by revealing just how important it is to be distinguished from them. It seems that the charge of artificiality militates against the emergence of an art of nature. Yet no less than art, indeed precisely as an art, works of nature need to defy artificiality, if only to earn our collusion. If natural history is to become the fictive and plastic substance of a poetics of nature whatever is false in such works must be frankly false, and whatever is shown, shown frankly as an image of nature. Works of narrative fiction show us images of lifethe mimesis of life Aristotle called it. To be precise it is the mimesis of narrative life, that is linguistic life or cinematic life, people talking, thinking, acting, looking, picturing, depicting, using the very substance of that life, namely talk, writing, pictures, gestures. Works of nature show us images of natural history, to be precise images of natural history as it is fraught with meaning, using the very substance of natural history. A landscape painter paints pictures and shows us pictorial life. A worker on nature makes works of nature and shows us natural history, makes images of nature in the already astonishing medium of nature itself. While, like an artwork, nature becomes fraught with communicative intentions, it also, like an artwork, aspires to the condition of an object given by nature and not that of a mere bearer of a message. Like Galatea in the Pygmalion myth—only perhaps happily so—works of nature come to life. Even artworks have an independent life once they leave their makers’ hands, so, in having a life of their own, works of nature are the prototype of the condition of art. Once art, nature and experience all took on their emphatic post 18th century modern forms, such experience became endlessly repeatable and, under pressure from other spheres of life, vulnerable to a certain drift into degradation. Once experience could be conceived as it is in the phrase having an experience it became something you could chalk up or get under your belt. It also became something that you could market. Tourism—so much of which is art or nature tourism—is mostly such experience marketed. Such a critical take on one form of experience should not be surprising. It is only in keeping with the modern impulse to keep working on the concept of experience and on the nature and experience of experience itself. This implies a different understanding of experience: not the notion of experiences as something you 289

have and collect, but of experience in its other sense as a process in which one encounters things and events and in turn reflects critically not only on those objects and events but also on the experience of them. The former is familiar as the process of lived experience; the latter preserves the no less familiar idea of experience as the process of coming to knowledge, the scientific processes of perception, conception and reflection carried on in its richest philosophical sense. Such experience cannot remain content with just the passivity of disinterested contemplation. Inquiry and knowledge demand the experience of practice and expression as well. As long as aesthetic experience of nature restricts itself to the side of passive reception alone it is not fully experienced or aesthetic—especially not when historical circumstance demands that we work on the expressive materials of nature and confronts us with the choice of overturning the condition of nature that, for those like Hegel, constituted the limitation of its aesthetics. And as long as we work on nature only in the narrow technical sense, as though the end of such practice were already given to us without the effort of aesthetic originality and imaginationfor certainly technical science cannot give such ends to us in any richer form than a list of ecosystem functionsthen our experience is not fully practical and scientific. It does not even begin to experience the rich functionality of nature. Karl Kraus said that ‘works of art are superfluous. It is necessary to make them but not to show them.’ It was just an aphoristic way of emphasizing the importance of process—hardly a neglected stance in modern thinking and especially not in artistic practice where as in other forms of life it has tended to become a fetish. Perhaps though we need to say something similar about the art of nature. Kraus’s point about the superfluity of the completed works reminds us how important an artist’s experience of art is. It informs one’s experience not only of one’s own works, but of the works of others. Anyone who has sung a song, written a story, taken a photo, or looked through a video camera has been given an insight into these arts. Since admiration is one of the most important responses to art, admiration is greater when one appreciates the difficulties out of which the work has been able to deliver itself. More importantly, anyone who has worked on nature has had the privileged experienced of the work and its nature, which the mere show does not show. The aesthetic and poetic status of nature has its own natural history. For an art of nature to be declared into social existence, there has to be a rethinking of both nature and aesthetic experience. In order that the following paragraph makes tolerable reading you will just have to put up with my referring to it as an art. For nature to be experienced aesthetically is not unusual. What is unusual is for works of nature to be experienced as works. Yet technocratic society experiences nature now as biodiversity and natural resources, and as managedor mismanaged. At least the norm that a work of art be something created is satisfied, even if it is not created by the genius of some post-18th artistic type in a garret, but managed, and only by a barely self-conscious genius of the times, and usually technocratically. Technocratic society is loath to discredit its management with some precious aesthetic tag, except in its idle 290

recreational moments when it is indulging or edifying itself with a little aesthetic irrationality or spirituality. Some Green theologians—technocrats too at heart, but manqué—think ecological management is all some kind of category mistake (see Higgs, 219); so strict is their dualism of autonomous nature and meddlesome culture that redemption is only conceivable if culture gives up and lets nature collapse into all-consuming authenticity. Worse, aesthetic societythe arts communityis inoculated against foreign bodies trying to penetrate its domain, beyond the odd, worthy, message-bearing fusion of the arts and science, which is usually just what acts as the inoculants. Mere declarations, especially lip-serviced interdisciplinarity from either side, will sound contrived, so completely do these spheres of life repel one another, whether as two societies, or as is just as often the case, in the compartmentalized consciousness of one person. Given the old bourgeois prejudice that persists in this compartmentalized consciousness, whatever lacks the genius of a creative artist is probably going to be easier to conceive as a craft. Piecemeal, collaborative, algorithmic works done by the likes of bushloving amateurs, community volunteers, government departments or corporations with an eye to public relations just don’t sound like art—at least not until we are reminded that art can come in the collaborative form of a gothic cathedral or a streetscape or a landscape garden or a film and not just an individual’s poem or painting. An art of nature, like any art, can only be declared into existence by the times. Such historical felicity exceeds individual intentions like mine; any declaration possesses the frailty of what is merely individual. Like many an aesthetic manifesto it is likely to end up on history’s cutting room floor. And where there is one manifesto it is likely to be one manifesto among many, each a proponent of its own ephemeral ism. What is original is always tentative, and might manage to succeed, but only if its time has come. And if it succeeds, its originality will only be recognizable in retrospect, and it will so thoroughly reconfigure the past with its own retroactive force that it will convince us that it was inevitable and that we should have seen it coming. It has been an old problem in art, for a particular art to make good its declaration of itself into existence and for it to happily render certain forms of life properly artistic. So at least then, for an art of nature to find itself in such a predicament is not so unusual. Formulations about aesthetic and poetic matters are terribly contingent. Many, once declared, become the target of works deliberately created to negate them. For indeed what is art and what is a work declares itself not in manifestos but primarily in the works themselves. The fact of works of nature may well in this case be preceding whatever art nature might become, whether it goes by the name of an art or not.

291

292

16 The Island, The Second as Farce. The restoration of a rainforest remnant.

Without lightness I achieve nothing —Michel de Montaigne, Essays

Madeira vine is a plant of myth and legend and many names. It is Anredera cordifolia for classification, Madeira, I presume, for its early dissemination through Portuguese colonialism, lambs tails for its chubby inflorescence, bridal wreath as a floral garland, jalap for the laxative tuber, mignonette for its horticultural niceties, white shroud for its funereal, flower-strewn covering of things. The cordifolia refers to the heart-shaped leaves. The Anredera part has hidden its etymological tracks. Like most of the species in local weed mythology, the plant's origins are obscurely South American. Somewhere in some South America there must be a pristine world of would-be weeds still living in their benign and natural balance, their malignant potential never unleashed because they have not migrated to more innocent lands. It seems Anredera is a native of southern Brazil, northern Argentina, Uruguay and Paraguay and Boliviaplaces that lie around the same latitude as the Bellinger, 30ºS. It occurs in what the Brazilians call mata, a word used in the title Mata Atlântica, the great stretch of forests that run, somewhat discontinuously now, down the eastern side of Brazil as far south as 30º. Mata shares its etymology with Madeira. Both refer to wooded country. Given that Australians argue the historical, and structural nuances of words like bush, scrub, brush and forest I will leave mata alone, except to say that the rainforests of the southern mata, which tend to be thicker, woodier and shorter than those of Amazonia, contain plants in some of the same genera as the pepperberries, jackwoods and carabeens that occur on The Island. Now, under the new globalized biogeography, Madeira vine grows wild throughout the tropics and subtropics of the south Pacific. Those who work in and around bush restoration like to talk up the monstrous power of weeds. It advertises a weeder’s adventurous spirit and experience. It strikes fear into the cautious heart of all who are happy to avoid

293

the tedium, folly or expense of weeding. Or it extracts a bit of entertainment valueenough at least to license one’s holding the floor in conversation, or at a conference. These intentions are the habitat of myth, and once established and reproducing itself, the myth works to put off action. Still, anredera, or andread-era as I first thought it was called, is a living hyperbole. As a general rule, the further north one goes, the more tropical, the lusher the vegetation, the more hyperbolic the weed. As a vine, it is immediately ambiguous. It does not have the obvious spatial definition of a tree. Even those who have worked against it for years can seldom clearly conceive its structure. It is a kind of amorphous, rapidly growing, rapidly strangling, rapidly cloning form. Stories about it replicate too, but with variation. One line has it growing a foot, a yard, a metre or several metres a day, twining in a right hand spiral (like most twining vines) up any unfortunate support and stretching across to anything it can reach. Fully grown, it becomes a heavy mantle of succulent leaves and tubers draped over the canopy of trees, or else, after it has weighed down and broken a tree’s crown, it is like a shroud covering the standing column of any remaining trunkbut a malignant, living shroud, waving its shoots like long tentacles searching for more. It is not always easy to find where the succulent stem of a particular vine springs from. Usually there are many vines and therefore many stems contributing to the tangled cover. Sometimes it conceals a stem and grows epiphytically, taking root above ground in the forks of trees, under the aerial roots of strangler figs or wedged beneath the stems of trunk creepers like pothos. When it flowers the whole blanket develops lush creamy racemes. In Australia these are infertile, but there are now rumours about specimens up in Queensland bearing seed. Wherever a vine grows, it spills its propagules from the canopysucculent little ginger-shaped tubers that shoot and grow on the ground beneath, even in low light. The tubers form at the bases of the leaves. At a year old, a single vine can have hundreds of tubers in its canopy, thousands according to legend. If a vine is cut, it quickly puts its resources into consolidation of its tubers, making more and fattening them up to finger size for a fall from the canopy that may take place any time over the next couple of years. The light brown tubers are said to be edible. They are very slimy when broken, bland when tasted raw, and reputedly laxativeperhaps an attribution based on the old herbalists doctrine of signatures in which medicinal virtue is signified by a plant’s outward likeness, in this case, of the tuber to a slimy turd. At certain points on a cut stem, large agglomerations of tubers can form a spherical cluster bomb, 20cm across—more according to legend—consisting of hundreds of tubers ready to shatter and disperse on impact with the ground. The ground beneath a mature vine is covered with thousands of tubers per square metre, every one viable. People have counted them in order to justify talking things up. Some tubers start sprouting immediately; others lie dormant. Very slow either to rot or dry out, they remain there, viable for years. Floods and fauna can bury the tubers and the stems of vines anything up to 30cm deep. Deeper according to legend. 294

The tuber at the base of a growing vine grows from finger size into a foot size rhizome and often branches into an underground cluster. Given time, trees can grow over them and wedge them into the soil, inextricably. Anredera roots occasionally form tuber-like swellings too, but the roots and their pseudo-tubers can’t shoot. Unless they do somewhere up in Queensland. Only the stems and the stem tubers can shootvery reliably. Carried by floods, humans and the occasional mysterious agent, they have managed to colonize nearly all the lowland floodplain and red soil rainforests left in subtropical eastern Australia. And the effects are disastrous. Anredera starves the native canopy of light, deforms its growth, weighs it down, breaks it, and eventually kills it. As well as draping itself over lowland forest, the other common habitat is the backyard fence of the country town. Specimens were originally grown there, close by the dunny, for those gorgeous fluffy lambs tails and for that laxative tuber, ready at hand. Wandering Jew is Madeira vine’s perfect partner in crime. While the vine is killing trees and vines young and old, the creeping Wandering Jew is covering the ground, eliminating germination and survival of seedlings and herbs. It gets its name from a story that long persisted in Christian Europe. Thomas Browne, the 17th century essayist and antiquarian, detailed one version in Book 7 of his Pseudoxia Epidemica—a kind of 17th century urban mythography. A contemporary of Christ, a Jew named Cartaphilus and later baptized as Joseph, was said to have been the keeper of the Judgement Hall. For expelling Christ from the Hall he was condemned to wander the world until the second coming, bearing witness to the obstinate unbelief of the Jews—a long and weary act of atonement. Clearly this wanderer personifies the migrations of the Diaspora and the story rationalizes the homeless fate of Jews. In other versions, the man was a Jew who mocked Christ on his way either from Gethsemane or to Golgotha. In all versions he was forced to be the bearer of punishment for the killing of Christ. Anti-Semitic tradition was no doubt one conduit for the tale. For its habit of spreading across the ground and propagating itself in odd places from small pieces of its brittle, succulent stem, the shiny herb with ephemeral white flowers was given its haunted name. From its native origins, yet again in that obscure, mythic South America, it has ended up in bathroom hangers, unused corners of backyards, old septic tanks and sullage trenches, garden clipping dumps, riverine forests and any other bit of moist, fertile ground it gets dropped on. Sometimes it has been called Creeping Jesus. Those now wary of antiSemitic connotations call it trad, a diminutive form of the botanist’s more formal Tradescantia fluminensis. This comes from John Tradescantthe name shared by both Charles I’s gardener and his son, a naturalist and natural history collector. The fluminensis is from the Latin for river. The original plant given this name was collected from near Rio de Janeiro, and the species occurs southwards through southern Brazil, again in mata, and through most of the same countries as Anredera. Speculation about the weedy variety in Australia is that it is probably an all green form that has reverted from a short-leaved ornamental with variegated leaf colour. Like lantana, the local weed is thus a 295

