Natural_passions_reason_and_religious_e.pdf

  • Uploaded by: Katerina Sergidou
  • 0
  • 0
  • October 2019
  • PDF

This document was uploaded by user and they confirmed that they have the permission to share it. If you are author or own the copyright of this book, please report to us by using this DMCA report form. Report DMCA


Overview

Download & View Natural_passions_reason_and_religious_e.pdf as PDF for free.

More details

  • Words: 10,123
  • Pages: 29
Text version of an article published in Passion and Passivity: Claremont Studies in Religion, ed. I. Dalferth and M. Rodgers, Mohr Siebeck, 2011, pp. 49-68. Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Natural Passions, Reason and Religious Emotion in Hobbes and Spinoza I. Some Stage-Setting Passions were a hot topic in the seventeenth century. And part of what made them hot was the hope of explaining them in fully naturalistic terms. Most important seventeenth century philosophers1 adopted a naturalist stance towards the passions that committed them to accounting for the passions in ways continuous with the best available natural sciences. Above all, they treated them as amenable to the explanatory tools and approaches, particularly causes, they recognized as applicable in the new “mechanical” philosophy. This approach was furthered by Descartes’s pivotal decision to count the passions as perceptions (rather than, e.g., appetitions). Although not all followed Descartes’s example, subsequent early modern philosophers tended to understand the passions as passive, receptive states2 that were either identical with, or based in bodily states and events. As such body-based states, the passions are both caused and shaped in ways susceptible to mechanical explanation. This naturalist approach may go some way toward explaining why many of the same philosophers entertained great suspicions towards supposedly special religious affects, particularly those that claimed their source in some divine inspiration, often derided as “enthusiasm”.3 This suspicion was furthered by the demand to submit any resulting knowledge-claims to the tribunal of natural reason.                                                                                                                 1

I particularly have in mind Descartes, Hobbes, Malebranche and Spinoza. There are exceptions, such as the Cambridge Platonists and perhaps Pascal. 2 This is one of the central themes of S. James, Passion and Action: the Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997). 3 For obvious historical reasons, mid-seventeenth-century British philosophers were particularly sensitive to the dangers of “enthusiasm”, with philosophers from Hobbes to the Cambridge Platonist Henry More rating it a form of mental illness, or plain hypocrisy. See R. Shaver, “Enthusiasm”, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy On-Line, ed. E. Craig (London: Routledge Publishing, 1998), http://www.rep.routledge.com.login.ezproxy.library.ualberta.ca/article/DB027 (accessed December 16, 2008).

 

1  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

The emphasis on rational explicability goes hand in hand with the general naturalism, whether because naturalism itself was taken to meet the demands of natural reason or because both our rational and our affective dispositions were taken to belong to the dominion of nature and thus must be as intelligible as nature itself. The naturalist conception of passions as bodily-based receptive states was exploited by both Descartes and Malebranche, who nonetheless maintained roughly functionalist accounts,4 in which the passions serve various goods of the embodied human. In this respect, Hobbes and Spinoza were even more uncompromisingly naturalistic, refusing to countenance so much as a whisper of final causes and working relentlessly to produce a thoroughly forward-driving picture of causation. One result is the centrality of the notion of “endeavor”, “striving”, or in the Latin, conatus, which both use to individuate “singular things” within the world. Conatus is the basis of all animal motion, and in Spinoza’s hands, the basis for all motion in general, whereas “affects”5 of various sorts are the fuel of volitional motion. For both Hobbes and Spinoza, such passions and affects determine what counts as “good” and evil”, and so even fully voluntary actions are more pushed by the affects than pulled by antecedent conceptions

                                                                                                                4

In Malebranche’s case, the functionalist approach is filtered through his Augustinian insistence on the pervasive corrupting effects of original sin; the Fall perverted our passionate dispositions from their functional course to hold us in their dysfunctional thrall. Nonetheless, Malebranche shares the view with Descartes that the passions and our other dispositions and faculties serve our good as embodied creatures. For an account of how Descartes’s functionalism could be reconciled with the rejection of final causation in physics, see A. Schmitter, “How to Engineer a Human Being: Passions and Functional Explanation in Descartes”, in A Companion to Descartes, ed. J. Broughton and J. Carriero (NY: Blackwell, 2007), esp. 427-8. For discussion of the relation between Malebranche’s neo-Augustinian commitments and his conception of the function of the passions, see P. Hoffman, “Three Dualist Theories of the Passions”, Philosophical Topics 19 (1991): 153-200, and S. Greenberg, “Malebranche on the Passions: Biology, Morality and the Fall”, British Journal for the History of Philosophy (forthcoming). 5 Because of Spinoza’s important distinction between passion and affect (to be explained further below), I will use “affect” as the generic term, even though Hobbes makes no such distinction and does not use the term.

 

2  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

of the good. The passions and affects, then, are where large-scale physical explanation meets the account of our behavior. It is, I maintain, the explanatory constraints imposed by the commitment to austere naturalism that motivate Hobbes and Spinoza to locate the affects within their overall psychic economy as they do. These commitments also play a role in their approach to the old canard opposing reason to emotion, for on the view they share, operations of both are driven by a blind conative striving that defies description in functionalist terms. What is true of the affects in general should also hold in particular cases, and so both adopt a similarly naturalist attitude towards religious emotions. Yet, curiously enough, they end up with opposing evaluations of the rationality, indeed the very possibility, of distinctively religious affects directed toward God: Hobbes has no truck with them, insisting that the only appropriate passions to feel for God are the same in kind (if not in degree) as those directed at the Sovereign of one’s Commonwealth. They follow in both cases from the recognition of power: “From internal honour, consisting in the opinion of power and goodness, arise three passions: love (which hath reference to goodness) and hope, and fear (that relate to power) [ . . . ]”.6 In contrast, Spinoza devotes the closing sections of the Ethics to a discussion of how the third kind of knowledge (a “scientia intuitiva”) simultaneously produces an “intellectual love of God” (“amor Dei intellectualis”), “blessedness” (“beatitudo”) and supreme contentment (“summa acquiscentia”), affects that are sui generis in Spinoza’s taxonomy.7 How could                                                                                                                 6

T. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. E. Curley (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 1994), 31.9: 238. All subsequent references will appear in the text, citing this edition as L, followed by chapter, paragraph and page. 7 See Spinoza’s Ethics VP32c, VP33s, VP27, respectively. All translations used subsequently will come from B. Spinoza, Collected Works of Spinoza, Vol. 1, trans. E. Curley (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985); they will be cited in the text as E, followed by Part, and when appropriate, component and sub-component, or section; in this scheme, “P” stands for proposition, “D” stands for definition, “d” for

 

3  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

a shared naturalism produce such contrasting conclusions about the very possibility of theocentric affects? To appreciate this puzzle, we should recognize that Spinoza does not merely resemble Hobbes: he owes Hobbes an enormous intellectual debt. That debt stands despite a sharp split between Spinoza’s “parallelism” about thinking and extension8 and Hobbes’s reductionist materialism. Such ontological differences aside, Spinoza borrows many tenets of his political philosophy from Hobbes.9 And what allows him to do so is the shared methodological and explanatory approach exacted by their naturalist commitments, particularly for their understanding of human rationality and its relation to the passions. Within this context of common commitments and approaches, seemingly slight differences in their conceptions of the relation between whole and part, and between activity and passivity produce opposing views on the possibility of individual rationality. I will argue that whether one can aspire to a robust and developed rationality as an individual, and not simply as a member of a tightly organized collectivity, is the difference that makes a difference for their divergent attitudes towards religious affects. II. Passions contra Reason Let us examine one bit of the terrain shared between Hobbes and Spinoza: each philosopher opposes passion to “reason,” on the grounds that the passions interfere with                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           demonstration, “s” for scholium, “Pref” for Preface, “Def.Aff” for Definition of the Affects, and “App.” for Appendix. Citations to Spinoza’s Theological-Political Treatise will refer to B. Spinoza, TheologicalPolitical Treatise, trans. R.H.M. Elwes (New York: Dover Publications, 1951), cited in the text as TPT, followed by page. 8 I describe Spinoza’s parallelism so, rather than glossing it as a matter of the mind-body relation, because its basic tenet is that “the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things” (E IIP7: 451). That claim derives from the fundamental identity of the infinite attributes of thinking and extension (and all other such attributes) as aspects of the single substance. Although parallelism also obtains between the minds and bodies of singular persons, establishing it requires several additional premises about the nature of finite modes. 9 This is widely recognized; see, e.g., H. Gilden, “Spinoza and the Political Problem,” in Spinoza: a Collection of Critical Essays, ed. M. Grene (NY: Doubleday Books, 1973), 377.

 

4  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

and degrade our reasoning processes. Hobbes expresses the view colorfully: “the understanding is by the flame of the passions, never enlightened, but dazzled (L 19.5: 12010). But this is an odd position to find in either philosopher. Hobbes, for instance, is a thoroughgoing materialist, who takes passions to be identical with specific motions in matter. As the title of Chapter VI of Leviathan puts it, they are “the Interiour Beginnings of Voluntary Motions [ . . . ]” (L 6: 27).11 Together with the imagination, the passions arise at the point where the general motions that circulate throughout the world and in animal bodies are channeled into voluntary animal motion; they anchor the interior chain of motions that produce appetites and aversions, and eventually actions. For this reason, they can largely be identified with the will. But thought itself is simply motion, more specifically, animal motion. Reasoning is a form of thought, and understood as “deliberation”, it issues volitions. As such, acts of reasoning are driven by passions, just as all animal motions are; indeed, they may even be identified with passions. So ultimately, it’s passions all the way down. For these reasons, Hobbes maintains an analogy between the force and degree of passion and reason. The motion of “greater” passions correlates with greater ambition and greater intelligence. Likewise, a “defect” of passion produces “dulnesse”. “Wit” in general is driven by desires, which all reduce to “desire of power” (L 8.13-15: 40-1). Moreover, our desires not only spur our thinking into action, they hold it on course:

                                                                                                                10

See also L. 26.21: 180; 27.4: 191; 27.18: 195, inter alia. Hobbes sometimes gives a slightly more restrictive sense to the passions, e.g., Elements of Law distinguishes between the motions in the brain that constitute sense and imagination and the continuation of those motions to the heart that are passions proper. For further discussion of these and related issues, see A. Schmitter, “Hobbes on the Emotions,” in “Seventeenth and Eighteenth Century Theories of Emotions,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 edition), ed. E. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/emotions-17th18th/. 11

 

5  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

For the thoughts are to the desires as scouts and spies, to range abroad and find the way to the things desired; all steadiness of the mind’s motion, and all quickness of the same, proceeding from thence [ . . . ] (L 8.16: 41). Thinking appears as a product of passionate drives and an expression of our basic “endeavour”. So what sense is there in maintaining that the passions are opposed to reason? Even if we could make sense of this opposition, Hobbes seems to give us no way to act on it, for a reason isolated from passion would seem utterly inert. Time and time again, he insists that passions can only be restrained by other passions (see, e.g., L. 14.31: 87-88). This may simply reflect their status as motions, for within Hobbes’s general mechanistic physics, only motions can affect other motions.12 Perhaps “reason” could be identified with some distinct set of motions other than those constituting the passions, but if so, Hobbes never mentions what those motions might be, or how they could arise independently of the imagination-passion-volition-action cycle. We seem faced with a dilemma: either reason cannot be opposed to the passions in toto, or it must be utterly ineffectual. Spinoza also supposes our thinking needs a moving force, although he locates it in what he calls the “affects”. “Desire” (“cupiditas”13), in particular, is identified with the conatus, or striving, that constitutes all our action, including our mental action.14 Because                                                                                                                 12

See, e.g., T. Hobbes, Elements of Law: Human Nature and de Corpore Politico with Three Lives (with selections from de Corpore, chapters I, VI and XXV), ed. J.C.A. Gaskin (Oxford: Oxford University Press,1994), chapter 9.7. 13 Spinoza notably does not use the term libido for the general type, but restricts it to a species of desire (translated by Curley as “lust”, e.g., E III P56d: 527). But Latin Stoics often used libido as one of the four basic perturbatione. This may indicate Spinoza’s rather different evaluation of desire as a whole, despite his close affiliations with various stripes of stoicism. 14 See E IIIP9s: 500. Although Spinoza identifies “appetite” (“appetitus”) with the striving (“conatus”), holding that “desire can be defined as appetite together with consciousness of the appetite”, human beings will typically have some idea of the appetite clear and distinct enough to count as conscious. So Spinoza insists that “between appetite and desire there is no difference”, and in the “Definitions of the Affects” that

