Bloor, Latour And The Field

  • May 2020
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Bloor, Latour And The Field as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 2,315
  • Pages: 6
Pergamon www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci., Vol. 31, No. 3, pp. 503–508, 2000  2000 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved. Printed in Great Britain 0039-3681/00 $ - see front matter

Discussion Bloor, Latour, and the Field Eve Seguin* The debate between Bloor and Latour is based on a fundamental misunderstanding due to too narrow a view of what Bloor calls ‘the field’. The boundaries of this ‘field’ are not defined by the sociological analysis of the content of science: SSK and Latour do not share the same object of study. Latour’s approach marks a shift from the social determinants of scientific knowledge to the ontological labour performed by scientific activity. The research on the science/society interface has generated two approaches. Some works tackle the social factors which determine science. Their object is society in science. Other works address the social role of science. Their object of study is science in society. The difference in the way SSK and Latour look at science is an incarnation of this division. A re-conceptualization of ‘the field’ based on the acknowledgement of these two objects is perhaps the only way to allow for a diversity of approaches in the study of the science/society interface.  2000 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.

In ‘Anti-Latour’, Bloor remarks that the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) and Latour’s approach are mistakenly put together under the label ‘social constructivism’ (Bloor, 1999a; p. 81). Bloor’s comment is undoubtedly right and provides an excellent starting point to reconsider his criticism of Latour, and to understand what is at stake in their debate. My contention is that in spite of the massive attack he mounts on Latour’s work, Bloor underestimates the distance between Edinburgh and Paris. The debate is not based on a disagreement but on a fundamental misunderstanding. This is due to too narrow a view of what Bloor simply calls ‘the field’ (Bloor, 1999b; p. 132), as if this phrase was not in need of clarification. The resistance of SSK supporters to Latour’s approach has often been explained in terms of the conservatism of the new orthodoxy (Friedman, 1998; Woolgar, 1992). In what follows I try to shed new light on the debate by offering an alternative reading of Latour’s work. This will allow me to propose a more comprehensive * Department of History, University of Aberdeen, U.K. (e-mail: [email protected]) Received 15 November 1999; in revised form 18 February 2000.

PII: S0039-3681(00)00020-0 503

504

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

mapping of the vast domain of research that tackles the links between science and society. When Latour states ‘I think David is right in everything he says’ (Latour, 1999a; p. 113), we should not see any irony in his remark. Indeed, Bloor’s difficulty in accepting Latour’s work comes from his addressing it from the viewpoint of SSK. Change the viewpoint and the work under attack changes accordingly. Bloor’s thesis is that ‘the two approaches are deeply opposed’ (Bloor, 1999a; p. 81). Of course, Latour agrees. Unfortunately, it seems to me that to read the debate in such simple terms is to miss something crucial. Bloor’s statement suggests that the two approaches are intended to explain the same phenomenon in divergent ways. But what phenomenon exactly? No doubt that for Bloor, Latour seeks to develop an alternative to SSK for studying science as knowledge: ‘His aim is to produce some manner of non-sociological, non-reductionist analysis of knowledge...’(Bloor, 1999a; p. 86). ‘Knowledge’ is a collectively held belief system. For exponents of SSK all belief systems are equal in the sense that their credibility is explainable by social factors (Barnes and Bloor, 1982; Bloor, 1976). Here, we touch the greatest achievement of SSK—that is, the secularization of scientific knowledge. But for Latour the analysis of science in terms of belief has limited value because it ignores the distinctive character of science as practice. Exponents of SSK do not address this question for the excellent reason that their goal is to eliminate the gap that epistemology builds between science and ‘irrational’ beliefs. For Latour the interesting aspect is that science differs profoundly from other cosmologies. The difference between science and other forms of ‘knowledge’ lies in the activity of the laboratory. This is perhaps the most important component of his work. His description of lactic acid, for instance, beautifully captures the importance he gives to the scientific laboratory: ‘...the acid is not presented as a substance durable in time and defined by its attributes but rather by a collection of verbs referring to laboratory gestures. Acid is ultimately a procedure, a recipe, and is coextensive with a course of action.’ (Latour, 1996; p. 83). This means that science is not to be regarded as a collection of beliefs. It is a set of procedures that activate a reality. Latour concludes his account of Pasteur’s discovery of lactic acid yeast by stressing the role of science in the production of realities: ‘...he [Pasteur] has given a phenomenon its chance’ (Latour, 1996; p. 87). This clearly shows that we are no longer in the study of science as knowledge. Latour’s approach marks a shift from the social determinants of scientific knowledge to the ontological labour performed by scientific activity. As we will see below, such activity is political through and through, and Latour has now accomplished the task of giving science a political philosophy. Here, the point that must be stressed is that the boundaries of what Bloor calls ‘the field’ are not defined by the sociological analysis of the content of science: SSK and Latour do not share the same object of study. Insofar as SSK seeks to shed light on the social interests that condition the formation of scientific knowledge, its object can be called