native of colonial horticulture. Like its namesake it has been deprived of a native land. Getting rid of these two weeds is not easy. Both are somewhat resistant to herbicides. In the serious infestations of the lowland rainforests, eradication has normally involved repeated spraying using a strong solution of herbicideusually glyphosateand a surfactant to make the poison stick to the leaves. Until recently, glyphosate has been preferred because of its reputation for low toxicity to animals and for quickly binding to soil particles. The use of surfactant has been a concern because of a reputation for killing frogs and tadpoles. Glyphosate’s safe reputation was much promoted by the chemical multinational, Monsanto, the company that long held the patent. It sold the stuff as Roundup®, a trademark name that became a common noun and a phrasal verb. In the 1980s glyphosate became a crucial chemical in globalized agriculture, a technology around which production organized itself, and around which developments in crop breeding and genetic engineering have since been organized. It also became a much-used technology and organizing principle of a whole generation of horticultural aesthetics and landscape architecture. Walk through municipal Australia and count how often you see verges, fences, trees and poles neatly framed with a fringe of brown rounded up lawn. It is not surprising then, that glyphosate also became the organizing technological principle of lowland rainforest restoration. The vines are sometimes poisoned by scraping the stem and painting it with glyphosate. This is done to kill as many of the aerial tubers as possible, but it does not kill all of the tubers all of the time. So in severely infested sites, the vines have usually been cut and, where time allows, left to fall, or where possible, pulled down and the tubers collected and removed. Then the spray regime is applied to re-shooting vines, the carpet of Wandering Jew and to the underground and fallen tubers that continue to sprout over the next few years. At the same time, care must be taken to protect surviving natives and protect native seedlings that sprout during the restoration process. Methods like these were initially developed at a lowland subtropical rainforest at Wingham and have since been repeated with assorted variations and innovation at every other lowland rainforest restoration. But not on The Island. Restoration work had been started many times on The Island. It was like giving up smoking many times. When more persistent work started in 1984, the discipline of ecological restorationor at least its popular environmentalist form in eastern Australia, where it went by the name bush regenerationwas at a formative and changeable stage. Environmentalism was still a thriving discourse in political and intellectual society, full of its own debates over the ecological and ideological implications of technologies. Restoration techniques and technologies were in a state of development, methods were being debated, the professional status of practitioners was being negotiated, curricula were being designed, and standards were being proposed and counter-proposed in a busy quest for the orthodoxy of a best practice and the prestige of having formulated it. Landcare had still not been heard of. Rainforest regenerators in 296

northern NSW were quick to distinguish their work from that of the bush regenerators already busy down south in Sydney. Two sisters, Joan and Eileen Bradleyin the habit of weeding Sydney sandstone woodland while taking their dog for a walkhad inspired the flourishing development of a discipline they themselves had called bush regeneration. A gentle, cunning and seemingly unprecedented art, it appealed especially to the green, post-feminist, antimachismo of the times, particularly in the leafier suburbs of the metropolis. It consisted of gradually and thoroughly removing weeds and then, as the seductive phrase puts it, letting the bush decide how to restore itself. They formulated 3 principles (Bradley, 19-21). 1. Work from areas with native plants towards weed-infested areas. 2. Make minimal disturbance. 3.Let native plant regeneration dictate the rate of weed removal. These were simple stepwise instructions. An algorithm. But they became either articles of faith or superannuated dogma in the bush regeneration wars of the 1980s. Just as the Bradleys had theorized their method in terms of a polemic against the clumsy, meddlesome and inconsistent management of municipal bushland parks, the rainforest culture up north theorized its methods in a polemic against the socalled Bradley Method. Rainforests were the high green fashion of the times. Oozing biodiversity, football fields of them were being bulldozed every minute by cowboys in Amazonia and North Queensland. Compared to the plain old bush, rainforests grew faster—especially the weeds—their flora was more complex, their soils richer, their seed production and dissemination more profligate, their vegetation canopy higher, its shade deeper, its layers more numerous. Indeed, dense tree canopy is the structural feature deemed to define rainforest or closed forest, and, by an all too happy coincidence, it could be used as the main tool of restoration. It shaded the ground and inhibited the germination and growth rates of most invading weeds. It thus increased the resistance of the native populations and reduced the resilience of weeds. It was a blessing that pure ecological science could come good with this most elegant and natural of technologies. As a defining feature of rainforest, it had the prestige of a given. It was the means and end of rainforest restoration, whatever contingencies merely empirical nature might come up with. Unlike herbicide, canopy was a device uncompromized by industrial chemistry or global capital. Within no time a can-do method that stressed the use of a safe, effective herbicide against otherwise terrifying weeds was sold in a package with the natural ecotechnology of canopy itself. It became the irresistible orthodoxy. For the then fragile, incipient professionalism, it was a method that would be unavoidable, whether in rainforest restoration or in bush regeneration generally. But not on The Island. While debates over method became almost theological, professionalism could hardly remain loyal to methods found convenient when amateurs walked the dog through open woodlands and heaths down south on the Sydney sandstone. However, the Island remained a bit of an island in the culture of rainforest restoration tooamateur, anti-professional, anti-herbicide, and sometimes, when it came to a rampant patch of cunjevoi lilies, even a little 297

indulgently anti-canopy. To some minds it was a bit like one of those islands that Gulliver visits where the locals persist with the notion of trying to make omelettes without breaking eggs. This turned out to be quite a scandaland costly when it came to attracting funding. When the Australian Bicentennial came along in 1988, The Island weeders, happy to work without herbicide, opposed its being sprayed. This led to a scrap with the National Trust, complicated by a bemused, mischievously anti-metropolitan, anti-green Shire Council. In the upshot, the Bicentennial went elsewhere to fund projects more fitting the spirit of harmonious nationalism. In functionally differentiated society, no value is advertised with such undoubting assurance as professionalism, and, along with the encouragement and the sincere lip service to gratitude, no one so easily unpaid as a willing volunteer. In a performance economy, where there is no higher value than efficiency, and nothing more dazzling than technological innovation, to work by one’s hands and on one’s haunches is to earn the opprobrious title of Luddite. So the progress of restoration on The Island was slowwalking pace let’s saybut it was along a fascinating path, and not timetabled according to the masochism of someone else’s program. It proceeded thus in the face of some worthy criticism, thoughtful discussion, much head-shaking and occasional admonishments to hurry up from the likes of the National Trust, local government, ecosystem professionals and assorted experts, and against the expectations of the old local school that saw all efforts coming to nought if the bats were not expelled. Walking pace is the pace of thoughts as Rebecca Solnit has put it. It’s also the pace of friendship, the pace of curious inquiry, and the pace of the natural history of a regenerating rainforest. Or, at least to me, that is how the restoration seemed most of the time, when it was not suffering or resisting the occasional infection from the hyperactive viruses of funded society. Bats were the other scandal on the Island. The scandal. Every year, whether in dry springs when they might plunder orchards for want of blossoms in the surrounding forests, or in late summer when their numbers on The Island are greatest, some kind of outcry against them would be sure to begin. At various times those with fond memories of The Island’s pristine bat-free past, leading citizens, shire councillors, rainforest botanists, can-do zoologists, banana growers and orchardists, residents, neighbours and lessees of the caravan park that adjoins The Island have suggested or demanded that something be done about the flying fox problem. Immediately. Sure, they are naughty animals. They eat garden fruit, make a lot of night-time noise, shit on things, spill over into neighbouring yards and give off a ripe, batty odoura heady perfume of sweet basil, manure and pheromones that can hang like a cloud over The Island and its surrounds on a muggy summer morning. At one stage in the 1980s, as the bat-loving weeders worked away, occasionally wishing they could advise, warn or negotiate with the curious little mammals, two petitions were circulated around the town for and against the bats’ removal, the numbers on each 298

cancelling the other out, and, as local politicians always like to lament, dividing the community in the process. All along the east coast it had been a tradition to shoot out flying fox camps. Bat lore is full of historical accounts and knowing solutions asserted with that proud, truculent assurance peculiar to cherished word of mouth beliefs. It was also full of light-hearted massacre stories. The White Bat is not quite a massacre story but it is part of the tradition. Someone, the local mayor it was, remembered someone and his mate who had solved the flying fox problem one year. They had got them out of the rainforest patch and out of town, back in the days of harmless larrikinism, before environmentalism. Of course, they had shot them up plenty of times. It was good target practice and harmless fun, but they found a better way. They caught a bata big buggerand painted the thing white. It wasn’t easy. The damn thing wouldn’t keep still. They had to use an old spray gun. When they let it go in the colony, that got the foxes going. You should have seen them. They didn’t know what it was. They went berserk, climbing over one another trying to get away. They flew off that night. And they didn’t come back. In the sequel they let the bat go again the next night. In the pub. That got the place going. Some of them in the bar didn’t know what they’d been putting in the drinks. Eventually the big bugger flew out a window. And you know, people still kept seeing that bat, years later. All this happened in Bellingen. And Grafton. And Maclean. And Bowraville. And elsewhere. It is told in all these towns. People still see it sometimes, that White Bat, condemned to fly around forever, like the story. There are other stories. Stories about numbers—always about numbers. About so many bats that when they flew out of the camp at sunset you couldn’t see the sky. A big summer might reach 70,000 but the usual wild estimates would have it that they’ve bred up to half a million—like a rat plague. About how long the bats have been using the camp. About their destruction of the rainforest. About the smell of those dirty, stinking, rotten bats. About how they shit through their mouths. About how the bats had never been a problem when you could shoot them and have a bit of fun doing it. Even what purported to be science was sometimes not far removed from folklore. In the absence of empirical application, word of mouth could almost qualify if it came from a bat lover or if it was the loose talk or undisinterested speculation of a scientist. The bats were supposed to drink by dipping their mouths into the water while flying along the river. In fact, they dunk their chests in and lick the water off. What they ate, how far individuals moved within and between camps, what the demographics of a camp were, what their calls were, how they mated, what predators and parasites affected them, what the total population was and whether it was growing or falling—simple facts that required painstaking observation—were not easy to come by. The best estimate is that there is a fluctuating population of around 420,000 ranging from Mackay in Queensland to Mt Gambier in South Australia. Some tagged individuals have been observed to move thousands of kilometres. As a species 299

they move around enough amongst themselves to make up pretty much a single population with a shared gene pool. The most common scientific view is that the population has fallen since European settlement and is still falling. This might be getting into the realm of speculation: the only thing empirical about history is the documentation, interpreting such data is retrospeculation, and painstaking observation of ongoing population changes takes time. Accounting, in turn, for a poorly validated estimation that has the population declining by citing things like reduction in habitat and changes in the ages of eucalypt forests is going way beyond reliable ecology. Such speculation might turn out to be valid, but it lacks good evidence and coincides very neatly with environmentalist sentiments—like mine. We know that the bats move from food source to food source, being especially partial to the nectar of certain eucalypts, bloodwoods, melaleucas and various other members of the myrtle family, as well as silky oaks, banksias and other members of the Proteaceae family. They also feed on rainforest and domestic fruits—the latter habit not endearing them to orchardists. Just how the nectar and fruit reserves differ now in amount and distribution from those 50 or 100 or 200 years ago is a question too fascinating to be answered with glib assumptions. A few years ago I went to a forum on flying foxes up on the lower Clarence, in the town of Maclean. I have attended too many meetings like this. Maclean had colonies of grey-headed and little red flying foxes hanging together in a little patch of rainforest right on the river, right next to the high school. Residents, students, academics, fauna researchers, pathologists, virologists, rainforest restorers, foresters, teachers, councillors, politicians, bureaucrats, wildlife rescuers, environmentalists, bat haters, bat lovers, balancers and inbetweeners all spoke. All the stakeholders as they say. A lot of the local people —most of them—just wanted to get rid of the bats, full stop. They said the bats were killing the rainforest, eating garden fruit, ruining orchardists, spoiling the school, shitting on children, fouling their lunches, carrying disease and stinking out the town. Stinking is a favourite word. The likely existence of a bat lyssavirusthe cause of a disease related to rabies that had killed a woman who had been scratched by an insectivorous bathad recently been in the news, so disease was a big gun in the anti-bat rhetoric too. ‘We’ve got do something about them now!’ As at most anti-bat meetings to say we don’t want to get rid of them, we just want to cull them comes across as the voice of compromise and reason. Cull is a favorite word. Bat haters know that bat researchers are bat lovers, so they suspect that their claims about bats are biased and can therefore be discounted. Various researchers said that if the bats were moved, they would probably just move somewhere else in the town; that it would not be feasible to move the bats to some predesignated place; that there was little point purchasing a designated site because the bats could not be told about itin a town in Queensland people accomplished no more than to move a bat colony from a residential area to a hospital garden; that culling the bats would simply reduce the whole eastern Australian population, and that bats would still come to the area for 300

nectar when the nearby paperbark and red gum forests were blossoming; that bat born diseases which might affect humans are very rare and eminently preventable; that bats pollinate many tree species; that bats so close to a school are an educational resource. Others advised that the rainforest could be restored; that the bat damage could be accommodated by removing the rampant viny weeds from the rainforest; that planting trees next to the rainforest on the side away from the school would also reduce the bat density near the school. Easy. Of course, many of those who did not like bats engaged in discussion about these things. Not all bat critics are ranting bat haters. Yet like leeches, bats do seem to have the power to engender a shudder of disgust even in quite rational people. And bats are, like many a wild animal, naughty. Very naughty. Especially in large numbers. And then of course someone told The White Bat, winning hearts with a bush yarn. After lunch a student from the high school took the stage. She declared that the bats terrorized and revolted the kids, shat on their sandwiches, got caught in long hair, disrupted the sports carnival, disrupted science classes, and caused illness. All the students wanted all of the bats gone. All of them. They’ve got do something about them now. The same opinions had been expressed by others during the day, but she had given them that winning candour, the sincerity and authenticity of youth. She was the voice of young people and future generations. When she’d finished, one of the academic bat researchers, cutting the losses, quickly stood up and responded by thanking her for the honest expression of her views, congratulated her on her courage in speaking, and acknowledged that her views were a cause for concern and a reason for action (which he did not specify). Two friends and I driving home that evening had no need to be so magnanimous. Out of the mouth of a babe had come rumour, superstition, fable, untruth, and truculence. Her speech reminded me of The Crucible, like someone pointing the finger at witches. I’ve been at meetings where lone defenders of bats get hooted and laughed at. All day, anger had simmered barely below, (sometimes above) the surface of many a wild claim, a kind of truculent, surly contempt, smugly excusing itself as honest, innocent indignation. It wasn’t a good day for bats, but I didn’t think it was a good day for we the people either. Truculence is a culture, a cranky culture for sulkers and sooks. During a bat crisis in the Melbourne Botanic Gardens the management put up official signs advertising it. The signs said the bats spelt the end of the gardens. This kind of thing flourished in Maclean too. And in Bellingen. As an excuse for not doing anything to conserve and restore the rainforest on The Island it almost became self-fulfilling prophecy. In Maclean it did become self-fulfilling prophecy. Any ecological claim that didn’t pander to the sooks was treated with truculence or ignored. However it turned out that there was a bat expert who advertised himself as a bat mover. He was a can-do bat professional when it came to herding bats, a practical ecologist working in an instrumental scienceno pussy footing for himand he found the perfect clients. Though not present at the meeting his prospectus offered the only claims worth hearing, the only 301