 

6  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Spinoza uses the notion of “passion” more restrictively than does Hobbes, he does not make our reasoning passion-driven. Nonetheless, he finds other grounds for insisting that the passions are an inescapable part of the human condition. Because we are finite creatures, we are always subject to being affected by external things, that is, those things lying outside our boundaries as “singular things”, but still within the conditioned causal chain of finite modes. And so, “we are acted on, insofar as we are a part of nature” (E IVP2: 548). Moreover, “the force by which a man perseveres in existing is limited, and infinitely surpassed by the power of external causes” (E IVP3: 548). That means that we are always subject to passions, for passions constitute our reactions to what impinges on us for better or worse: indeed, “the force and growth of any passion, and its perseverance in existing, are not defined by the power by which we strive to persevere in existing, but by the power of an external cause compared with our own” (E IVP5: 549). This point follows directly from Spinoza’s official definitions of passions and affects. Spinoza makes passions a species of affects. More precisely, he declares: an affect that is called a Passion [“pathema”] of the mind is a confused idea by which the mind affirms of its Body, or some part of it, a greater or lesser power of existing [“existendi vis”] than before, which, when it is given determines the Mind to think of this rather than that (E III Gen.Def.Aff.: 542). Affects in general are “affections of the Body by which the Body’s power of acting is increased or diminished, aided or restrained, and at the same time, the ideas of these

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                          concludes Part III, reiterates that “I really recognize no difference between human appetite and Desire” (E III Def.Aff: 531).

 

7  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

affections” (E IIID3: 493). The mind itself is just the idea(s) of the body.15 As such, it is largely constituted by its affects, since any idea that involves a change in conatus counts as an affect. Now, Spinoza holds that ideas that require external causes – those for which we are not “adequate”, or full and sufficient causes – count as confused, mutilated, and “inadequate”. The upshot is that passions are simply passive affects. Since we are always subject to being acted upon (and acted upon by forces greater than we are), we will always be subject to passions, and the conceptual confusions they involve. Spinoza does not leave us with quite the same conundrum as we found with Hobbes in contrasting reason to the passions. But the outlook for achieving rationality with such forces lined up in opposition does not look bright. Moreover, Spinoza – like Hobbes – remains committed to the view that only an affect can combat another affect: “an affect cannot be restrained or taken away except by an affect opposite to, and stronger than, the affect to be restrained” (E IVP7: 550). Here again, Spinoza’s distinction between “passion” and “affect” moderates his position greatly, for he can allow that a particular (passive) passion may be restrained by a particular (active) affect, although we have no hope of actively overcoming our susceptibility to passions in toto. Still, while he maintains that only affective techniques for overcoming the “bondage” of the passions are effective, the opposition between reason and passion strikes an odd note: what role could be left to reason? At best, it would seem epiphenomenal, since “no affect can be restrained by the true knowledge of good and evil insofar as it is true, but only insofar as it is considered as an affect” (E IVP14: 553). III. Passion-Driven Conflict                                                                                                                 15

See E IIIP13: 502: “the object of the idea constituting the human Mind is the Body [ . . . ] and nothing else”.

 

8  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

In short, the general position embraced by both philosophers looks like a recipe for despair. On the one hand, our passions are painted as exuberantly and violently irrational; on the other, our very ability to reason depends on the driving force of affect. And reason itself seems to have no power to constrain our emotions, no matter how irrational they may be. As we will see, all is not lost, but it is important to realize how dangerous the effects of unbridled passions appear to both Hobbes and Spinoza. For they identify the causes of social conflict in general in the clash of individuals’ passions. Hobbes famously sees the condition of war as “necessarily consequent [. . . ] to the natural passions of men” (L 17.1: 106), particularly to glory. That they sow discord is one of the main reasons for counting such passions as irrational. Reason is the same for all, and ipso facto cannot generate conflict: “For all men by nature reason alike, and well, when they have good principles” (L 5.16: 25). What is true of social conflict in general is true of religious conflict: it is driven by the passions of individuals, operating as a force of unreason. Indeed, some religious conflict simply enacts the opposition pitting reason against passion. The sorts of religious conflicts whose causes and nature most concern Hobbes are intra-societal religious disagreements between established, conformist religion and dissenters, which he understands as a conflict between established, rational forces and irrational schismatics. The connection between established religion and reason is so strong that Hobbes makes it a test for the truth of prophecy. For there can be “nothing contrary to” reason in God’s word (L 32.2: 246), even if some aspects of God’s will may not be accessible to our unassisted natural reason without pronouncements or positive laws enunciated by special messengers. Still, we have only our natural reason to determine whom to trust. Reason

 

9  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

proposes two individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for trusting those claims that reason cannot discover itself: the performance of miracles (which gives evidence of power) and “the not teaching any other religion than that which is already established” (L 32.7: 248). In contrast, religious conflict often arises from innovation, motivated by the excessive and superstitious “opinion of inspiration, called “commonly “private spirit, [ . . . by which a person styles himself] as being in the special grace of God Almighty, who hath revealed the same to them supernaturally, by his Spirit” (L 8.22: 42). Such claims to “inspiration” or “enthusiasm” are rationally insupportable; they also can spur social upheaval. Consider the following indictment: [Although] the effect of folly in them that are possessed of an opinion of being inspired be not visible always in one man by any very extravagant action that proceedeth from such passion, yet when many of them conspire together, the rage of the whole multitude is visible enough (L 8.21: 42). The passage is somewhat opaque, but Hobbes clearly goes on to identify this “folly” as “private spirit”. It’s notable that he is willing to consider it “private”, even though it may be widespread through a multitude, and even though its appearance may be symptomatic of large-scale social distress, such that the “singular passions [of a few] are parts of the seditious roaring of a troubled nation”. Hobbes seems to evaluate the passions as “singular” and the roaring as “seditious” because they depart from what is broadly accepted and established in and by a commonwealth. They do not issue from the unified whole, but from disparate individuals. And since “to have stronger and more vehement passions for anything than is ordinarily seen in others is what men call MADNESS (L 8.16: 41), they constitute a madness on the part of individuals, of which “that very arrogating such inspiration to themselves is argument enough” (L 8.21: 42). So, here we can see