Bloor, Latour, and the Field

505

‘society in science’. In contrast, Latour is trying to theorize the social function exerted by science. His object is therefore ‘science in society’. As he and Callon put it: ‘We have never been interested in giving a social explanation of anything, but we want to explain society...’ (Callon and Latour, 1992; p. 348). The linking of science to society has a long history. Already Luka´cs was claiming that science is a bourgeois enterprise (Freimiller, 1998). Unfortunately, it often remains unnoticed that the study of the society/science interface has generated two broad approaches which correspond to the objects mentioned above. The difference in the ways that SSK and Latour look at science is an incarnation of this division. Yet, they are seen as forming one field because they share a micro-approach, marked in a preference for detailed case-studies. As we will now see, this feature undoubtedly differentiates them from the other perspectives that exist for the study of the link between science and society. On the one hand, we find the works that tackle the upstream of science. They scrutinize the conditions of possibility of the scientific enterprise: its method, research priorities, funding, bureaucratic organization, ideological assumptions, personnel training, disciplinary divisions, and so on. These critical studies come from various quarters: Marxism, feminism, radicalism, environmentalism. They give rise to the object I have above called ‘society in science’. The sociology of scientific knowledge belongs here. However, as already mentioned, SSK introduces a novelty in the study of the determinants of science, that is, a focus on the most esoteric aspects of science, along with careful analysis of the micro-mechanisms that account for the content of scientific knowledge. The originality of this ‘micro turn’ cannot be overemphasized. On the other hand, there exists a corpus of works that address the role of science in society: its downstream. Here the point of departure of the analysis is science itself and the aim is to assess its impact on society. The above critical perspectives are present here too, and form the social interests thesis. They derive the social role of science from its conditions of possibility. Being a phallocratic, capitalist and productivist undertaking, the only function science can exert is to reproduce the dominant social interests and the existing order. Thus, in this view science is not granted any original activity, nor is it seen to make any accomplishment of its own. It merely reflects the pre-existing social interests that condition it. The works that make up the social interests thesis combine the two objects I am distinguishing here. For instance, the feminist analysis of the reproductive technologies shows that reproductive biology feeds on the subordination of women and, via reproductive technologies, reinforces it. This could explain why the distinction between upstream and downstream studies is often not perceived. This distinction becomes evident when the technocracy thesis is taken into account: this is the polar opposite of the social interests thesis. Studies that call upon the notion of technocracy are diverse but can be classified into two sets. In its limited version the thesis holds that experts within the state use scientific tech-