strategy worth funding. The course of official thought and action just had to flow between claim and counterclaim, between science and truculence, straight into the handy outlet he’d prepared. Chris Tidemann (2003) got the contract to move the bats by using intense, loud noise. Chainsaws and fire-crackers apparently worked best on the recalcitrants. For a couple of years after the initial eviction the bats tried to re-occupy Maclean. 15 times they came back and 15 times they got hounded off with more noise. Bat moving was the applied ecology to get a go. Rainforest restoration didn’t get a shoe in. As in the Melbourne Botanic Gardens, where the management let the precious Fern Garden fester just to show how awful the bats were, the remnant rainforestthe pleasure and heritage of Macleanwas left to degrade, reifying the claims of those who said the bats spelt its doom. It gave people the sweet satisfaction of successful prediction and the gratification of public indulgence in righteous self-flagellation. Sulking fed off its success, keeping open its sores and displaying them. It was win win. Unfortunately though, it was not win win win: no one ever did manage to get bat lyssavirusthe deadly rabies-like infectionor any other suspected bat disease. And it wasn’t win win win win either: the rainforest got no better when the bats were hunted off. The Melbourne Bat Crisis was manufactured in 2001, the same year that the panic button was pushed over the famous Tampa Crisis. The management erected a sign in the gardens advertising the crisis as ‘the greatest threat in its 154 year existence’. During the crisis, Andrew Bolt, the right-wing journalist and dab ad hominem rhetorician, started an article with the old line about bats always seeming evil. A dollar for every bat article that starts like this. Cue Count Dracula and vampires. There must be something evil about them given the way they engender this rabid behaviour in people. They are like people. But bat detestors see them as inversions of people in a world turned upside down. Grotesque, disgusting inversions. Those light-hearted massacre stories always remind me of how bats behave in a panic—even when someone just breaks a stick beneath a tree. They remind me of the eyewitness description of the Darkies Point massacre, up at the end of the Bellinger Valley in 1841. The narrator had gazed down on a group of people caught on a cliff edge under volleys of gunfire. When I read the description I had understood how there was a poetics of panic, a kind of sublime, prurient pleasure in gazing at anonymous others reduced to grotesque figures and humiliated in the wild moment of mass suffering. In Bellingen, bat crises still come up year after year. One year there is a dry spring and they raid orchards. Another year a swarm of Little Reds arrives. More itinerant than the grey-headeds, they come on occasion for short periods in great numbers. They hang thick in the trees like a crop of fruit obscene in its abundance and they wipe out a lot of foliage. Another year the population of grey-headeds swells in late summer because there is not much for them to feed on further north. They colonize the trees in the caravan park. Another year they start up a new camp in Urunga or Coffs Harbour or Bowraville—not because they are rapidly breeding up, but because they are chasing variable supplies of 302

nectar and fruit around the country. Another meeting is held. Even when 6000 bats die on The Island in the 45°C heat of a January stinker, the bats don’t have a crisis, they become a crisis. A health issue. Sometimes I just wish you could whisper to them and advise them: Look, just go over there for a while. They have a fortunate or unfortunate habit of setting up camp in towns and cities. There may be many reasons why. Perhaps they like the places people like—like the tidal limits on rivers, or largish tree-filled gardens or rainforest remnants. Perhaps they use rivers to navigate. And roads. They drive down Anzac Parade in Sydney and turn left at Cleveland St, down to feed on the trees in Centennial Park. Perhaps nectar and fruit are in reliable supply in towns. Perhaps there is now just such a lot of urban landscape anyway. Perhaps all of the above. In the 1980s, Bellingen Shire Council, although favouring culling, had been forced by environmental bureaucracy to opt for another tactic. They tried scaring the bats away using ‘Birdfrite’ cartridges fired by shotguns. A friend who lived near The Island was arrested for hiding a case of cartridges under the Wandering Jew. The repeated gunfire had kept his baby awake. Years later the red and blue plastic shells would still turn up under the leaf litter. The council even undertook what pretended to be a hi-tech attempt to broadcast ultrasonic noise at them from speakers hung in stinging trees. This solution probably had something to do with the notion that, like little insectivorous bats, large fruit bats use sound and echoes to navigate. They don’t. Some wit commented that if they did then they were using the ultrasonic signal to navigate their nightly return back to The Island after feeding. Newspaper photos of the day showed bemused bats hanging next to the speakers like stunned fans waiting between bands at a rock concert. The council was never competently ruthless enough to succeed and eventually became powerless in the matter. The National Parks and Wildlife Service was given the power to make decisions about flying foxes, and finally, in 2001, grey-headed flying foxes were declared a threatened species. Moral panic about vast breeding hordes blackening the evening sky was no substitute for the ongoing population studies that suggested a gradual decline. A long diversion on bats is only appropriate. Bat crises have been a constant diversion on The Island. But by the mid 1980s they could no longer be a diversion from restoring the rainforest. They were a regularity. You could rely on them. You could plan around them. For them. For me they make The Island even more interesting. For some, too interesting. I said a persistent effort at the restoration of The Island began in 1984. But persistence is a quality that is not a fact until after the fact. Like the beginning of a story, many phenomena stand in this special relation to time: promises, friendship, originality, memorability, self-identity, the function of an evolved adaptation, the judgement of a work of art. All are subject to the judgement of history. It is why Solon advised the obscenely wealthy Croesus never to judge anyone’s life happy until they are dead. Even history’s irrevocable past, history as it actually wasincluding this history of The Islandcan only be the end of a succession of tellings, the product of the eventual selection of things told about the past. Only time will tell. In the case of The Island of course the most 303

eloquent of these tellings will be The Island itself. Persistence is also a relative rather than an absolute quality; what might be long-term persistence for a human is only a blink in the eye of a society’s tradition of exploitation, or of its culture of nature, or of a rainforest’s growth to maturity. Still, in such a timequeered universe persistence is a valuealmost an absolute one. Merely to state the aims and methods of rainforest restoration is just a blink in the eye of time. Yet people can spend years doing this. We are such goal oriented creatures, that we are ready to entertain ourselves endlessly with planning and then fussing about getting the beginning right. Social conditions favour this: our society has long recognized and employed planners and managers, but not, until recently, rainforest regenerators. Besides, planning is easier and more pleasant and more lucrative than weedingfor most people. Perhaps all the management plans and all the statements of aims and all the prescriptions of methods are primarily fetishes, or at least the fruits of a kind of misunderstanding about nature and the task of restoring it. Perhaps the restoration of The Island was not a goal-oriented, teleological action at all. Perhaps its end could not and still cannot be foreseen. In a teleological process the end is setit is the organizing principle throughout the course of the processand then each stage in the procedure is undertaken so as to achieve that end within some at least roughly pre-specified time. But perhaps restoring The Island has been more algorithmic in character. Such a procedure differs from a teleological process primarily in that its length need not or may not be known ahead of timeit is often the case that it can only be known after the factand the actual outcome of the procedure will not be known until after the procedure has been undertaken. It is a matter of just bandicooting away according to a given set of repeatable tasks, watching what happens. The method of weeding was algorithmically blind to the bigger task. Do this bit here because it is already pretty good. Go over it tuber by tuber, leaf node by leaf node, seedling by seedling, again and again. Tiny as the bit was, you have the pleasure of almost instant bush. Maintain what has been achieved while proceeding to the next bit. Typically if some big picture person with visions of weed-free vistas was allowed to clear too muchand there was always someone who thought that they would bestow some such boon upon the poor crawling regularsmuch of the supposed gain would be lost. The nature of the weeds, the pace of native regeneration and the pace of the weeders determined just how big an area was to be done at one time. I have found that it is a concept almost beyond the imaginative grasp of most humans that a square metre weeded and maintained in the midst of and downstream from a whole landscape of weeds is better than a square kilometre weeded and lost, let alone a thousand square kilometres or a whole catchment merely dreamed in the the big picture of the landscape scale. Wild human reason cries out, ‘But there is so much to do!’ or ‘There is no point starting unless we do the WHOLE catchment!’ In the notion of merely planning and persisting and taking pleasure in no more than a square metre of work, inveterate, human goal-oriented reason can see nothing but the pathos of futility, ad-hocery, and defeat. 304

In 2000, after the first decade of Landcare, the official social movement that they helped to launch, Philip Toyne and Rick Farley, were reported saying that the success of Landcare had been to provide information and stimulate attitudinal change, rather than having a large direct impact on changing the direction of environmental actions. Curiously, they were also reported saying that progress was being prevented by platitudeslike theirs perhaps. Perhaps they were trying to be positive, but this dismal and perennial stimulation of attitudinal change, or raising community awareness is another fetish to substitute for starting. The other received criticism of Landcare and the Natural Heritage Trust was that lots of piddling, disconnected things had been done and where was the big picture in all this. In order to get that picture, this all too glib observation ushered in a regime of monitoring, gratifying the insatiable desire for anything but just doing it. I am no apologist for the Natural Heritage Trust that funded much Landcare, but a big picture is built from a million pixels, and each pixel of what’s pictured has to be worked on. Big is empty. Everything is in the detail. Success, they say, has many parents. So does failure. On the little Island several people have worked away, different people at different times over the years, meeting each fine Tuesdaya grab bag of bleeding hearts, do-gooders, fiddling Luddites, aspiring astronauts, security risks, concertina players, Leapers, loafers and old lefties, dole bludgers, activists, bat lovers, buskers, Islandettes, Batettes, bandicoots, grey-headed flying foxes, vandals and very naughty swamp wallabieswith nothing better to do. If bush regeneration was an art, The Island wasat least up until it won a Landcare award and got some National Heritage Trust fundingits Underground. We would arrive separately in the morning and work separately and differently on different bits, each according to one’s inclinations or abilities, sometimes at cross-purposes, and then together after morning tea, cutting the curtains of Anredera where remnants of the old canopy still stood, pulling down the vines and tubers, piling them to compost, ideally letting the remaining aerial tubers fall over the next couple of years, not letting the vines climb back up in the mean time. Ideally. Then teasing or rolling up the carpet of Wandering Jew, picking up any stems and leaf nodes left behind, composting it all. And that at last was the start. The actual work was the follow-up, follow-up and follow-up: the ‘three rules of restoration’. Technologically we preferred the Neolithic to the hi-tech: primarily the hands, the hand trowel and the knife. As the tubers sprouted they would be dibbled up with fingers and trowels, bagged and composted. If Anredera vines managed to twine back up into the trees again they would be unwound, their tubers dug up and bagged too. As unweeded bits of Wandering Jew revealed themselves in new growth, they would be teased up off the ground or out of the native flora, bagged too and composted too. Ideally. The tubers were not always successfully dug. Brittle and often deep, it was easy to leave living bits of tuber behind in the ground, especially in heavier soil. And the tubers sprouted at different rates too. At the very least, a bit of ground and whatever canopy 305

remained above it would, after initial treatment, require two years of vigilance and determined weeding before the natives were more resilient than the weeds. Two years of watching native seedlings appear, of searching out weeds among the proliferating giant maidenhair ferns, the lacy ground ferns, the pollia and aneilema, of unwinding new vines from the cunjevois, of digging deep tubers from among the buttresses of old trees. Eventually a regular group of friends found themselves selected by the nature of the task, down on their haunches among the ticks and leeches, kneeling on stinging tree leaves, talking nature, politics, art, music, religion, history, ideas, food, gossip, as they went, lying low to avoid the simmering controversies over bats and methods, looking up occasionally at the call of a bird or into the curious eyes of a swaying flying foxyes all of it going on under the gaze and chatter of 50,000 flying foxes, the leaves littered over the ground by their industry, the foliage of seedlings and herbs spattered in high summer by their particoloured shit, khaki with eucalypt stamens, bottle green with mistletoe seeds, purple with fig, pink with guava, orange with pawpaw. Where there was no remnant canopy, trees had to be planted into the weedscape to grow a new one. Giant stinging trees, sandpaper figs, and red cedars were what came up naturally in sunny gaps and they grew fast, so they were the main species planted. But there were plenty of others. And five years later when their crowns touched one another, and the bats deigned to use them, the time came to roll up the weedy carpet underneath them too. On the water-stripped riverbanks it was river mat-rush, weeping lilly pilly trees and sandpaper figsplants that can be whipped and bent under 5 metres of wild floodwater and still hold themselves and the soil together. Here we were part of a great tradition. Up on the Never Never the locals had been slowly knitting their riverbanks back together and winning praise for it. All over the north coast now there is a culture of ripariana. Banks erode, water gets polluted, eutrophied, turbid. Silt clogs the matrix of gravel, suffocating organisms. Childhood swimming holes disappear, reaches become clogged by weeds, fish disappear, banks become weedy. When it comes to working on nature it is rivers that get worked on most. Here we were part of the long task of reconciling the social desire invested in their beautiful and damaged nature The Island’s restoration all happened so slowly that people often did not recognize there were changes. Sympathizers would try to reassure the weeders that they could see changes. All around The Island, particularly in the old course of the river where floodwaters would periodically rip through, the weedscape was left to grow while the main rainforest on the higher ground was imperceptibly restored. Visitors to the place would have to cross from the caravan park to The Island via the old swimming hole footbridge now almost submerged in silta narrow path with rampant, tick-infested weeds threatening to engulf it, a sort of eye of the needle for nature lovers. In the new millennium the lessees of the caravan park made things more of a challenge. They banned all public access across their leasehold, giving the weeders an unexpected opportunity to canyon down a stormwater drain called Ringworm Creek. Crossing cascades and riffles of dumped concrete and foam mattresses, there 306

was a chance of some greywater rafting during floods or after summer storms. Years after the restoration had been plodding on, letters would still arrive at the local paper decrying the fact that no one was doing anything about the old place. Being a kind of art that likes to conceal art, I suppose such an observation can be taken, perversely, as high praise in the aesthetics of restoration culture. It was all a bit embarrassing. Restoration ecologists sometimes distinguish between, on the one hand, something called adaptive management and, on the other, some presumably more incisive, minimally intrusive, technologically adept interventions suggested (it is to be expected) by theoretical ecology and developed in rigorous statistical trials. The latter is imagined as the scientific and technological ideal. Cutting edge. World’s best practice. Its appeals to the values of efficiency, precision, control and best practice follow from ecological science’s niggling aspiration to the status of other physical, instrumental sciences. Adaptive management is a procedure of trying something, typically on an initially small area, seeing how it goes, and then refining it when proceeding to the next stage of the procedureusually a series of follow up stages undertaken on the same given area. After the given area has been attended to and procedures refined along the way, then the management proceeds to the next area, this time using the refined techniques and method; meanwhile what has been achieved in the first area is maintained. I say that is adaptive management, but others might disagree. That, at least, is how it was adapted to The Island. When dealing with a natural historical process like the restoration of a biological community, adaptive management of some form is almost unavoidable; the unpredictabilities of natural history demand it. The ongoing nature of things historical demands it. And, at least as I have described it, it is a procedure that can work piecemeal and systematically over a geographical area. Certainly predictive ecology and adept intervention are of the utmost importance, even when one must resort to a procedure of adaptive management. Bad adaptive management might amount to no more than what the ecologist Ian Lunt (2001) has called ‘start it up, stuff it up and start it up again’. The most common form of bad management though is worse: start it up, give up, and leave it stuffed up even morebreaking eggs without making the omelet. As in algorithmic processes generally, each action in a procedure need not be especially clever or complicated or grand: the instructions can be quite simple. Persistent application is what counts. There is no once-only action for removing exotic weeds or feral animals from a community of plants and animals. Follow-up is the bulk of the procedure; and restoration works that fail do so because, for all the fuss and fanfare of their start, and all the ingenuity of their plans and techniques, they do not persist. Whether you spray herbicide or not, in subtropical rainforests restoring a site demands that treatment be reiterated several times over several years. Why use a technology that you don’t want to use if using it means you wont want to come back? Or why fund a program that will only last one year? 307