 

10  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

several ways in which Hobbes attributes religious conflict to the passions: first, inspiration itself counts as a passion; second, a (false) opinion of inspiration is proof of madness, 16 which Hobbes identifies with the “passions that produce strange and unusual behavior” (L 8.20: 41-2). All of these features combine in one of the most dangerous characteristics of enthusiasts – their claim to religious exceptionalism, insofar as they hold inspiration to be a source for religious and moral imperatives that depart from what is available to natural reason and approved by the body and brains of the commonwealth. Instead, Hobbes tends to attribute such assertions of exceptionalism – whether a matter of special contact with God, or of special kinds of religious emotion – to a rationally insupportable presumption that constitutes either passion-driven madness, or mere cant. And since chicanery might be driven by excessive vainglory, or an overweening desire for some form of power, it too could count as impassioned madness. In no case does the purported enthusiast experience any passions distinctive in kind, but at most pathological excesses of run-of-the-mill passions. As might be expected, Spinoza seems less distressed by the possibility of dissidents’ inciting religious conflict. But in many respects, he is just as impatient of supposed religious exceptionalism as Hobbes, attributing it to superstition – of which he is perhaps even more impatient. Superstition is a form of unwarranted credulity and unreason. It generates “inconsistency” and variability, and this inconsistency makes it immensely difficult “to maintain in the same course men prone to every form of credulity”. That means it is a source of social unrest: “the cause of many terrible wars and revolutions” (TPT: 5). In its inconsistency, and unpredictability, Spinoza likens                                                                                                                 16

It is also often likened to intoxication of various sorts. See L 8.23-25: 42-3, as well as the discussion of the superstitious religions of the Gentiles and the insignificant speeches of “enthusiastic” madmen, L. 12.19: 68-9.

 

11  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

superstition to “mental hallucinations and emotional impulses”. Indeed, superstition in general “springs, not from reason, but solely from the more powerful phases of emotion”. And the passions it springs from are not only powerful, but particularly disruptive, for it is “engendered, preserved and fostered by fear” and “can only be maintained by hope, hatred, anger, and deceit” (TPT: 4-5). Such passions are commonplace, but nonetheless divisive, representing particularly extreme ways in which “men disagree in nature”. Spinoza explains: “men can disagree in nature insofar as they are torn by affects which are passions; and to that extent also one and the same man is changeable and inconstant” (E IVP33: 561); indeed, “insofar as men are torn by affects which are passions, they can be contrary to one another” (E IVP34: 562), which is why “hate can never be good” (E IVP45: 571). Spinoza adds: “he who is guided by Fear, and does good to avoid evil, is not guided by reason” (E IVP63: 582). Here, as elsewhere, Spinoza contrasts the socially divisive passions with reason and its effects, for “only insofar as men live according to the guidance of reason, must they always agree in nature” (E IVP35: 563). Superstition, however, incites a kind of passionate pathology, maintaining “that the good is what brings Sadness, and the evil, what brings Joy [ . . . ]” (E IV, App. XXXI: 593). It is both the result of, and an impetus to violently irrational passions. It is true that Spinoza sometimes allows that peculiar religious rites and ceremonies promote social solidarity, even though the injunctions of “ceremonial law” have no intrinsic rational value. Unlike divine law, ceremonial law is not “intimately deduced from human nature [so] that it must be esteemed innate, and, as it were, ingrained in the human mind (TPT: 69). But Spinoza does not seem to consider ceremonial law to constitute full-blown superstition: although not fully rational, neither is

 

12  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

it fully irrational. Without being based in the sound strictures of reason, “ceremonies are no aid to blessedness”. Still, they do “have reference to the temporal prosperity of the kingdom” (TPT: 70). That is, they do not perfect our health or liberty, but they promise “security of rule, prosperity and temporal happiness” (TPT: 71). They do so through “commands especially adapted to the understanding and character of [ . . . a] people” (TPT: 70) at a particular time and in a particular context – commands that address their characteristic passions to harness them for cooperative ends. Thus the extreme strictures of the Mosaic law were suited to the condition of the Jews just released from slavery, for which it was appropriate that they “should always act under external authority” (TPT: 756); for similar reasons, Christian rites “were instituted as external signs of the universal church [ . . . ] ordained for the preservation of a society” (TPT: 76). Yet important as obedience and cooperation are, Spinoza insists that neither is well-served by fear: so long as men act simply from fear they act contrary to their inclinations, taking no thought for the advantages or necessity of their actions, but simply endeavouring to escape punishment or loss of life. They must needs rejoice in any evil which befalls their ruler, [ . . . ] and must long for and bring about such evil by every means in their power (TPT: 74). In contrast to Hobbes, Spinoza insists that whatever social cooperation might be promoted through threat of punishment and the resultant fear will by highly unstable. Instead, he recommends instituting laws that work so “that people should be kept in bounds by the hope of some greatly-desired good, rather than fear” (TPT: 74). Soldiers are motivated more effectively by “a thirst for glory” than the terror of threats, and people better urged to “do their duty from devotion rather than fear” (TPT: 75). Hope, the thirst for glory and devotion are all passions, but they are passions by which other passions can  

13  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

be harmonized and calibrated with each other, so as to work towards the same ends. Ceremonies and other human laws that are socially beneficial will incite these passions. In contrast, Spinoza insists that superstition is based primarily on fear, and that is at least part of what makes it irrational. For all its usefulness, though, the warrant of ceremonial law remains wholly prudential and wholly relative to context. Thus, Christian rites are not binding on those who live alone or in countries where they are forbidden; indeed, residents of such countries are positively bound to abstain from them (TPT: 76). Nor are the Jews bound by the Mosaic law after the destruction of their kingdom, any more than they “had been before it had begun, while they were still living among other peoples [ . . . ] and were subject to no special law beyond the natural law, and also doubtless, the law of the state in which they were living [ . . . ] “ (TPT: 72). Spinoza takes enormous pains to show that scriptural injunctions to ceremonial law are part of the primary appeal of scripture to the “understanding of the masses”, “whose intellect is not capable of perceiving things clearly and distinctly” (TPT: 77, 78). But anyone who knows God’s existence by natural reason and thus “has a true plan of life” has all that is required for blessedness. Such a truly “free man” has no intrinsic need of ceremonial law. He may act in conformity with ceremonial laws to comply with his neighbors, but out of understanding the big-picture reasons, and not because he is bound by passion to obey such laws. The actions may be the same, but their basis is utterly different: “to every action to which we are determined from an affect which is a passion, we can be determined by reason, without that affect” (E IVP59: 579). A free person acts from reason, and ideally is not moved by passion at all (see E VP3: 598).