506

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

niques in decision-making to reduce the uncertainty inherent in political decisions. Science is thus transforming liberal democracy into a new, technocratic, political regime. In the generalized version of the thesis, the complexity of contemporary society means that every field of social activity is ruled by technoscientific principles mastered by a new expert dominant group. Here science is granted the power to turn industrial society into a new, post-industrial, technocratic society. Analyses in terms of technocracy have their shortcomings. Their failure to pay attention to the concrete business of science means that the latter appears as an alien enterprise. Also, they tend to draw a rather gloomy picture of the impact of science on modern society. That being said, they are very important because unlike the social interests thesis, they demonstrate the possibility of ascribing to science an original contribution to, and effect on, society. Crucially, Latour adopts a microapproach to science, but shares with the technocracy thesis a commitment to accounting for the centrality of science in contemporary society. He has now devised a theory of the role of science which takes the form of a political philosophy treatise (Latour, 1999b). Latour argues that at present our public life is organized in a bicameral system that seriously impoverishes the quality of our democracy. One chamber deals with values and society, and its political character is acknowledged: it is called politics. The other chamber is concerned with facts and nature, and is officially apolitical: it is called science. This organization is defective because the sociology of science has shown that science is in fact entirely political. With their laboratories, machines and instruments scientists perfom a collecting work, endlessly mobilizing and adding new, non-human entities to the collective. This associative labour is the antithesis of the unified nature of modernity whose function is, in the guise of transcendence, to limit and constrain politics. Thus, science is the activity whereby the natural order is decided by scientists behind closed doors. It is therefore the last remain of an absolutist regime in which public debate and the participation of the people are not allowed. For Latour, this anti-democratic organization calls for a republican transformation in which the common world will be democratically established. This political theory clears up any doubt regarding Latour’s aims. His study of science is a means of understanding society as a whole. Despite scrutinizing scientific articles or laboratories as SSK practitioners do, Latour has crossed the border that divides the vast domain of research on the science/society interface. Indeed, the beauty of his work lies in the combination of close-up observation of scientific practice with a theoretical concern in the organization of society. Crucially, his approach opens up new possibilities for studying the political function of science. In particular, the functioning of scientific discourse and the impact of its circulation in the public sphere can now be analyzed (Seguin 1996, 2001). Failure to acknowledge the existence of two different objects in the study of the links between society and science can only prevent new explorations. ‘The field’

Bloor, Latour, and the Field

Fig. 1.

507

Studies of the science/society interface.

should give way to a conceptualization along the lines suggested in Fig. 1. This is perhaps the only way to do justice to this rich area of research and to allow for a diversity of approaches. References Barnes, B. and Bloor, D. (1982) ‘Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge’, in M. Hollis and S. Lukes (eds), Rationality and Relativism (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 21–47. Bloor, D. (1976) Knowledge and Social Imagery (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Bloor, D. (1999a) ‘Anti-Latour’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30A(1), 81–112. Bloor, D. (1999b) ‘Reply to Bruno Latour’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30A(1), 131–136. Callon, M. and Latour, B. (1992) ‘Don’t Throw the Baby Out with the Bath School! A Reply to Collins and Yearley’, in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press), pp. 343–368. Freimiller, J. (1998) ‘Unnatural Discourse’, Social Theory and Practice 24(2), 283–299. Friedman, M. (1998) ‘On the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge and Its Philosophical Agenda’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29A(2), 239–271. Latour, B. (1996) ‘Do Scientific Objects Have a History? Pasteur and Whitehead in a Bath of Lactic Acid’, Common Knowledge 5, 76–91.

508

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

Latour, B. (1999a) ‘For David Bloor … and Beyond: A Reply to David Bloor’s ‘Anti Latour’’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30A(1), 113–129. Latour, B. (1999b) Politiques de la nature. Comment faire entrer les sciences en de´mocratie (Paris: La De´couverte). Seguin, E. (1996) ‘L’analyse politique de la science: technocratie vs discours scientifique’, Politix 36, 181–193. Seguin, E. (2001) ‘Narration and Legitimation. The Case of In Vitro Fertilisation’, Discourse & Society 12(3), forthcoming. Woolgar, S. (1992) ‘Some Remarks about Positionism: A Reply to Collins and Yearley’, in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press), pp. 327–342.

Related Documents