Notwithstanding people working at occasional cross-purposes, the periodic havoc of floods and tree falls, sometimes taking three steps forward and two steps back, and other forces of nature, the algorithm eventually works. Eventually. Cross-purposes may get written into the results on the ground, but this differs little from the way that the naughty wallabies’ purposes are written into the results, or the bats, or the vandals’. Certain more tangible, shorter term ends work themselves into separate subroutines of the algorithmthings like morning tea, conversation, friendship, seeing what has happened somewhere, seeing what it looks like since the booyongs seeded or now the fine cool winter weather has come, or the bats have gone, or come back. At each iteration the burden is reduced, native species eventually dominate a site and invasion by weeds declines to a minimum. Even then, weeds get reintroduced by birds, water and wind, because a place like The Island is in the sea of a modern culturescape rampant with the globalized flora and fauna of exotic species. So the procedure must continue as maintenanceeven if considerably less maintenance than a pasture, a golf course, a front-yard or a football field demands. And living complexes of organisms do not stand still. There is no getting out of natural history: in the end there is no end. Another thing restoration ecologists like to stress is the importance of setting goals and selecting indicators for assessing their achievement (see Lake, 2001). However, during any process of restoration, things happen and questions arise that can make such goals seem somewhat arbitrary. You try something and it works in unexpected ways. You change your goals. Bertolt Brecht said somewhere that production is a matter of not quite knowing where you are. As authors often say, the characters take over. Nature itself, the works of nature and the unfinished new human-globalized nature that keeps on emerging as the great distinctive feature of the Quaternary, seem to be asking us to think again and question whether rigid initial goal setting was not just some inappropriate teleological habit, and whether the goals were not somehow given by a dumb aesthetic orthodoxy, under cover of ecological prestige. What is a goal anyway when nature and society shift too fast for it and under its feet? What is a goal if, at the end of the day, there is no end of the day? The Island was exemplary in this regard. There were decisions to be made about the relative value of certain species: What about the relative importance of animals versus plants? Should those bats be tolerated when they damage the canopy and crop the rainforest back to a low scrub and rub epiphytes from the branches of trees? Does the need to remove Wandering Jew for native seedling establishment justify removing its function as habitat for dwarf crown snakes and salt and pepper Challenger’s skinks and Murray’s skinks? A regenerating rainforest goes through many different structural and floristic stages, so is any stage more important than the others? Shouldn’t intermediate stages of recovery be valued for their own qualities? Is some final mature phase rightly the main goal, even if it is going to take hundreds of years to reach it? Are mere herbs like pollia and cunjevoi expendable? What about ferns or the generations of tree seedlings laid down 308

and then mostly laid waste year after year? Are native vines that scramble over trees going to be tolerated? Are trees and tree canopy the be all and end all, the happy means as well as the unambiguous end of rainforest restoration? Should the aim be restoration of an actual, historically specific community rather than a weird, historically unprecedented community that nevertheless consists of local native species? With 50,000 bats mowing a canopy that growing like crazy down to a 10 metre lawn of stinging trees, booyongs and sandpaper figs, aren’t those who yearn for the dark, high, multi-textured canopy of memory justified in dismissing the so called restoration as a misguided failure? With weedy town and farm all around it, and the country having lost all ecological memory of its pristine nature, how can the rainforest any longer decide properly what to do after the weeds are removed? What hope that The Island could be anything more than a damaged, malignant reminder of the pastscarcely an image, remotely an index, arbitrarily a symbolat best an ironic, postmodern reference to the present lapsed condition of nature? Then there are questions of appropriate means. In many ecological communities there is the question of whether one should use fire in order to encourage fire adapted rather than fire intolerant species, but is fire ever useful in rainforest restoration, or is it anathema? What about other technologies such as heavy machinery, tree planting and silvicultural practices? What about using genetically engineered pioneer species to get a quick temporary canopy? For that matter, what about this canopy technology even when it is only engineered from endemic pioneer tree species? Doesn’t the quick establishment of canopy foreclose on the option of exhibiting a community in which short-lived, lightloving species do their thing? What about everything from flame throwers to biodynamic preparations. What about doing nothing and going with flow? What about herbicide? This last technical and methodological questionherbicidewas also a political question about a technology in the context of busy environmentalist critique of technologies, a critique that was properly framed in the context of the old ethical relation of ends and means. And since it had begun as a political question it became quite publicly one on The Island. I have already answered it in part: Why use a technology that you don’t want to use if using it means you wont want to come back to do the maintenance? Two years before the herbicide issue reached a crisis on The Island, the question had arisen at Wingham Brush. There, the locals had wanted to spray herbicide and the National Trust, concerned about its effects, had insisted they shouldn’t. The Wingham group outlasted the Trustit was their own ground after all and they could keep coming back. Eventually, after a change of personnel at the Trust, spraying herbicide became accepted and promoted not simply as professional and best practice but as the only feasible practice. Perhaps the practicalities of professionalism blinded the Trust to the social nature of nature. Anyway, the claim about feasibility was just not valid, especially with a bunch of plodders and fiddlers on a small remnant like The Island. But even then, why would

309

anyone living in labour saving society not want to use this labour saving technology? Well, perhaps they might like the work. If I speak personally I would have to say how tedious I find herbicide. How impractical it is to carry around, how it gets between me and the things I am working on, how it changes the action of weeding from a nice physical engagement like walking or wrestling and talking into an experience of wearisome almost disembodied concentration, like drivingbut without the view and without the meditation. Why wouldn’t painters give up and take snaps or buy postcards. I am now surprised how often herbicide is used even when a manual or mechanical technique is more efficient; but then, people like using it, and it’s a custom. As in the restoration of works of art or architecture, the question of rainforest restoration methods has always been concerned with producing something befitting the original being restored. It is almost always assumed that authenticity, apart from efficiency, is a major question in the herbicide debatethat using a particular technology results in a better or more authentic restoration. When it comes to ecological restoration though, I think there are many ways to skin a cat. I would argue that whatever the means, it is persistence, skill and care that countand, dare I say, pleasure. Given the social nature of nature, the more means at hand, the more restoration. Probably, like nature, we plodders had nothing better to do. Many questions of ends and means confronted the people working on The Island. Just how much they get posed as ecological questions with ecological answers, and just how much they arise as political questions that technocratic ecology might dismiss as impractical and ideological, they are primarily poetic. To assert what, in philistine terms, would be condemned as such a precious idea, is to assert that this work involves aesthetic motives. To assert the aesthetic character of nature is to assert that all the values listed in technocratic and political societybiodiversity, ecosystem functions, water quality, whateverare only values because their end, like art, is not only life, but the good life. So in turn, decisions about means are questions of craft. Considered in this context, these matters are far more important than merely individual preferences. In technocratic ecology individual preferences end up in the dustbin of history, but in aesthetic society individuality and particularity might just get asserted. They can become more than merely personal or subjective. Come to think of it, particularity is what matters in nature too. The Island was wilder than wilderness, and restoration in the midst of such an abundance of natural and social history could not help but reveal the contradictions inherent in aims conceived simplistically as purely those of technocratic ecology. These contradictions were and still are there to be read off the work of The Island itself, in rampant sunny patches of cunjevoi, in troops of seedlings across the ground, in the patches of a canopy mown down by the bats, in areas with few seedlings or little ground cover or understorey or shrub and vine structure, in the magnificently ugly weedscape that immediately surrounds The Island like a wild sea, in successes, failures and follies all alongside one 310

another. These things show social antagonisms as much as they do nature’s. Certainly one could do better than what often becomes the emergent wildness of volunteer work, with all its unfortunate baggage of false communitarian worthiness. Certainly The Island could have been restored more adeptly, less intrusively, faster. Nature could have done a better job too. It could have pulled up its socks. Floods buried thousands of seedlings under silt and brought more weeds along with it. Wallabies nibbled planted seedlings like sweeties on a plate. Vandals could have laid off the trees, instead of blissfully doing all that hard work of cutting hundreds down. All these things though become new historical meanings in a place that must obtain under the new dispensation of nature. More importantly though, like any work it deserves to be judged not by its intentions but by what is produced on the ground. Trust the tale not the teller. Perhaps the unexpected events that take place in the natural history of a work of restoration arise from the limitation of restoration culture’s self understanding. The peculiar post-colonial conditions that apply in coastal, subtropical Australia have had an affect on shaping the way restoration ecology sees itself in this country, especially on this humid east coast. There is a kind of war between natives on the one hand and weeds and ferals on the other. Indigenous biological communities are understood as being made up of species that have long evolved together. The common assumption is that this long evolution has resulted in a great deal of biodiversity. Over time, more and more species have evolved to find their own small niche in any given community. The post-colonial weeds and ferals are understood as species that invade indigenous communities and compete successfully with and to the detriment of indigenous species. This success is typically explained by the absence of the exotic species’ pests or predators in their new environment, and by the absence of adaptation among the indigenous species to compete, survive and reproduce in an environment that becomes dominated by the exotics. In critical cases, these invasions transform the indigenous communities by causing local extinctions of species and reducing the diversity of the original communities, thus producing different kinds of community altogether. Considering all the scientific speculation implicit in this string of rationalisations, and all the ideology pent up in it, and all the aesthetic desire invested in it, it is little wonder that the responses of nature to restoration surprise our expectationsespecially when our works of nature are nature’s works and when nature’s works now throw our own repressed and ugly image back at us from where we had least expected to see it. When such things surprise us, what should we do? Are there scientific theories or even just environmental standards that resolve these questions? Sometimes events and results, expected and unexpected, have occurred juxtaposed together on The Island. In some places they have existed in the succession of time. In the poetics of nature, the exhibited works change all the time. You don’t keep them in an air-conditioned museum to preserve them. There may now be 81 species of native tree on The Island, where there used to 311

be 68, 30 vines where there used to be 13, 14 ferns where there were 5, 14 new perennial herbs all having naturally regeneratedand no new epiphytes at all. There are god-knows-how-many insects and etceteras. But it will change, and the structure will change and animals will come and go and any and every stage is its own end. It will change by the second as the bird flies, as the bat fans itself on a summer morning, as the upside-down fly shunts around the cunjevoi spathe, as the water dragon drops into the river, as the dwarf crown snake disappears into the pollia, or as the light shifts over the ground while the wind rustles the leaves. By the minute as land mullets copulate beside a fat log, or bats fly around after some undue disturbance, forced to take to their big wings in midday sun. By the day as the stinging tree is brushed, stings, inflames the skin, stabs lymphatically up under the arms later when you wash, and slowly subsides into an itch over night. By night as the swamp wallaby browses the sandpaper fig and the bandicoot burrows after grubs. Seasonally as the bats come and go, tearing off leaves when they arrive, letting in the light to fall on the forest floor, giving birth, hanging around all the long humid summer, yakking, licking, fucking, taking off at twilight, the mass breaking into soft black fragments all over the sky, heading east along the river or somewhere else, these foresters of the night, in search of blossoms, returning just before dawn, eventually leaving the canopy to the fig birds and pigeons during winter. Yearly as the weeping lilly pillies bend under freshes and floods and the odd white booyong topples from the bank, as tens of thousands of seedlings germinate to feed a herbivore, or to survive and growwhether across the ground or over trees or up into a gap in the canopyeach at their different rates, each in their distinctive forms, together constructing a complex where there had been the simple masses of anredera and Wandering Jew. In decades, as the slow surpass the quick, as big floods come and destroy a hundred thousand seedlings under a sheet of silt, sending rare species back into local extinction, as old giants that knew Gumbaynggirr times fall in big winds, as The Island shifts itself like a great beast in the river, and things happen that no one can notice until years later. And beyond lifetimes there are timescales that defy observation and can only be imagined using theories of long-term rainforest succession, and geomorphology and beyond that, times so long The Island will not matter any more. Our little works in nature are not the frozen music of cathedrals but narratives, extended dramas of history, comedies and tragedies, absurdly overburdened with incident, impossible to follow, utterly unrepeatable, with beginnings, middles and ends following beginnings middles and ends in sequel after sequel, long and fast and slow, neverending. This is why ends pure and simple are not the ends of restoration. It is why, if you want closure, have counselling instead. It is why what Aldo Leopold said (175) about the aesthetics of nature is so true: that the richest experience of nature is given to those who work on it and with it, who run their hands over the soil, who imitate the action of a bandicoot, the scratching of a turkey, who watch the crawling galaxies of invertebrates, the seedlings or the leaves and fruits, with the eye of a pitta, a swamp wallaby or a flying fox, and who at least 312

see some of the scenes in the unfolding tale. It is why the notion of getting it all done and out of the way as quickly and efficiently as possible is wrong-headed. It assumes that people do not want to do it and just want to get it over with. That it’s a mug’s game. It is as if people would rather just know the end of a story without having the tedium of reading it. It reveals how unknowing society is about happiness and about itself, how wowserish in its selection of the permitted practices of pleasure, how little able to countenance the commonwealth of the senses rather than the dictatorship of gratification. It is a pathetic predicament for a society that needs a poetics of nature, an erotics of nature. It’s a bit sad really, a bit of a joke. You can see it told now in The Island and in the various restored municipal mini-wildernesses and in all the restoration works that started out to reconstruct the pristine from its tragic ruins. It is nature the second time as farce.

313

Selected Source Notes The sources of direct quotations and references are acknowledged in the text using the Harvard system. The following notes cite particular authors upon whose work I have drawn significantly for the first three chapters, but whose work, nevertheless, I have interpreted to the extent that the ideas, though indebted to the respective authors, should not necessarily be attributed to them. The ideas expressed are my responsibility. 1. The Island, The First Time As Tragedy Flying-foxes: Eby, Peggy, 1995; Jones, Vivien, pers. comm.. General history of the Bellinger Valley since European settlement: Braithewaite, Norman, & Beard, Harold. 1978. Geomorphology of the Bellinger River: Cohen, Timothy J., 2003 & pers. comm.. History of Bellingen Island and of Flying-fox colonies: Lunny, Daniel & Moon, Chris, 1994. History of vegetation in the Bellinger Valley in the 19th century: Hodgkinson, Clement, 1845; Maiden, J.H., 1894; Swain, E.H.F. 1912. 2. Imagining The Pristine Earliest written descriptions of the Bellinger Valley: Hodgkinson, Clement, 1845; Hawkesworth, John, 1969; Eldershaw, Finney, 1854. Reports of traditional Gumbaynggirr and Dunghutti culture and history: Ryan. J. S., 1988; Blomfield, Geoffrey, 1981. 3. Tallowwood Country Cultural history of eucalypts: Hay, Ashley. 2002. Eucalypt ecology and silviculture: Florence, R.G. 1996; Floyd, A.G. 1962; Van Loon, A.P. 1966. Eucalypt evolution, ecology and taxonomy: Hill, Robert S. 1994; Williams, Jann E., & Woinarski, John C. Z. (eds). 1997; Ladiges, Pauline. 1997. Eucalyptus flowering: Law, B. Mackowski, C. Schoer, L. & Tweedie, T. 2000. Evolution and taxonomy: Hull, David. 1988. History of Australian vegetation: Lange, R.T. 1982; Smith, J.M.B. (ed.) 1982; Singh, G. 1982; Hill, Robert S. (ed) 1994. History of vegetation in the Bellinger Valley in the 19th century: Hodgkinson, Clement, 1845; Maiden, J.H., 1894; Swain, E.H.F. 1912.