 

14  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Thus, a society of free persons would have absolutely no need of such laws and the other devices that appeal to our passions to promote social harmony. Moreover, the free person “desires [the good] for other men” (E IVP37: 564-5) – namely, that they achieve freedom and the perfection of their reason found in knowledge of the Divine law. That means that she strives to bring everybody to such a pitch of rational perfection and knowledge that they have no need to keep their passions in check with particular ceremonies and rites. Thus a society of such free individuals would have no need for ceremonial law and the like “to keep the common laws of the state” (E IVP73dem: 587). Indeed, there would be no need for any sort of partisan religion. On Spinoza’s view, Divine Law is just what is “revealed” by our natural reason; it is “natural Divine Law” and is “comprehended solely by the consideration of human nature”, so that it is “universal or common to all men” (TPT: 61, my emphasis). And living according to Divine law suffices for freedom, perfection and “blessedness;” it “does not demand the performance of ceremonies, [ . . . ] [for] the natural light of reason does not demand anything which it is itself unable to supply”. And that is because “the highest reward of the Divine law is the law itself”, or as Spinoza puts it at the very end of the Ethics, “blessedness is not the reward of virtue, but virtue itself” (E VP42: 616). Much of Spinoza’s scriptural exegesis is directed at making this point: whatever pertains to morality, salvation or, blessedness is universally applicable, and whatever seems to address a particular audience is only a device for negotiating partisan passions, so we can live “in security and [ward] off the injuries of our fellow-men, and even of beasts” (TPT: 46).17                                                                                                                 17

Even prophecies reveal no truths unavailable to natural reason, but only choose forms of address that appeal vividly to the imagination; see, e.g., TPT: 24-9.

 

15  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

IV. Private Passions and the Rational Common Measure We are now in a position to understand the important – but nonetheless superficial – contrast between passion and reason that both philosophers make. What worries them is not affectivity as such, but passions that are idiosyncratic, partisan, and thus divisive. For all their different conceptions of “passion”, both Hobbes and Spinoza think that there is something about the passion-driven actions of unorganized individuals that tends to put them at cross-purposes. Left to their own devices, such passions motivate individuals to engage in zero-sum conflicts and worse. It is this tendency towards partisan splintering that Hobbes and Spinoza deem irrational, even though the force that so tends also fuels our thinking and reasoning. For instance, we can find Hobbes declaring that when humans judge good and evil “by their own passions”, this “private measure” is “not only vain, but also pernicious to the public state” (L 46.32: 464). More generally, he contrasts the “faculty of solid reasoning [ . . . ] grounded upon the principles of truth” with “the passions and interests of men (which are different and mutable)” (L R&C.1: 489). Spinoza is even more explicit: “Men can disagree in nature insofar as they are torn by affects which are passions; and to that extent also one and the same man is changeable and inconstant” (E IVP33: 561), and so they “can be contrary to one another” (E IVP34: 562). But “men [who] live according to the guidance of reason [ . . . ] agree in nature” (E IVP35: 563). So, the opposition between reason and the passions is founded upon a contrast between what is common, shared, public – and thus stable – and what is idiosyncratic, partial, private – and thus mutable and inconstant. This, then, is the conceptual difficulty we face: Hobbes and Spinoza hold simultaneously 1. that individuals’ passions tend to drive them towards conflict; 2. that

 

16  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

all our actions (including thinking) are set into motion by affects (including passions); 3. that conflict is eo ipso irrational; yet also 4. that rational action is possible. Indeed, both philosophers remain hopeful that we can escape the worst excesses of individual passions run amok. The trick is to find some way of resisting, blocking, or redirecting the tendency of our private passions to drive us into conflict; doing so would constitute a “remedy for the passions”, bringing our private passions into accord with the shared dictates of reason. But Hobbes and Spinoza have rather different conceptions of what is involved in achieving détente between private passions and public reason. Hobbes seeks techniques for managing the passions, so that the individual actions they incite will not run at crosspurposes. Spinoza takes over much of Hobbes’s machinery for this management of the passions (E IVP37s2: 566-8). But such management is only an interim measure, for Spinoza directs us ultimately towards transforming the passions – converting them into active affects, of which we will be the adequate causes. Despite this considerable difference, both take the view that only affective “remedies” will be effective in restraining and retraining the passions. This is so even though both insist that we must find some “common measure” to restrain and coordinate the passions. Again, that common measure is identified with reason – producing the rather odd consequence that reason both contrasts with and is fueled by the passions, so that it is simultaneously true that reason restrains the passions, and that passions are only restrained by their own kind. There is no affectless force of reason on an equal, but opposite footing with the passions. Rather, the affects themselves are harnessed by other affects to produce an outcome that is in accord with reason. And the common measure of reason appears as an effect of properly aligning the affects.

 

17  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Here again it is important to recall Hobbes’s and Spinoza’s shared naturalism and restriction of explanation to efficient causation alone. It is, I maintain, their shared stance about how the passions drive individual action from behind that frames their view of the problem with the supposed “irrationality” of passion. Because the passions determine their ends unilaterally, and hence somewhat blindly, individuals can come into conflicts harmful to their well-being, even though what fuels their actions is simply the “relentless striving after power” of each individual. That relentless striving works only as an efficient cause (see E IVPref: 544-545), and so cannot be understood to possess any ends intrinsically. Since there are no ends for our basic activity, how our actions conform to rational norms cannot be understood in terms of such ends. Instead, Hobbes and Spinoza propose understanding the rationality of our actions by the degree of their calibration to the actions of others. Reason constitutes the “common measure”, the metric by which to measure calibration, and in measuring it, provides another motive to calibration. As such, affects that conform to and uphold the common measure count as “rational”. For Hobbes, passions that support the common measure are simply coordinated ones. The situation will be a bit more complicated for Spinoza, because of his distinction between passion and active affects. But even he will count the coordination of our motives, and the affects that constitute our motives, as an important effect and measure of rational action. V. Fear and Coordination One of the places where Spinoza borrows most heavily from Hobbes is in the vision of how sovereign power coordinates our passions. Instituting a sovereign power alters the conditions under which we each seek “to preserve our own life” while reckoning for our future felicity (as Hobbes puts it), or to “pursue our own advantage” (as

 

18  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Spinoza would have it) so that our strivings do not jointly result in prisoners’ dilemmalike conflicts. But although the results are the same as those that would occur if we surveyed possible outcomes and chose the actions with the biggest payoff, the technique works by bearing on our passions: altering the conditions to which we respond generates different passions, which themselves incite actions congruent with the actions of others, rather than at cross purposes. This much is shared territory between Hobbes and Spinoza, even though they recommend rather different forms for instantiating sovereign power, and even though they recommend inciting rather different passions in order to push the other passions in line. Hobbes – notoriously – relies on the passion of fear to force our other passions into line in ways that reason can approve. Not only is fear for one’s life an important and sufficient motive to enter into a commonwealth by submitting to its sovereign power, fear oils all the workings of commonwealth. Hobbes does take it that persons are duty-bound by the natural law to “perform their covenants made”. Doing so conforms to the third Law of Nature, which enjoins justice (L 15.1: 89). But he also deems “the bonds of words [ . . . ] too weak to bridle men’s ambition, avarice, anger, and other passions, without the fear of some coercive power” (L.14.18: 84). That coercive power resides in the sovereign, which wields threats both civil and ecclesiastical, to incite the fear that will push subjects into cooperative behavior. Its deployment of fear is, in fact, a condition for the very possibility of covenants (especially those that are not immediately beneficial to both parties), and hence of justice itself (L 15.4: 89). The sovereign is, in turn, itself subject to those natural laws that enjoin justice, equity, perspicuity, mercy, prudence, publicity, the promotion of education, and the like (see L. 15, 30: 89-100, 219-33). Those

 

19  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

natural laws, like all natural laws, are discoverable by reason, and thus binding on anyone who finds herself in the appropriate conditions where they apply. But even the sovereign power is moved to obey them by the passion of fear – although not fear of any human, or artificial power. There is no earthly power to which the sovereign is subject; nor can the sovereign power be subject to any law other than the natural law. Rather, the sovereign power is motivated as we all are – by fear of God, and even more, fear of the consequences for breaking natural laws that God has ordained. Those consequences are consequences inimical to preserving one’s own lives. Fear, then, inspires prudential behavior, and constitutes the most widespread motive to lawful behavior (L 27.19: 196). It’s true that Hobbes admits several variants of fear, of which some, e.g., superstition or panic terror, are unlikely to serve the proper management of the passions (L 6.36-37: 31). But the kind of fear that does most of the work for Hobbes is of another flavor, and might better be understood as respect, for it is typically directed at an object with regard to its power. That object can equally be the object of fear and love, for both being loved and feared are “arguments of power” (L 10.37-38). As such, love and fear are essentially connected to honoring and valuing (L 10.24: 52); fear, in particular, involves “confession of power” (L 31.33: 241), while to honor is to acknowledge power, consisting “in the inward thought and opinion of the power and goodness of another” (L 31.8: 237). For these reasons, the passions appropriate to direct at God are “love (which hath reference to goodness), and hope and fear (that relate to power)” (L 31.9: 238). These passions do honor to their object, and when outwardly expressed, constitute worship. They are also fitting passions in the face of the sovereign power; that is, they express the honor due to the sovereign’s power, and are part of the obedience due the

 

20  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

sovereign by virtue of its power. What’s more, power is just the grounds for God’s dominion over us: “the right of nature whereby God reigneth over men, and punisheth those that break his laws, is to be derived, not from his creating them [ . . . ], but from his irresistible power (L 31.5: 235). Hobbes makes the analogy between Divine power and political power explicit in declaring the Commonwealth, of which the Sovereign power is the “soul” (L. Intro.1: 3), “that Mortal God [ . . . ] under the Immortal God” (L 17.13: 109), the object of “civil worship” comparable to “divine worship” (L 45.13: 443). This analogy holds even though “there is nothing to be compared to God in power”, and we must grant God infinite value (L 45.12: 443). The degree of value, honor and worship we grant to God and to the sovereign may be incommensurable in degree, but are founded on passions the same in kind. As we have already seen, Spinoza does not share this evaluation of fear.18 In particular, he rejects Hobbes’s views of the effectiveness of threat. Although the sovereign may use fear of punishment to coordinate our passions and actions, the cooperation it engenders is unstable, for fear motivates not just cooperation, but actions to remove the source of the fear. And even if fear may occasionally be useful, it is not advisable for the long run: “fear is an inconstant Sadness, born of the idea of a future or past thing whose outcome we to some extent doubt, (E III Def.Aff. xiii: 534). Sadness always indicates a transition to a lesser degree of power, a weakening of conatus. But Spinoza makes an even stronger case against the appropriateness of fear of God, for he                                                                                                                 18 In part, this may be because he does not share Hobbes’s conception of fear; Spinoza typically uses the term “metus”, or more rarely, “timor” to express fear. Hobbes’s notion of fear might be captured as well by “cautio”, which some Latin Stoics permitted to a sage. At the 30th Annual Claremont Philosophy of Religion Conference, Thandeka suggested that the differences between Hobbes’s and Spinoza’s evaluations of fear reflected their Christian and Jewish backgrounds (Claremont Graduate University, Claremont, CA, USA, 13 February 2009). Her suggestion is intriguing, but the most obvious source for the difference, I think, lies in their very different commitments to neo-Stoicism.