314

Bibliography Adair, R. J. 1995. The threat of environmental weeds to biodiversity in Australia: a search for solutions. In Bradstock et al 1995, pp 184-201. Adorno, Theodor W. 1973. Negative Dialectics (trans. E.B. Ashton) London: Routledge  1984 Aesthetic Theory (trans. C. Lenhardt, eds Gretel Adorno & Rolf Tiedemann) London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Bacon, Francis. 1620 Novum Organum (ed. & trans.Basil Montague). Hanover Historical Texts Project, http://history.hanover.edu/texts.html Barkow, Jerome H., Cosmides, Leda & Tooby, John (eds.) 1992. The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology & the Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press. Benjamin, Walter. 1968. Illuminations. London. Jonathan Cape (1970)  2002. Selected Writings. Volume 3: 1935—1938 Cambridge, Massachussets: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Benson, J. S. & Redpath, P. A. 1997. Nature of pre-European native vegetation in SE Australia: a Critique of Ryan et al (1995) The Australian Landscapeobservations of explorers and early settler. Cunninghamia Vol 5(2): 285-328 Berndt, Ronald & Catherine. 1989. The Speaking Land, Ringwood, Victoria: Penguin Books Australia Birmingham, John. 1998. Leviathan. Milson’s Point, NSW: Vintage Books, Random House.  2003. Off One’s Tits: ill-considered rants and raves from a graceless oaf named John Birmingham. Milson’s Point, NSW: Vintage Books, Random House. Blomfield, Geoffrey. 1981. Baal Belbora: The End of the Dancing. Chippendale, NSW: Alternative Publishing Co-operative Ltd. Boswell, Anabella. 1965. Anabella Boswell’s Journal: An Account of Early Port Macquarie. Sydney: Angus & Robertson (This edition 1981) Bradley, Joan. 1988. Bringing Back the Bush; the Bradley method of bush regeneration. (Edited by Joan Larking, Audrey Lenning & Jean Walker). Sydney: Lansdowne Press. Braithewaite, Norman, & Beard, Harold. 1978. Pioneering in The Bellinger Valley. Bellingen, NSW: Bellinger Valley Historical Society. Briggs, Sue V. 2001. Linking ecological scales and institutional frameworks for landscape rehabilitation. Ecological Management & Restoration 2, 28-35  2003. Command and control in natural resource management: Revisiting Holling and Metcalfe. Ecological Management & Restoration 4, 161-62

315

Booth, B.D. & Larson, D.W., 1999. Impact of language, history and choice of system on the study of assembly rules. In Weiher, Evan, & Keddy, Paul. (eds) 1999. Ecological Assembly Rules: Perspectives, advances, retreats. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 206229. Bonyhady, Tim. 2000. The Colonial Earth. Melbourne: The Miegunyah Press, Melbourne University Press. Bradstock, R.A., Auld, T.D., Keith, D.A., Kingsford, R. T., Lunney, D., Sivetsen, D. P. 1995. Conserving Biodiversity: threats and solutions. Chipping Norton, NSW: Surrey Beatty & Sons (with NSW National Parks & Wildlife Service) Brown, Bob. 1984. Wilderness versus Hydro-Electricity in South West Tasmania. In Mosley, J.G. & Messer, J. (eds) 1984. Fighting For Wilderness; Papers from the Australian Conservation Foundation’s Third National Wilderness Conference, 1983. Melbourne: Fontana Books & The Australian Conservation Foundation. Cody, Martin L. & Diamond, Jared M. (eds.) 1975. Ecology and Evolution of Communities. Cambridge, Massachusetts.: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press. Cohen, Timothy J. 2003. Late Holocene Floodplain Processes and PostEuropean Channel Dynamics in a Partly Confined Valley of New South Wales.Wollongong, NSW: School of Geosciences, University of Wollongong. Cribb, A. B. & J. W. 1976. Wild Food in Australia. Sydney: Fontana Collins Australia. Curtis, David. 2003. The arts and restoration: A fertile partnership? Ecological Management & Restoration 4 (3), 163-169. Debord, Guy. 1983. Society of the Spectacle. Detroit: Black & Red. Dennett, Daniel C. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books. Dessaix, Robert, (ed.) 2004. The Best Australian Essays, 2004, Melbourne: Black Inc. Diamond, J.M. 1975. Assembly of species communities. In Cody, M.L. & Diamond, J.M. (eds.) 1975. Ecology and Evolution of Communities. pp. 342-444. Cambridge Ma.: Harvard University Press Durgnat, Raymond. 1976. Durgnat on Film. London: Faber & Faber Eby, Peggy. 1995. The Biology and Management of Flying Foxes in N.S.W. NPWS Species Management Report 18. Hurstville: NSW National Parks & Wildlife Service. Eldershaw, Finney 1854. Australia as It Really Is, in its life, scenery and adventure: with the character, habits, and customs of its aboriginal inhabitants, and the prospects and extent of its gold fields; by a resident and eye-witness of the facts recorded. London: Darton & Co. Elliot, Roger (ed.) 1995. Environmental Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 316

Elliot, Roger. 1995 Faking Nature. In Elliot, Roger (ed.) 1995. Environmental Ethics, pp76-88. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Evans, D. Warrington (ed.), 1969. Compiled from Hawkesworth, John (ed) (1773) An Account of a Voyage Round the World with a Full Account of the Voyage of the Endeavour in the Year MDCCLXX along the East coast of Australia by Lieutenant James Cook Commander of his Majesty’s Bark Endeavour. Brisbane: W.R. Smith & Paterson. Fensham, R. J., Fairfax R. J., & Cannell (1994) The invasion of Lantana camara L. in Forty Mile Scrub National Park, north Queensland. In Australian Journal of Ecology 19, 297-305. Finlayson, Max 2003. Ecosystem assessment: links between science and community – the common ground? Ecological Management & Restoration 4 (1) Flannery, Timothy. 1994. The Future Eaters: An ecological history of the Australasian lands & peoples. Sydney: Reed New Holland Books. Florence, R.G. 1996. Ecology & Silviculture of Eucalypt Forest. Collingwood, Victoria: CSIRO Publishing Floyd, A.G. 1962. Investigations into the Natural Regeneration of Blackbutt— E. pilularis. Research Note No. 10. Forestry Commission of N.S.W.  1990. Australian Rainforests in NSW. Chipping Norton: Surrey and Beatty & Sons, and NPWS.  1991. Natural Regeneration of Rainforest In NSW. In Rainforest Remnants: Proceedings of a Workshop on Rainforest Rehabilitation held at the North Coast Agricultural Institute, 17-18th November, 1988. Ed. Stephen Phillips, Lismore, NSW: NSW National Parks & Wildlife Service, 20-25. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 2001. Truth and Method. (Second, revised edition) (trans. Joel Weinsheimer & Donal G. Marshall) London: Sheed & Ward. Gentle, C. B. & Duggin, J. A. 1997. Lantana camara L. invasions in dry rainforestopen forest ecotones: The role of disturbances associated with fire and cattle grazing. In Australian Journal of Ecology 22, 298-306 Giddens, Anthony, 1990 The Consequences of Modernity. Oxford: Polity Press. Goethe, Johann Wolgang von 1998 Maxims and Reflections (trans. Elizabeth Stopp). Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin. Gould, Stephen Jay. 1987. The Panda’s Thumb: More Reflections in Natural History Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin (1st published 1980) Gould, S.J. & Lewontin, R.C. 1978. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist program. In Conceptual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, 2nd ed., edited by E. Sober. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (1994) 317

Gow, Graeme. 1989. The Complete Guide to Australian Snakes. North Ryde, NSW: Angus & Robertson. Gray, Robert. 1996. Lineations: Poems and Drawings. Potts Point, Australia. Duffy & Snellgrove. Hay, Ashley. 2002. Gum: the story of eucalypts and their champions. Sydney: Duffy & Snellgrove. Hegel, G.F.W. 1975. Aesthetics (trans T. M. Knox) Oxford: Oxford University Press Hickey, Dave. 1997. Air Guitar, Los Angeles: Art Issues Press Higgs, Eric. 2003. Nature by Design: People, Natural Process, and Ecological Design. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press Hill, Robert S. 1994. History of the Australian Vegetation: Cretaceous to recent.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hill, Robert S. 1994. The history of selected Australian taxa. In Hill, Robert S. 1994. History of the Australian Vegetation: Cretaceous to recent. 390-419. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hodgkinson, Clement. 1845. Australia from Moreton Bay to Port Macquarie; with Descriptions of the Natives, their Manners and Customs; the Geology, Natural Productions, Fertility, and Resources of that Region; first Explored and Surveyed by order of the Colonial Government. London: T. & W. Boone. Hopkins, M. S. 1981. Disturbance and change in rainforests and the resulting problems of functional classification. In: Vegetation Classification in Australia. A. N. Gillison and D. J. Anderson (Eds), 42-52. Canberra: ANU Press. Horton, David. 2000. Pure State of Nature: Sacred cows, destructive myths and the environment. St Leonards: Allen & Unwin. Hull, David. 1988. Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Husserl, Edmund. 1954. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy. (Trans. David Carr. Evanston: Northwestern Universoty Press, 1970) Jordan, William R., Gilpin, Michael E., & Aber, John D., (eds). 1987. Restoration Ecology: A Synthetic Approach to Ecological Research. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Kant, Immanuel. 1790. The Critique of Judgement (trans. James Creed Meredith) http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/critique-of-judgment.txt Kirkpatrick, J.B. 1997 The future of Australian plant ecology – incisively idiographic or nebulously nomothetic. In Klomp, Nicholas & Lunt, Ian (editors). 1997. Frontiers in Ecology: building the links. Oxford: Elsevier Science. Klomp, Nicholas & Lunt, Ian (editors). 1997. Frontiers in Ecology: building the links. Oxford: Elsevier Science.

318

Kraus, Karl. 2001. Dicta and Contradicta. (trans. Jonathan McVity). Urbana & Chicago: University of Illinois Press. Ladiges, Pauline. 1997. Phylogenetic history & classification of eucalypts. In Williams, Jann E., & Woinarski, John C. Z. (eds) 1997 Eucalypt Ecology: Individuals to Ecosystems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 16-29. Lake, P.S. 2001. On the maturing of restoration: linking ecological research and restoration. Ecological Management & Restoration 2, 110-115). Lakatos, Imré. 1970. The methodology of scientific research programmes. In Lakatos, I. & Mulgrave, A. (eds). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 91-96. Lange, R.T. 1982. Australian Tertiary vegetation: Evidence and interpretation. In Smith, J.M.B. (ed.) 1982. The History of Australasian Vegetation. Sydney: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 44-89. Langton, Marcia. 1998. Burning Questions: Emerging Environmental Issues for Indigenous Natural & Cultural Resource Management. Darwin: Northern Territory University. Law, B. Mackowski, C. Schoer, L. & Tweedie, T. 2000. ‘Flowering phenology of myrtaceous trees and their relations to climatic, environmental and disturbance variables in northern New South Wales.’ Austral Ecology (2000) 25, 160-178. Leopold, Aldo. 1948. A Sand County Almanac,and sketches here and there. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (1978) Lindblum, Charles E. 1959. The ‘Science’ of Muddling Through. In Theodoulou, Stell Z. & Cahn, Matthew A. 1987. Public Policy: The Essential Readings. Eaglewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Lines, William J. 1998. A Long Walk in the Australian Bush. Sydney: University of NSW Press.  2003. Correspondence in Quarterly Essay 9. Edited by Peter Craven. Melbourne: Black Inc, 91-96. Low, Tim. 1999. Feral Future: The Untold story of Australia’s Exotic Invaders. Ringwood Victoria: Viking, Penquin Books  2002. The New Nature: winners and losers in wild Australia. Camberwell, Victoria, Australia: Viking (Penquin Books) Luhmann, Niklas 1984. Soziale Systeme:Grundriss einer allgemein Theorie (Social Systems) (Trans. John Bednarz, Jr., with Dirk Baeker [Stanford, California: Stanford University Press. 1995])  1986. Ecological Communication. (Trans John Bednarz, Jr, Oxford: Polity Press, Basil Blackwell, 1989)  1995. Die Kunst der Gesellschaft Frankfurt-am-Main: Suhrkamp Verlag (Art as a Social System, translated by Eva M. Knodt, Stanford California: Stanford University Press, 2000) Lunny, Daniel & Moon, Chris. 1994. Conserving the Main Flying Fox Camps: A History of Flying Foxes, their habitat & their camps on the North

319

Coast of NSW with a view to planning their management. Hurstville: NSW National Parks & Wildlife Service. Lunt, Ian. 2001. Enhancing the links between restoration ecology and ecological restoration. Ecological Management & Restoration 2, 3-4. McDonald T, Wale K, & Bear V (2002) Restoring Blue Gum High Forest: lessons from Sheldon Forest. Ecological Management & Restoration 3 (1), 15-27. Maiden, J.H. 1894. The Dorrigo Forest Reserve. Sydney: Department of Agriculture NSW. (Reprinted from The Agricultural Gazette. April & September, 1894) Mc Intosh, R.P. 1985. The Background of Ecology: Concept and Theory. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press. Mooney, Scott D., Radford, Kate L., Hancock, Gary 2001. Clues to the ‘burning question’: Pre-European fire in the Sydney coastal region from sedimentary charcoal and palynology. Ecological Management & Restoration 2 (3), 203-212. Mosley, J.G. & Messer, J. (eds) 1984. Fighting For Wilderness; Papers from the Australian Conservation Foundation’s Third National Wilderness Conference, 1983. Melbourne: Fontana Books & The Australian Conservation Foundation. Murray, Les. 1997. A Working Forest: selected prose. Sydney: Duffy and Snellgrove Orians, Gordon H. & Judith H. Heerwagan 1992. Evolved Responses to Landscape. In: Barkow, Jerome H., Cosmides, Leda & Tooby, John (eds.) 1992 The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology & the Generation of Culture. 555-580. New York: Oxford University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders 1931-1958. Collected Papers. (Vol. II) Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Peters, R. H. 1991. A Critique for Ecology. Cambridge: Cambridge Univsersity Press Petrarch, The Ascent of Mont Ventoux: A Letter to Dionisio da Borgo San Sepolcro, in Peter Halsell (ed.) Internet Medieval Source Book: http://www.fordham.edu/halsell/source/petrarch-ventoux.html Pimm, Stuart. 1991. The Balance of Nature? Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ponder, Warwick. 1997. Reaching for the sky—the tallest tree in NSW. www.forest.nsw.gov.au/bush/aug97/ stories/9.asp Pyne, Stephen J. 1991. Burning Bush: A Fire History of Australia. New York: Henry Holt and Company Quine, W.V.O. 1969. Epistemology naturalised. In Ontological Relativity & other essays. New York & London: Columbia University Press. Rolls, Eric. 1981. A Million Wild Acres: Ringwood, Victoria: Penguin (1984) Rosenberg, Alexander. 1994. Instrumental Biology or The Disunity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press