 

21  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

argues it is impossible. Proposition 18 of Part V of the Ethics explicitly rules out feeling hate towards God, and much the same reasoning applies to fear. As a species of sadness, fear expresses a reduction in power, and as such always requires an external cause. To feel fear in the face of God would require that God be a (partial) cause of a decrease in perfection, which is metaphysically impossible: “there can be no Sadness accompanied by the idea of God” because “insofar as we consider God, we act” (E VP18: 604). In short, the very act of considering God is performatively incompatible with passions such as fear or hate. Instead, Spinoza insists that the understanding of God can only inspire love. The love that it inspires, however, is distinctive both in degree and in kind: it is amor Dei intellectualis. VI. Instantiating Reason: Now as we saw before, both Hobbes and Spinoza took reason to be the “common measure”, in which people “agree in nature”, in contrast to the idiosyncratic and divisive passions. But for all these similarities, Hobbes and Spinoza diverge in their understanding of how this common measure can be instantiated. Hobbes’s view is particularly demanding, for he requires that any robust form of reason worthy of governing our actions be instantiated in a public entity – namely, in the sovereign power – which determines what constitutes right reason, as well as enforcing it. In the absence of such an entity to provide the common measure, we may be proto-rational, and even capable of various kinds of reckoning, but we will not be, I maintain, fully rational. That the “common measure” must be set by a public entity may not be obvious at first blush because of the importance Hobbes gives to means-end calculations, of which both humans and animals are capable to some degree. Desire and passions play an

 

22  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

indispensable role in such thinking, driving the “regulated” “mental discourse” whereby we seek the means to produce some effect (L 3.4-5: 13), and for which we can exercise the virtue of prudence (see L 3.7,9: 14). But whereas such instrumental trains of thought are within the natural abilities of individuals, others require art and “proceed all from the invention of words and speech” (L 3.11: 15). This is true of everything Hobbes dubs “reason”, which he first introduces by declaring that “REASON, in this sense, is nothing but reckoning (that is, adding and subtracting) of the consequences of general names agreed upon for the marking and signifying of our thoughts” (L 5.2: 22-23). Nonetheless, Hobbes allows that such marking (rather than signifying) of consequences is something we do when “we reckon by ourselves”. So, there does seem a weak sense of reason as an instrumental “reckoning”, which is accessible to us individually, at least if we already possess language. But along with this reckoning, Hobbes interjects another, seemingly substantive kind of reason. For there must be some way for “good” and “evil” to be determined publicly, and thus provide a common measure that is shared and stable. Without such public determination of the common measure, good and evil are measured simply by private passions. In order to settle the controversies that arise when individuals rely only on the yardsticks of their own passions, Hobbes proposes that the parties must “set up for right reason the reason of some arbitrator or judge to whose sentence they will both stand” (L 5.3: 23, my emphasis). Although it is unclear how it can be reconciled with the official account of reckoning,19 “right reason” occupies an important place in Hobbes’s                                                                                                                 19

For a lively debate about the nature and number of Hobbes’s notions of reason, see, e.g., J. Deigh, "Reason and Ethics in Hobbes's Leviathan," Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (1996): 33-60; M. Murphy, "Desire and Ethics in Hobbes's Leviathan: A Response to Professor Deigh," Journal of the History of Philosophy38 (2000): 259-68; K. Hoekstra, “Hobbes on Nature, Law and Reason,” Journal of the

 

23  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

thought. For one, he invokes it in treating how reason discovers the dictates established by God (L 31.3: 235) as natural law (L 14.3: 79). Then too, he makes it central to the stability of our thinking: we must submit to the common measure of right reason, since indulging “every of [our] passions as it comes to bear sway” would be “as intolerable in the society of men as it is in play, after trump is turned, to use for trump on every occasion that suit whereof [we] have most in [our] hand” (L 5.3: 23).20 These roles merge if we take right reason to settle “good” and “evil” not only for ends, but also for means. Indeed, when Hobbes turns to how the sovereign power functions as a public reason, he stresses that it determines good and evils of all kinds. The sovereign power is established by receiving the “right of nature”, wielded by every person “in the condition of mere Nature” as “the liberty each man hath to use his own power, as he will himself for the preservation of his own nature, [ . . . ] and consequently of doing anything which, in his own judgment and reason, he shall conceive to be the aptest means thereunto” (L 14.1: 79, my emphasis). Although people can transfer their right, they cannot simply exempt themselves from the laws of nature, and so Hobbes does not suppose the state of nature to be utterly irrational. But only the first and second laws of nature get any real purchase in the absence of a sovereign power; they instruct us on the value and means for instituting a commonwealth, or if that should prove impossible, command us to defend ourselves by any means possible. Without a common measure, all judgments about such means are left to the liberty of the individual. And those judgments will be driven by                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           History of Philosophy 41 (2003): 111-20. What I am arguing here is not really captured by any of these accounts, but my argument does not depend on deciding what Hobbes’s ultimate account of reason is, as long as we acknowledge the role of the sovereign in determining “right reason” in the case of conflicts. See also B. Gert, “Hobbes on Reason,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 82 (2001): 243-57. 20 Michael Ridge, following David Gauthier, makes a similar point, although I do not agree with the rest of his account, see M. Ridge, “Hobbesian Public Reason,” Ethics 108 (1998): 544-6, but also cf., D. Gauthier, “Public Reason,” Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (1992): 24-32. For a particularly strong view of the extent of public reason, see also A. Baier, “Commodious Living” Synthese 72 (1987): 163-6.

 

24  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

passions without any requirement of consistency even with other passions of the same individual across time. But in establishing a commonwealth, individuals transfer the right of nature to the sovereign, and thereby make themselves subject to its determinations of the means apt to preserving our lives. The standard and measure then lie outside of private individuals, where it is capable of imposing normative demands on both their passions and their reckonings. And so, individuals become fully rational only by submitting to the determinations of a public reason instantiated in the sovereign power. This is why the remedy for the irrationality of the passions must come from the top down, and no moral philosophy can be a science without recognition of the role of political authority. The downfall of Aristotle and other practitioners of “darknesse from vain philosophy” lies in their failure to see that there is no internal guide – not even passions moderated by reason – that will provide an appropriate common measure in the absence of a sovereign authority (L 46.32: 464) In contrast, Spinoza allows each individual a share of the common measure of reason. On his view, not only are the norms of reason common to all humans, the object and content of reason is what is common in the nature of things: “common notions”, necessary truths, and aspects of the “eternal and infinite essence of God” that are in each thing (E II P40s2, P44, P45: 478, 480-2). This is a robust vision of reason, but one that Spinoza thinks in the grasp of every individual, for each of us “has common notions and adequate ideas of the properties of things” (E IIP40s2: 478). What makes it universally available is its universal instantiation: reason deals in the common nature of things, and what is common to all is “equally in the whole and in the part”. We are parts of nature, and so these genuinely common aspects of nature are in us as much as in anything else.

 

25  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

Moreover, “those things which are common to all, and which are equally in the part and in the whole, can only be conceived adequately” (E IIP38: 474). An adequate conception is one that is not partial or mutilated. Thus, any common notion, or idea of those things equally in the whole or in the part, can only be conceived completely and adequately. In a sense, then, the reason Spinoza proposes is every bit as commonly available as that sketched by Hobbes, perhaps even more so. But that is not because it is embodied only in a public entity; rather, it is because this reason permeates the fabric of the universe. VII. Activity and Affectivity in Spinozistic Love of God: The difference that makes a difference to this conception of a universally distributed measure of reason lies in Spinoza’s basic metaphysics of activity and passivity. Spinoza takes it that we have adequate ideas – and only adequate ideas – of common notions. We are capable of acting as adequate causes for those ideas that are adequate in us. Such ideas can exist in us whole and complete because their objects are instantiated in us. That means that we have all the resources sufficient to act as the causes of those ideas within us, which is to say, that we can be their adequate causes, and thus fully active agents. Now, Spinoza does not think that we play no causal role when we are acted on, only that we are merely a partial cause of the state we find ourselves in then. By parallelism, such passive states are both states of the body and ideas of the mind. Passive ideas, i.e., passions, are responses to what impacts us from outside, but because they involve external forces, we have only a partial idea of the causes of our perceptions. And so passions are characteristically confused. In contrast, when we reason, we have adequate ideas, for which we can be adequate causes. This entails that insofar as we reason, we are capable of experiencing only active affects, without being torn by the

 

26  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

passions. Reasoning for Spinoza thus exhibits our capacity to be genuinely active, by which we deploy what is common to us and the universe: to act is, in a sense, to act universally. This sort of genuine activity on our part is not something Hobbes thinks is possible. Hobbes’s most general account of a passion, or passive faculty, is “power limited by somewhat else” (L 31.25: 240). We are always passive in this sense, for what we are is endeavor, and a restless seeking after power. But our endeavor is always limited by other things, and so our agency, is both bounded by and dependent on what lies outside it. On Hobbes’s conception, we appear as nodes of motion that can be individuated from the rest of the matter in motion constituting the universe by our endeavor. But we are also immersed in the whole universe, and ultimately set in motion by it. The only thing that can be accounted fully active is God; for this reason, Hobbes insists that it would be a sign of dishonour to attribute a passion of any kind to God (L 31.25: 240). But Hobbes is equally adamant that we have no real conception of God: that God is the “divine and incomprehensible nature” (L 46.23: 462). In the face of God’s incomprehensibility, we can only do honor to Its infinite power, and offer signs of the passions of love, hope and fear evoked by such incomprehensible power. Here too is a stark contrast with Spinoza, who allows not only that we can be active when we reason, but points to yet another, “third kind of knowledge” that goes beyond reasoning by means of common notions. This is the scientia intuitiva, which is simultaneously an intellectual love of God, blessedness or beatitude, and supreme contentment. It is also a hard nut to crack, and I will not attempt any sort of comprehensive explanation of this baffling scientia. But a few points relevant to the

 

27  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

issues under discussion seem clear enough. First, it seems possible to arrive at this scientia intuitiva by working our way through the rationally discovered, necessary connections between the properties of things, the task of the second kind of knowledge, until we achieve a vision of the whole, the third kind of knowledge. Doing so means that we gain a maximally large set of adequate ideas, since the holistic nature of this vision, removes the partiality and mutilation of ideas received piecemeal from outside. As such, the process of working our way towards this intuitive knowledge involves converting our passions to active affects, a process that increases our power and is therefore joyful. Now, the third kind of knowledge is holistic in nature, but Spinoza thinks God just is the whole (conceived as active), so “the more we understand things in this way, the more we understand God” (E VP25d: 608). This combination of joy in coming to understand, and taking God as the object of our understanding and cause of our joy means that scientia intuitiva entails love of God (E VP15, P32: 603, 611). But this is a special and especially active affect, “the intellectual love of God”. As such, it generates the “greatest satisfaction of Mind”, in which the mind is affected with the greatest Joy as it passes to the greatest human perfection (E VP27: 609). The mind thereby also achieves “blessedness”, which “consists in Love of God [ . . . ] a Love which arises from the third kind of knowledge [ . . . ] [and] must be related to the mind insofar as it acts” (E VP42d: 616). This is a distinctive and impressive package of affects, arising out of the “remedy” of transforming our passions into active affects and thereby gaining insight into the necessary, eternal, interconnected and unified nature of Deus sive Natura. Although many of the affects that accompany this package are recognizable ones, such as joy, and love, the entire set must be considered completely distinctive in kind, only related to

 

28  

Claremont Conference  

 

Amy M. Schmitter

Natural Passions

ordinary love and joy by a kind of loose analogy. For Spinoza also tells us: “The Mind’s intellectual Love of God is the very Love of God by which God loves himself, [ . . . ] i.e., the Mind’s intellectual Love of God is part of the infinite Love by which God loves himself” (E VP36: 612). For this reason, such love cannot be a passion. Ultimately, it may not even qualify as an affect in Spinoza’s sense, for an affect signals a change in our conatus, an increase or decrease in our power of acting.21 If the mind’s love is part of God’s infinite love, then it should already be complete, perfect and immutable. So, it seems neither affect, nor passion, but once again something utterly distinctive in kind.22

                                                                                                                21 For a discussion of this point, and for the nature of the mind that can engage in such love, see D. Rutherford, “Salvation as a State of Mind: the Place of Acquiescentia in Spinoza’s Ethics,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (1999): 463-5. 22 I’d like to thank the audience at the 30th Annual Claremont Philosophy of Religion Conference (Claremont Graduate University, Claremont, CA, USA, 13-14 February 2009), for a lively and fruitful discussion; I am particularly grateful to Ingolf Dalferth and Michael Rodgers for organizing and hosting a very successful meeting.

 

29  

Claremont Conference  

 

More Documents from "Katerina Sergidou"