320

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1782. Le Reveries du promeneur solitaire. ( Reveries of the Solitary Walker, trans. Peter France, Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1979) Ryan, D. G., Ryan, J. E. & Starr, B. J. 1995. The Australian Landscapeobservations of explorers and early settlers Wagga Wagga NSW: Murrumbidgee Catchment Management Committee Ryan. J. S. 1988 The Land of Ulitarra: Early Records of the Aborigines of the Mid-North Coast of New South Wales Together with various Vocabularies. Revised Edition. Lismore NSW: New South Wales Department of Education, North Coast Regional Office. Seddon, George. 1997. Landprints: Reflections on place and landscape. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Paperback edition 1998) Singh, G. 1982. Environmental upheavel: Vegetation of Australasia during the Quaternary. In Smith, J.M.B. (ed.) 1982. The History of Australasian Vegetation. Sydney: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 90-108. Solnit, Rebecca. 2000. Wanderlust: a history of walking. New York: Viking Penguin. Smith, J.M.B. (ed.) 1982. The History of Australasian Vegetation. Sydney: McGraw-Hill Book Company. Sperber, Dan. 1996 Explaining Culture: a naturalistic approach. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Sterelny, Kim & Griffiths, Paul. 1999. Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology. Chicago: University of Chicago. Swain, E.H.F. 1912. The Forests of the Bellinger River. Bulletin No. 5. Department of Forestry. N.S.W. Theodoulou, Stell Z. & Cahn, Matthew A. 1987. Public Policy: The Essential Readings. Eaglewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Thomas, Sarah E. & Ellison, Carol A. 2000. A Century of Classical Biological Control of Lantana camara: Can Pathogens Make a Significant Difference? In Neal R. Spencer [ed.]. Proceedings of the X International Symposium on Biological Control of Weeds, 4-14 July 1999, Montana State University, Bozeman, Montana USA (pp. 97104).http://www.ppru.cornell.edu/weeds/Symposium/ proceed/01pg97.pdf Tidemann, Christopher R. 2003 Displacement of a flying-fox camp using sound. Ecological Management and Restoration 4, 224-6 Timms, Peter. 2001. Making Nature: Six Walks in the Bush. Crows Nest, Australia: Allen & Unwin  2004. Love, Death and Wilderness Photography. In Dessaix, Robert, (ed.) The Best Australian Essays, 2004, Melbourne: Black Inc. (152161) Turner, Frederick. 1987. The self-effacing art: restorartion as imitation of nature. In Jordan, William R., Gilpin, Michael E., & Aber, John D., (eds) 1987 Restoration Ecology: A Synthetic Approach to Ecological Research. Pp.47-50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 321

Underwood, A. J. 1997. Experiments in Ecology: Their logical design & interpretation using analysis of variance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Van Loon, A.P. 1966. Investigations in Regenerating the Tallowwood—Blue Gum Forest Type. Research Note No. 19. Forestry commission of N.S.W. Voltaire, Francois Marie Arouet de, 1733. Letter Concerning the English Nation. New York, NY: Burt Franklin Reprints (1974). Walker, Donald. 1990. ‘Directions and Rates of Tropical Rainforest Processes.’ In Australian Tropical Rainforests: Science – Value - Meaning. (Eds L. J. Webb & J. Kikkawa) Melbourne: C.S.I.R.O. Wallace, Ken H. 2003. ‘Confusing means with ends: a manager’s reflection on experience in agricultural landscapes in Western Australia.’ Ecological Management and Restoration 4 (1), 23 Weiher, Evan, & Keddy, Paul. (eds) 1999. Ecological Assembly Rules: Perspectives, advances, retreats. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wilkins, J. S. 1998. ‘What’s in a Meme? Reflections from the perspective of the history and philosophy of evolutionary biology.’ Journal of MemeticsEvolutionary Models of Information Transmission 2. http://www.cpm.mmu.ac.uk/jom-emit/1999/vol2/wilkins_js.html Williams, George 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Williams, Kathryn, & Carey, John 2001. Perception of native grassland in southeastern Australia, Ecological Management and Restoration 2, 2, 139-144 Williams, Jann E., & Woinarski, John C. Z. (eds). 1997. Eucalypt Ecology: Individuals to Ecosystems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Williams, Raymond. 1973. The City and The Country. London: The Hogarth Press (1985) Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. (Trans. C.K. Ogden) London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd. (1981) Yibarbuk, Dean. 1998. Notes on traditional use of fire on Upper Cadell River. In Langton, Marcia, 1998. Burning Questions: Emerging Environmental Issues for Indigenous Natural & Cultural Resource Management. Darwin: Northern Territory University.

322

Index Abee, Edward (writer, naturalist), 246, 276 Adorno, Theodor (philosopher), 231, 244, 266, 288 aesthetic theory, predicament of, 255-256, 282, Algomerra Creek, 22 angophora (Angophora spp), 42, 46, 48, 49, 58, 60 smooth coast (A. costata), 33, 34, 36, 38, 41, 49, 58 Anthony, Doug (politician), 162 Aragon, Louis, 189 Araucaria spp., 50, 60, 200-203 bunya pine (A bidwillii), 60, 200-203 hoop pine (A. cunninghamii), 17, 50, 60, 73, 246 Aristotle (philosopher), 138, 155, 160, 161, 268, 273, 278, 289 Attenborough, David (television producer), 193 Augustine (philospher, theologian), 236239 azalea, 6, 267 Bacon, Francis (essayist, philosopher), 137-138, 155 environmentalist criticism of, 159-161 Bail, Murray (novelist), 43 bandicoot northern brown, 16, 71, 93, 305, 311, 312 story of, 221 Banks, Joseph (botanist), 48-49 banksia, 121, 200, 300 coast, 17, 52 bass, eastern, 9, 119 Bazin, André (film theorist), 192 bean, black (Castanospermum australe), 6, 65, 215, bean, red (Dysoxylum Muelleri), 19, 65, 67, 95, 96, 98, 100, 101, 244 beauty, natural, 240, 256, 258-260, 262, 266-271, 273-277, 283, 286, 288 and ethics, 273-274, evolution of, 269273 as irrational, 262, 266 precedence of natural over artificial, 267 relation to artistic beauty, 274-277, 287, 288 relation to narrative art, 278 relation to science, 251, 262-263 bee, native social (Trigona carbonaria), 52

323

beech, white (Gmelina leichhardtii), 67, 91, 95, 96, 100 Bellengen Billy (guide to Bellinger Valley), 26 Bellingen Island, 3-10, 19, 20, 250, 293313 changes and management, 5-7 flying foxes on, 7, 59, 298-301 geomorphology of, 4 latent social functions of, 132 names for, 3, 9 original rainforest of, 5 restoration of, 293-313 Bellingen township, 24, 33, 60, 74, 75, 299, 302 naming of, 4 relation to river, 7 Shire, 9, 303 Bellinger (Balliijir) River (see Bellinger Valley), 1-30, 33 geomorphology of, 4, 8-9 name of, 4 Bellinger Valley, 1-30, 99, 117, 119, 120, 124, 208, 210, 229, 236, 246, 249, 280, 293, 302 area of, 19 feral fruits of, 201 fire in, 220-223 geology of ridges, 33-34 paintings of, 80, 188 pasture weeds of, 213 as sickness country, 26 suitability for agriculture 23, 74 vegetation of 33-83 view of, 231, 248, 263 Benjamin, Walter (writer), 24, 102, 250, 251 Bentham, George (botanist), 47-48 Big Scrub (Richmond Valley), 132 biology, philosophy of, 140-141 Birigundah, 11, 24, Birmingham, John (writer), 226, 250 Bischoff, Joseph (photographer), 186 bitou bush (Chysanthemoides monilifera), 121, 122 bloodwood (Corymbia spp.), 33, 54, 79, 300, cadaghi (C. torreliana), 51 flowers & fruits of, 57-58, 60 lemon-scented gum (C. citriodora), 6

northern spotted gum (C. variegata), 52 pink (C. intermedia) 34, 35, 38, 42, 59, 93 red (C. gummifera), 41, 48, 59, 223, relation to eucalypts & angophoras, 4649 Blue Mountains, 23, 77, 88, 267 Boat Harbour, 4 bolly gum ,white, 38, 65 booyong (Heritiera spp.) black (H. actinophylla), 65, 119, 246, 248 white (H. trifoliolate), 5, 19, 65, 67, 149, 246, 308, 309, 312 Boswell, Annabella (19th century diarist), 87 bottlebrush, red, 14, 200 Bowerbirds, 20, 37, 252 regent, 38, 105, 248 satin, 105 Boyd, Arthur (painter), 80 Boyle, Robert (chemist), 138 Bradley, Joan & Eileen (bush regenerators), 296-297 Method, 297 Brooks, Sue (filmmaker), 191 Brown, Bob (politician), 186, Browne, Thomas (17th century natural philosopher & essayist), 152, 295 brushbox, 33, 34, 36 Bundagen, 17, 226 Burke, Edmund (aesthetic theorist), 18, 238, 259 bush tucker, 200-203 Bush, The as national symbol, 196-199, 261 words for, 197 butcherbird, pied, 105 Buvelot, Louis (painter), 78 Campbell, ‘Beaky’ (photographer), 186 camphor laurel (Cinnamomum camphora), 6, 7, 15, 20, 71, 73-76, 122, 180, 206, 214-215, 219 caper, brush (Capparis aborea), 92 carabeen in highland subtropical rainforest 247252 red (Geissois benthamiana) 5 yellow (Sloania woolsii), 5, 19, 65 casuarina (Casuarina spp. Allocasuarina spp.) diversification of species, 61 oak, black (Allocasuarina littoralis), 52, 72,

324

oak, forest (Allocasuarina torulosa), 36, 39, 61, 66, 71, 85, 99, 100, 105, oak, river (Casuarina cunninhamiana), 6, 7, 8, 61, 215, ecology and weedy reputation of, 21, wet sclerophyll, 52 oak, swamp, (C. glauca), 21, 35, 52, 61, 71, 212 catbird, green, 68, cedar pencil, (Polyscias murrayi), 64, 97, 98, 101 red (Toona ciliata), 4, 5, 12, 13, 19, 20, 23, 27, 64, 65, 67, 72, 91, 96, 98101, 249, 306 tip moth, 20 white (Melia azedarach var. australasica), 67, 97, 98 celtis, Chinese (Celtis sinensis), 6, 7 cheese tree (Glochidion ferdinandii), 15, 67, 85, 92 Christmas, 38, 223-224 cinema, Australian landscape in, 191-192 cinnamomum, native (Oliver’s sassafras, Cinnamomum oliveri), 39 Clarence River, 16, 132, 300 Clements, F.E. (ecologist), 150 coachwood (Ceratopetalum apetalum), 22, 67, 246, 263 coast, 120-121 cockatoo glossy-black, 66, 105 yellow-tailed, 59, 105 cockspur (Maclura cochinchinensis), 6, 67, 88, 99, 151, 215 coffee (Coffea arabica), 6, 7, drink, 248, 250, 273, 274 Coffs Harbour, 17, 74, 250, 302, breakwall, 17 community, ecological assembly rules for, 151-153 ecological concept of, 35, 62, 63, 98, 139, 143-144, 146-154, 164, 207, 213, 216, 308, 311 function (see function, ecosystem) succession, 64-65, 71, 75, 91, 96, 97, 147, 149-150, 152, 157, 158, 201, 212, 213, 219, 225, 228, 262, 284, 285, 312 Conroy, Joseph (painter), 80 Cook, James (navigator) fire, comments on, 221 Gumbaynggirr country, comments on, 13, 17

vegetation, comments on 40 Cook, Patrick (cartoonist), 103 Coowoongambah, 24 coral pea (Kennedia rubicunda), 17 Coramba, Mt, 13 Coramba, Nature Reserve, 132, Mt., 13 Corot, Jean-Baptiste (painter), 244 Corambirra Headland, 17 Crown Lands Act, 4 Cudgerie (Flindersia schottiana), 19, 65, 67, 91, 96, 98, 101 culture, nature of, 126-134, Curtis, David (restoration theorist), 284 cypress, southern (Callitris spp.) 51 Port Jackson (C. rhomboidea), 52 D’harawal, 49, 222 Darkies Point (see Nguloongeer) Darkwood, 14, 74 Darwin, Charles (biologist), 158, 269 evolution and ecology, 141-144 natural selection, 127-129 opinion of the bush, 40, 88 species concept of, 149 Dawkins. Richard (evolutionary biologist), 128 de Heer, Rolf (filmmaker), 192 Debord, Guy (cultural critic), 185, 282 Dennett, Daniel (philosopher), 128 Descartes, René (philosopher), 137-138 Diamond, Jared (ecologist), 151, 152, 153 Dibbs Head, 13 Dickinson, Emily (poet), 265 Diehappy, 13, 234, 236 dollar bird, 105, 148 Dombrovskis, Peter (photographer), 186, 189, 190 Dorrigo (Dundurriga) Aboriginal people of, 26 Don, 13 Eastern, 37, 50, 203, 246 Mountain, 4, 119 National Park, 246-250, 263 Plateau 13, 26, 39, 41, 49, 50, 52, 60, 70, 72, 75, 246, plum (Endiandra discolor), 65 township, 72 dove, bar shouldered, 113 dragon angle-headed, 93 water, 119, 274 Dunghutti, 14, 18, 26-29, 205 hostilities against, 27-30 Durgnat, Raymond (film critic) 191 eagle, sea, 106

325

echidna, 71, 110, 161, 162 Eco, Umberto (semiotician), 261 ecocentrism, 209 ecological restoration & management, 9, 23, 95, 98, 121-123, 130, 133-134, 147, 150, 157, 159, 161-165, 168, 171184, 227, 280-289, 293-313 adaptive, 164, 165, 184, 307-308 ecology applied, 158-166 biological origin of ecology’s interests, 148-149 deep, 209 folk, 148, 151, 180 historical relation to evolution, 142-144 holistic vs reductionist, 144-145 as instrumental science, 145-46, 155157, 159 philosophy of, 141-166 pop, 155, 180, 181, 192 problem of defining its objects, 142149 pure, 157-158 as redressing instrumental science, 159 relation to environmentalism, 159-162 relation to natural history, 62, 143, 146-147, 163-164 and restoration, 161-166 ecosystem, 76, 95, 98, 111, 132, 181, 183, 207, 210, 216, 219 concept of, 104-105, 143-156, 158, 162, 163 services, 112, 118, 126, 167, 168, 207, 210, 211-213, 215, 255, 257 ecotone, 69, 95 eel, long-finned, 8, 119, 249 El Niño, 57, 67 Eldershaw, Finney (squatter, witness to Aboriginal massacre), 27-30 Elliot, Roger (environmental philosopher), 163 Elton, C.S. (ecologist), 151 Endeavour, 13, 48, 221 Enlightenment, The, 12, 18, 268-269, 273274 environmentalism, 80, 123, 167, 168, , 175, 179, 185, 204-208, 296, 299 apocalyptic, 204-205 philosophy of, 207-208, scepticism of, 205-207 selling, 210 uncompleted project of, 167 wariness of aesthetics of, 256-257

epistemology (theory of knowledge), 140, 141, 148, eucalypts (gums: Eucalyptus spp. Angophora spp., Corymbia spp.) die-back, 41 diversification of species, 61 ecology and evolution 33-83 evolutionary relation to humans, 61 flower arrangement, 44-46, 59 flowering and fruiting, 57-60 forest management of, 16-17, identification & taxonomy, 42-50 lignotuber of, 48, 53-55, 70, 81 naming of, 48-49 regeneration of, 53-56 Eucalyptus spp. blackbutt (E. pilularis), 16, 17, 18, 34, 41, 45, 46, 58, 59, 61, 63, 70, 71, 79, 85, 102, 265, fire response, 5354, flowering, 57, forestry, 35-37 Dorrigo white gum (E. dorrigoensis), 52 Dunn’s white gum (E. dunnii), 37 E. deglupta, 42 flooded gum (E. grandis), 17, 34-35, 41, 42, 45, 49, 51, 56, 58, 61, 63, 74, 88, 93, 94, 95, 100.,101, 214, fruits, 53, flowering, 57, response to fire, 57, tallest tree in NSW, 63, forest red gum (E. tereticornis), 35, 41, 45, 57, 59, 70, 71, 78, 208, 210, 300, river, 208 grey gum (E. propinqua), 34, 36, 46, 71, 85, 102, flowering, 57 ironbark (E. ancophila, & E. siderophloia), 34, 35, 43, 46, 56, 59 messmate (E. obliqua), 41, 43, 49, 50, 246 red mahogany (E. resinifera), 16, 43 snow gum (E. pauciflora), 41, 241 stringybark, 41, 42, 49, 51, 77 swamp mahogany (E. robusta), 17, 35, 41, 56, 59, flowering, 57 Sydney blue gum (E. saligna), 34-35, 41, 43-45, 55, 56, 66, 77, 85, 88, 105, 113, 120, 214, fruits, 53, flowering, 57, fire response, 53, 59, tallowwood (E. microcorys), 16, 17, 33-39, 41, 43, 49, 53-59, 62, 64, 85, 88, 93, 95, 99, 101, 105, 113, 120, 207, 214, 265, response to fire, 66, 67, flowers, 35, 57, regeneration, 59, koala food, 71, painters of, 80, stringybark, 41, 42, 49, 51, 77

326

white box (E. albens), 41, 208 white gum (E. nobilis), 41, 43, 63, 72, 246 white mahogany (E. acmenoides), 16, 34-36, 43, 45-46, 53, 56, 66, 102, flowering, 57, soil preference, 59, white-topped box (E. quadrangulata), 47, Farley, Rick (lobbyist), 305 Fernmount, 4 ferns, 5, 15, 23, 30, 65, 66, 70, 72, 73, 74, 85, 92, 97, 248, 262, 301, 308, 311 bracken (Pteridium esculentum), 65, 66, 86, 97, 214 climbing (Microsorum spp., Arthropteris spp.), 65 downy ground (Hypolepis glandulifer), 17, 97 felt (Pyrrosia spp.), 50 giant maidenhair (Adiantum formosum), 306 gristle (Blechnum cartilagineum), 17, 265 lacy ground (Dennstaedtia davallioides), 311 rasp (Doodia aspera), 66, 81, 265 rough ground (Hypolepis muelleri), 97, 98, 100, 107, 201 shield (Lastreopsis spp.), 66, 92, 101, 249, 265 tree (Cyathea spp., Dicksonia spp.), 30, 66, 79, 88, 93, 100 umbrella (Pteris tremula), 97 fig (Ficus spp.) associated fauna, 20-21 black (F. watkinsiana), 20 deciduous (F. superba), 20 fruit, 20-21 manner of growth 20-21 Moreton Bay (F. macrophylla), 20 Port Jackson (rusty, F. rubiginosa), Small-leaved (F. obliqua), 20 strangler (Ficus spp.), 5, 6 fire, 14, 15, 16, 17, 25, 76, 79, 81, 82, 83, 101, 110, 118, 121, 182, 194, 198, 259, 280 fighters, 121, 223, 224 adaptation to, 59 in eucalypt ecology and evolution, 3573 as cultural problematic, 25, 123, 130, 185, 218 antagonism about, 224-228, 309 pristine form of, 220-222

as media event, 222-224, as agricultural technology, 6, 7, 36, 76 Aboriginal use, 15, 17, 69-72, 118 campfire, 16, 26, 28 fireflies (Atyphella sp.), 14, 112, 119 Flannery, Tim (biologist), 15, 198, 199, 217, 218 Floyd, Alex (botanist), 65, 91, 95 flying foxes, grey-headed (fruit bats), 3, 6, 7, 9, 20, 31, 34, 38, 45, 56, 59, 6466,75, 248, 305-313 camp location, 133-134 food of, 57 as pollinators, 52 as social problem, 298-303, flying foxes, little red, 300 foambark (Jager pseudorhus), 39, 67, 85 Forestry Commission of NSW, 17 frangipani, native (Hymenosporum flavum), 95-98 function in aesthetics, 211, 216, 256-257, 266, 268, 269, 283-284, 287, 290 confusion about, 25, 81, 162, 204, 210213, 216, 257, 283-284, 287, 290, 298 of cultural forms, 118, 122, 122, 123, 128, 132-134, 153, 169, 187, 192, 196, 203, 212-213, 222, 233, 236, 237, 239, 247, 280 in division of landscape, 25, 38, 119, 120. 123, 183, 287 in ecological descriptions, 146, 151, 153 in ecosystem mamagement, 24, 122, 123, 152, 162, 211-213, 256, 257, 283 of ecosystems and ecological communities, 23, 56, 90, 146, 151153, 211-213, 216, 219, 248, 256, 266, 283 in functionalist reason, 25, 81, 162, 204, 210-213, 216, 257, 283-284, 287, 290, 298, of managerial and bureaucratic practices, 170, 172, 173, 175 of organism features, 47, 53, 56, 110, 127, 131, 139, 146, 226, 252, 309 relation to form in evolution, 131-134, 226, 311 future denaturing of, 207 history of, 203-204, 207 optimism/pessimism about, 207

327

Gadamer, Hans-Georg (philosopher), 287 gecko, northern leaf-tail, 103-105, 108, 111, 114 geebung (Persoonia sp.), 109, 200 gerygones (warblers), brown, 35, 113, 148 Giddens, Anthony (sociologist), 238, 273 gliders, 34, 56, 63, 71 greater, 17 sugar, 17, 105 yellow-bellied, 17, Glover, John (painter), 77, 261, 264 glyphosate, herbicide, 296 goanna, tree (lace monitor, Varanus, varius), 67, 71, 93, 105-107, 161, 162, 218, 232 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von (writer), 102, 188, 244, 287 Gondwana, 14, 219 Goobergooberyam, 13, goshawk, grey, 106 Gould, Stephen Jay (evolutionary biologist), 140, 149 Grafton, 4, 299 grape, native, (Cissus antarctica & C. hypoglauca), 15, 65, 66, 67-68, 83, 91 grass, 3, 7, 8, 19, 21, 22, 24, 72, 77 agricultural, 71, 73, 75, 120, 214, 218, 246 barbwire (Cymbopogon refractus), 92, 250, 265 basket (Oplismenus spp.), 92, 265 blady (Imperator cylindrica), 16, 66, 70, 214, 220, 228 burrgrass, hillside (Cenchrus caliculatus), 215 fate of native grasses, 74 fine-flowered finger (Digitaria parviflora), 92 fondness for, 17-18, 270 grassy forest, 14, 15-18, 21-22, 23, 39, 58, 59, 65, 66, 69, 70 grassy headlands, 121 grassy plains, 72 kangaroo (Themeda australis), 17, 70 kikuyu (Pennisetum clandestinum), 213 palm (Setaria indica), 7 panic (Panicum spp.), 92, 265 Parramatta (Sporobolus indicus), 213 paspalum (Paspalum dilatatum, 6, 73, 75, 213-214 paspalum, broad-leaved (Paspalum wettsteinii), 37, 75, 76, 94, 97, 101, 180, 213-215

Rhodes (Chloris gayana), 215 Whiskey (Andropogon virginicus), 75, 97 Gravel mining, 6, 8, 9 shoaling and scouring, 8 Gray, Robert (poet), 17, 35 Gray, Thomas (poet), 238 Great Dividing Range, 13, 40, 41, 60, 279, 280 Greens, 171, 206, 209, 225, 290 Griffiths, Paul (philosopher), 140 Gruner, Elioth (painter), 73 guava, native (Rhodomyrtus psidioides), 38, 67 yellow (Psidium guajava), 76, 210, 306 Guérard, Eugène von (painter), 13, 264 guioa (Guioa semiglauca), 39, 67, 92 Gumbaynggirr, 3, 5, 7, 11-21, 26, 30 Gumbaynggirr country, 3-32 European perceptions of, 26-27 hostilities against, 27 land management, 69-72 Haeckel, Ernst (biologist), 142 hawk, crested (Pacific baza) 105 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (philosopher) on aesthetic feeling, 258 on the precedence of art over nature, 275-277, 290 on reflexivity of modernity, 238, 281 Heidelberg painters, 78, 79, 189, 264 herbicide, 9, 96, 123, 157, 285, 296-297, 307, 309-310 Heysen, Hans (painter), 78, 79, 189, 264 Hickey, Dave (art critic), 276-277 Higgs, Eric (restoration theorist), 284-285 Hillyer (painter), Ted, 80, Hodgkinson, Clement, (government surveyor) 11-30 career of, 23 purpose of expedition, 14 reliability as witness, 14, 19 honeyeater Lewin’s, 35, 38, 68, 87, 94, 109-114, 161, 287 scarlet, 35, 105, 113 Horton, David (anthropologist), 217-218, 226-227 Hull, David (philosopher), 128 Humboldt, Willhelm von (linguist), 244, 250 icon, evolution of, 187

328

Irving, Helen (legal academic), 198-199 island biogeography, 3, 206-207, 215, 293 jacaranda, 6, 200, 215 jackwood, 38, 67, 58, 96, 101, 293 Johnson, Samuel (essayist, poet, lexicographer), 37, 231, 232, 238, 286 Kalang River, 19, 236 Kangaroo’s Deceit (Gunwinggu version), story of, 31 Kant, Immanuel (philosopher), 18 on the aesthetics of nature, 259-264, 266, 268-269, 271, 273, 287 on artificiality, 216, 282 on nature and Enlightenment, 273-275, 277-278 on objectivity, 232, on the sublime, 211, 237 Keating, Paul (politician), 13 Kelly, Ned, 196-197 Kempsey, 4 kinds, natural, 143-147, 149, 155 kingfisher, sacred, 105, 273 Kraus, Karl, (satirist), 290 L’Heritier de Brutelle, Charles Louis (botanist), 49 Lakatos, Imré (philosopher), 139 land mullet, 93, 105, 317 Landcare, 21, 114, 121, 167, 172, 184, 210, 256, 283, 296, 304, 305 landscape aesthetics, 270-272 in architecture and restoration ecology, 280, 289 architecture, 118, 296 art, 77-78, 80, 126, 132, 186-190, 264, 267 in cinema, 190-192 criticism of, 244 as document and memory, 24-26 functional division of, 38, 119, 120, 122, 233, 283, 287 national myth of, 196, 198 spatial scale of, 121, 181, 183, 184, 213, 228, 257, 283, 287, 304 uses of word, 197 Langton, Marcia (cultural theorist), 217218 lantana, 6, 7, 15, 17, 37, 68, 69, 249, 295 biological control of, 86, 180 early records of in northern NSW, 87 effect on forest structure and aesthetics, 88-89 effects on ecology and regeneration, 89-90

niche, 90, 151 popular acceptance of, 91, 122, 180, 208, 215 in eucalypt regrowth 73-76, 85-98, 214 removal of, 91-98, 100, 101, 201 structure and floristics, 85-86 uses, 87 Lawrence, Ray (filmmaker), 91 leech, 18, 22, 93, 213, 247, 263, 301, 305 lemon, bush (Citrus limona), 6, 76, 200, 201, 215 Leopold, Aldo (naturalist), 126, 231, 312 Lewin, John (painter), 77, 109, 264 Lewontin, Richard, (biologist), 140 lilly pilly lilly pilly (Acmena smithii)38, 67 blue (Syzygium oleosum), 38 purple (Syzygium crebrinerve), 38 weeping (Waterhousia floribunda), 5, 7, 8, 64, 306, 312 Lines, William (environmental writer), 159-160, 209-210 Linné, Carl von (Linnaeus, biologist), 48, 86 litter, 119-120 Livy (Roman historian), 234-235 lomandra (mat-rush, Lomandra spp.), 90 orange lomandra (L. spicata), 101, 265 river lomandra (Lomandra hystrix), 211, 212 Lomborg, Bjørn (environmental critic), 205-207 Low, Tim (ecologist), 89-91, 125, 217 Luhmann, Niklas (sociologist), 128, 144, 276 Lunt, Ian (ecologist), 307 Maclean, 132, flying foxes of, 299-302 Macleay River, 4, 11, 16, 22, 27, Macleay, Alexander (Colonial Secretary), 87 Macquarie Dictionary, 19 Macquarie, Lachlan, (Governor of NSW) 77 Madeira vine (Anredera cordifolia), 6-10, 150, 293-296 naming of, 293 removal of, 296, 303-313. structure and ecology, 294-295 magnolia, white (Magnolia grandiflora), 6 Maiden, J.H. (botanist), 47, 72, 74 maiden’s blush (Sloania australis), 5, 92 mangroves, 18, 212, 273 Manning River, 132 Marsh, G.P. (geographer), 256

329

Marvel, Andrew (poet), 263 Marx, Karl (philosopher), 68, 165, 215 massacre stories, generic form of, 30 mata, Brazilian, 293 Mayr, Ernst (evolutionary biologist), 148149 McGrath’s Hump, 13, 73, 249, 263 Megafauna, 15, 65, 192, 218 meme (replicable unit of social selection process), 128-129 science of (memetics) 128, 131, 219 Midjau-Midjau (storyteller), Jimmy, 31 Milton, John (poet), 37-39 mistakes, tendency to make, 123 mistletoe bird, 105 mistletoe, 35, 57, 215, 224, 252, 306 Montaigne, Michel de (essayist), 287 Moombil, Mt, 13, Moon, story of,17 Morris, Meaghan (cultural theorist), 89 Mountaintop, 14 Mueller, Ferdinand von (botanist), 47-48, 63, 78, mulberry, 6, 76 Murray, Les (poet), 15, 34, 35, 89, 122, 214, 261 murrogun (Cryptocarya microneaura), 38, 67, 88, 100 muskwood (Alangium villosum), 20, Muttonbird Island (Giidayn Mirral), 17 Myles, William (stockman), 11, 12 Namatjirra, Albert (painter), 78 Nambucca River, 14, 20, 22, 23, 27, 35, 119, 249 National Park Bongil Bongil, 16-17 Royal, 222-223 National Parks & Wildlife Service, 181, 187, 223, 240, 245, 303 natives (native plants), in horticulture, 199200 Natural Heritage Trust, 305 natural resource management bureaucratisation of, 170-174 language of, 168-169 managerial character of, 167-184 role of fire in, 219-230 role of pop ecology in 179-184 role of the community for, 175-179 sociology of, 173-174 standards or norms of, 211-219, nature concept of, 124, 125-126 criticism of, 243-253

as cultural, 126-127 as fact or norm, 280-281 gone wrong, 123 intrinsic value of, 209-210 as made, 264-265, 277, 279-291 of future, 122-123 poetics of 279-291, second, 117 selling of, 210-211 as unconscious cultural form, 117-124, 126 as unmade, 260, 275 Nelson, David (botanist), 49 Neruda, Pablo (poet), 200 Never Never River, 4, 14, 21, 124, 236, 282, 306 New England, 28, 41 Nguloongeer, massacre at, 27-30 niche, 90, 147, 171, 207, 211, 248 concept of, 151-152 Nietzsche, Friedrich (philosopher), 125, 131, 259, 276 nightshade, prickly, 93 Nolan, Sydney (painter), 196-197, 264 Nothofagus, sp (southern beech). 50 Antarctic (Nothofagus mooreii), 246 Noyce, Phil (filmmaker), 191 Nunguu Mirral, 18 Nymboida, 37, 52, Ockham, William of (philosopher), 137 Odum, Eugene (ecologist), 118 Olsen, Mike (ecologist), 90 Onus, Lynn (artist), 78 orange (Citrus aurantium), 6, 76, 200 organisms, as ecological objects, 62, 124, 127, 131, 138-144, 164, 175, 211, 216, 226, 268 osprey, 105, 161, 162 Pacific Highway, 16, 41, 250 Ocean, 12, 19, 48, 49, 99, 119, 243, 293 pademelon, red-necked, 16, 72, 245, 252 palm bangalow (Archontophoenix cunninghamina) 5,, 18, 19, 41, 58, 66, 88, 100 cabbage (Livistona australis), 88, 92, 221 lawyer (Calamus muelleri)5, 6, 16, 65, 67, 88, 100. 252 queen (progress, Arecastrum romanzoffianum), 7, 51, 120, 122, 219, 245, 246

330

walking-stick (Linospadix monostachya), 23, 252 paperbark, 45, 40 (Melaleuca spp. & Callistemon spp.) broad-leaved (Melaleuca quinquinervia), 17, 35, 38, 59, 71, 300 prickly (Melaleuca sp.), 41 Peirce, Charles Sanders (philosopher), 187 pepper vine, giant native (Piper novaehollandiae), 5, 65 pepperberry (Cryptocarya obovata), 5, 19, 65, 293 Perkins, Rachel (filmmaker), 192 persimmon (Diospyros kaki), 77 persimmon, wild (Diospyros pentamera), 5 Peters, Robert (ecologist), 142, 165 Petrarch (poet), ascent of Ventoux, 234239 photography glossy, 190 nature, 186-190 wilderness, 190 Picketts Hill (see Nunguu Mirral), 18, 99, 165 pigeon baldy (white-headed), 68 topknot, 21, 75, 113 wonga, 67, 68, 93, 114, 248, 250, 252, 263 Pine Creek, 17 pine Bunya (Araucaria bidwillii), 60, nuts as food, 200-203 hoop (Araucaria cunninhamiana), 17, 50, 60, 72, 246 Huon (Dacrydium franklinii), 50 plum (Podocarpus elatus), 50 Wollemi (Wollemia nobilis), 60 pitta, noisy, 93, 312 Plato (philosopher) 147, 149, 233, platypus, 8, 119 Podocarpus sp. 50 plum pine (Podocarpus elatus), 50 poetics of nature as comic, 286 concealment of, 282 as experience and practice (as nature and art), 287-288, 289-290 as fictive, 288-289 as guard against unconscious aesthetic judgement, 283-284, 285 and ideological or methodological antagonisms, 285

materials of 283 as mediation of facts and norms, 280282 natural history of, 290-291 and preconceptions of art’s limitation, 290 as process, 290 realism in, 285-286 as social restoration, 284 Point Lookout (Barangarnyatta), 40, 63, 236 Port Macquarie, 23, 87 Possingham, Hugh (ecologist), 198, 199 possums, 20, 56, 92, 101, 151 brushtail, 71 ringtail, 248, 263 pothos (Pothos longipes), 5, 119, 294 pristine, the significance of, 18, 23-24, 30-32 as standard or norm of environmental management, 215-219, 220-222 privet, 6, 7, 15, 72, 74-76, 101, 120, 123, 208, 214, 215, 219, 246 Pyne, Stephen (environmental historian), 217, 225, 230 Pythagoras (mystic, philosopher), 259 python, carpet, 22, 71, 93, 110, 263 quandong blue (blue fig, Elaeocarpus grandis), 65, 119 hard (Elaeocarpus obovatus), 35 Quine, Willard Van Ormand (philosopher), 141 quoll spotted, 17 eastern, 90 rainforest (closed forest), 3, 5, 8, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 20, 25, 33, 34, 35, 38, 39, 40, 42, 50, 52, 53, 55, 58, 60, 70, 74, 75, 76, 79, 81, 89, 90, 91, 95, 100, 117, 118, 120, 121, 123, 149, 157, 158, 180, 192, 197, 199, 205, 210, 214, 215, 219, 224, 225, 227, 228, 229, 262, 264, 265, 271, 282, 286 critical appraisal of, 245-252 history of Australian rainforests, 50, 60, 62 regeneration of, 64-65, 96-99 relation to wet sclerophyll forest, 52, 64-69, 71-72 remnants, 132-134, restoration of, 96-98, 293-313 raspberry (Rubus spp.)

331

giant (Rubus nebulosa), 15, 67, 85, 88, 95, 151 wild (Rubus rosifolius), 16 67, 91, 92, 97, 99, 211, as food, 201 red ash (Alphitonia exzcelsa), 15, 17, 64, 67, 74, 85, 91, 92, 93, 96, 97, 98, 101, 232 rhodamnia (see turpentine, scrub) riberry (Syzygium leuhmannii), 17, 38, 201, 246 roadside, 120 Robertson, John. (Premier of NSW), 3 robin, yellow, 91, 94, 109-113, 196, 210, 248, 287 Rolls, Eric (writer), 15, 217 Romanticism, 18, 19, 25, 30, 189, 239, 261, 269, 275 Roogatargah, 13 Rosenberg, Alexander (philosopher), 146 Rosewood River, 4, 124, 236, 246, 249, 257, rosewood hairy (Dysoxlum rufum), 92, rosewood (Dysoxylum fraserianum)4, 19, 20, 65, 72, 246, 247, 248, 249, 259 scentless (Synoum glandulosum), 85, 92 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (philosopher), 237, 260, 282 Russell, Bertrand (philosopher), 141 sandstone, 186, 222, 223 Hawkesbury, 41, 58 Sydney, 36, 200, 209, 2962, 297 sarsaparilla (Smilax spp.) prickly (Smilax australis), 15, 16, 17, 35, 67, 88, 245 sweet (Smilax glycophylla), 200 Schlegel, August Wilhelm (philosopher), 258 Schlegel, Friedrich (philosopher), 255 science disunity of, 139-140 empirical principle of, 139 philosophy of, 137-166 relation to art, 281, 286 as smokescreen for aesthetics, 284 validity of, 138-139 scrubwrens, 90, 113, 248 sedges, 8, 35, 65, 70, 71, 76, 92, 96, 100, 121 selection process

natural, 45, 50-53, 62-64, 117, 127131, 140, 142, 146, 149, 158, 164, 219, 226, 239, 269, 270-272 social, 117-118, 120, 127-134, 139, 183, 270-273 Sen, Ivan (filmmaker), 192 Shakespeare, William (dramatist, poet), 195, 277 shearwater, wedge-tailed, 17 shrike-thrush, grey, 35, 99, 111, 113, 248 Sidney, Philip (poet), 275 skinks blue-tongue, 105 Challenger’s, 308 common or garden 105, 107 land mullet, 105 Murray’s, 105, 108, 308 tree, 38, 105, 107, weasel, 105 snake green tree, 106, 110 marsh, 93 red-bellied black, 161, 162 small-eye, 110, 111 socketwood (Daphnandra sp. A), 5, 19, 67, 247 Socrates (philosopher), 147, 237-238, 276 Solander, Daniel (biologist), 48-49 Solitary Islands, 13, 16, 17, 325 species concept of, 143, 144, 147-149 evolution of, 51 Sperber, Dan (anthropologist), 129 statistics in ecology, 154 philosophy of, 154-155 steelwood (Sarcopteryx stipitata), 39 Stein, Gertrude (writer), 12, Sterelny, Kim (philosopher), 140 stinging tree, giant (Dendrocnide excelsa), 5, 6, 13, 18, 22, 65, 119, 247, 250, 252, 253, 263, 303, 305, 306, 308, 311 Stott’s Island, 132 subjectivity, 138-139, sublime, the, 11, 12, 13, 18, 30, 78, 79, 88, 91, 102, 119, 126, 157, 163, 189, 190, 191, 198, 232, 271, 273, 277, 282, 286, 288, 302 history of sublime views 234-239 relation to sacred, 235 traditional aesthetic analysis of, 258264 Sugars, R.S. (photographer), 186 surfing, body, 243-244,

332

Susan Island, 132, Swain, E.H.F. (District Forester on Bellinger), 19, 27, 73 Swainson, William (botanist), 43 tamarind, native (Diploglottis australis), 39, 45, 67, 97, 100 Tanban, 12, 18, teatree (Leptospermum spp.), 50, 72, 200, teatree (Melaleuca alternifolia) oil, 121 television, representation of nature in, 192196, Tench, Watkin (colonial diarist), 261 Terra nullius, 15, 25, 26, 237, 264, 281, 282 The Dome, 13, Theocritus (poet), 18, 37 thornbills, 35, 113, 161, 1652 brown, 109, 111, 265 striated, 109 thrush grey (shrike), 35, 99, 111, 113, 248 russet ground, 234, 248 tick, paralysis (shellback), 13, 18, 88, 93, 213, 263, 265, 305, 306 Timms, Peter (art critic), 99, 190 Toyne, Philip (environmental lobbyist), 305 tree frog bleating, 112 dwarf green, 112 Tyler’s, 106 triboluminescence, 36 Tucker’s Knob, 13, 40 tuckeroo (Cupaniopsis anacardioides), 17, 39, 246 turkey, brush, 71, 93, 99, 100, 248, 312 Turner, Frederick (philosopher), 269 turpentine, 33, 34, 38 scrub, 67, 99 Tweed River, 132 Ulitarra (see Birigundah), 11, 24 unconscious, social, 124 Urunga, 17, 250, 302 Valla Mountain (see Nunguu Mirral) Virgil, 18, 30, 37, 265 vision, fascination with, 239 wallaby, swamp, 16, 59, 70, 71, 72, 76, 82, 86, 87, 90, 91, 92, 93, 94, 96-98, 99, 100, 101, 102, 104, 111, 120, 150, 248, 262, 279, 305, 307, 310, 311, 312 Wallace, Alfred Russell, 42 Wandering Jew, 6, 7, 306, 305, 308, 312 name and ecology of, 295-296 Water Gum Creek, 14

water gums, giant (Syzgium francisii), 5 Watkins, Carleton (photographer), 186 wattle (Acacia spp.) 39, 42, 48, 50, 52, 61, 66, 74, 77, 201, 214 black (blue skin, A. irrorata), 39 blackwood (Acacia melanoxylon), 15, 39, 61, 64, 67, 85, 91, 97 Maiden’s (A. maidenii), 39, 42, 45, 102 Wauchope, 4 weeds, 3, 18, 20, 21, 23, 25, 37, 56, 62, 63, 68, 69, 70, 77, 80, 81, 147, 150, 163, 180, 182, 190, 200, 201, 207, 208, 220, 227, 245, 246, 267, 279, 280 cultural standards for, 213-219 degradation of rainforest by, 6-9 in forest regrowth, 73-76 mythologies of, 293-294 portrait of (lantana), 85-98, 101, 119 in remnant rainforest, 132-134 unconscious culture of, 121, 123 removal from rainforest, 293-313 Weir, Peter (filmmaker), 191 whipbird, eastern, 90, 113 whistler, golden, 35, 113 Whitman, Walt (poet), 18 Wilbur, Richard (poet), 104 wilderness, 15, 80, 131, 161, 187, 200, 204, 237, 259, 263, 274, 284 as cultural form, 117, 230-234, 280281 experience, 263 as normative in technocratic society, 281 photography, 190 Williams, Fred (painter), 77, 78, 79, 264 Williams, George (evolutionary biologist), 131 Williams, Raymond (cultural theorist), 238-239 willow (Salix spp.), 5, 6, 34, 122, 123 Wingham, 4, 296, Brush, 132, 309 Wittgenstein, Ludwig (philosopher), 141, 250 Wondurrigah, 13 Wordsworth, William (poet), 12, 258 Wright, Judith (poet), 104, 265 Yarrahapinni, 26 Yibarbuk, Dean (fire manager), 220

333

Related Documents

Nature Culture
April 2020 11
Nature
November 2019 60
Nature
May 2020 31
Nature
November 2019 51

More Documents from ""

Nature Culture
April 2020 11
Australian Stories
April 2020 6
Nothing Better To Do
May 2020 11
Media Events
May 2020 10